Skip to main content

Full text of "Logical Positivism"

See other formats


THE LIBRARY OF PHILOSOPHICAL MOVEMENTS 
GENERAL EDITOR: Paul Edwards 









Copyright © 1959 by The Free Press, a Corporation 
A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co., Inc. 


Vll richts reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced 
,r transmitted in any form or by any means. 
nechanical. including photocopying, recording, or by any 
tformation storage and retrieval system, without permission 

n writing from the Publisher. 


'The Free Press 

A Division of Macmillan Publishing Co.Mnc. 
866 Third Avenue, New York. N.Y. 10022 


Collier Macmillan Canada.Ltd. 

Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 58-6467 
Printed in the United States of America 


printing number 


5 6 7 8 9 10 



Preface 


U,0cal is fte » a » ™U 

available to the general p viewooints. Each volume will deal 

of philosophers of J'Jg two philosophical “schools” or 

with one or, m some cases, wi ’ rarely umted by 

“movements.” It is inspires political or religious 

the kind of common purpose ^ jul to consider the 

“movements.” Nevertheless, it frequen^ similarities in their aim 
work o. different iSi has beer, adopted in dc- 

SiSr ii“»r, f^-^'tSTEngiish, many o£ the 

~ Ste 

These and other amcte “«am jrtonlan™^^ 

doctrines most /®^°“pJotessor .^ver in his introduction, 

ever, for reasons explained by as 'expositions or defenses 

several pieces whmh canno gj ^ included. The scope of the 

of logical positivism have also oeen ^ would sug- 

bibliography, too, b broa^r than ho philosophy . a 

gest. No volume dealing with ot therefore thought desirable 

contemplated in this ^^^"cs and it was t^ 

to Ust L S 4lT„i po-dvism. 

of analytic philosophy the translators who gen- 

I wish to express my Ifahwoe _ 
erously contributed their labOT^t^ M helping to com- 

Irving Salt 2 inann, and Satinoff, Maxwell Grober, and 

pile the bibliography, and to L^on 

L6 Huerta-Jourda for Pf P^^n^ ^ notes which indi- 

to Professors Carnap and He p papers, 

cate their present PO^iPon on translation 

Professor Carnap was also kind enou^n 

of his own articles. p^UL Edwards 



Preface 


Editor’s Introduction 


Logical Atomism 

1. Bertrand Russell 

“Logical Atomism” 

Philosophy, Metaphysics and Meaning 

2. Moritz Schlick 

“Tme Turning Point in Philosophy” 

5. Rudolf Carnap 

“The Elimination of Metaphysics through 
Logical Analysis of Language” 

4. Moritz Schlick 

“Positivism and Realism” 

5. Carl G. Hempel 

“The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning” 


Logic and Mathematics 

6. Rudolf Carnap 

“The Old and the New Logic” 

7. Hans Hahn 

“Logic, Mathematics and 
Knowledge of Nature” 




Contents 


[viii] 


* Knowledge and T ruth 

8. Rudolf Carnap 

“Psychology in Physical Language” 165 

9. Otto Neurath 

“Protocol Sentences” 199 

10. Moritz Schlick 

“The Foundation of Knowledge” 209 

11. A. J. Ayer 

“Verification and Experience” 228 

Ethics and Sociology 

12. Moritz Schlick 

“What Is the Aim of Ethics?” 247 

13. C. L. Stevenson 

“The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms” 264 

14. Otto Neurath '' 

“Sociology and Physicalism” 2S2 


Analytical Philosophy 

15. Frank D. Ramsey 

“Philosophy” 321 

16. Gilbert Ryle 

“Philosophical Arguments” 327 

17. Friedrich Waismann 

“How I See Philosophy” 345 

Bibliography of Logical Positivism 381 


Index 


447 


LOGICAL POSITIVISM 



Editor s Introduction 


I. History of the Logical Positivist Movement 

The term ‘‘Logical Positivism” was coined some thirty years ago 
to characterize the standpoint of a group of philosophers, scientists 
and mathematicians who gave themselves the name of the Vienna 
Circle. Since that time its reference has been extended to cover j 

other forms of analytical philosophy; so that disciples of Bertrand 
Russell, G. E. Moore or Ludwig Wittgenstein at Cambridge, or 
members of the contemporary Oxford movement of linguistic analysis 
may also find themselves described as logical positivists. This wider 
usage is especially favored by those who are hostile to the whole 
modern development of philosophy as an analytical rather than a i 

speculative enquii^'. They wish to tar all their adversaries with a ; 

single brush. This is irritating to the analysts themselves who are ( 
rather more sensitive to their differences; they would prefer that the 
appellation of “logical positivist” be reserved for those wLo share the 5 
special outlook of the Vienna Circle. In compiling this anthology, I 
have not been quite so strict. I have drawn mainly on the writings • 
of the members of the Vienna Circle, or of those who stand closest 
to them, but I have also included wSeveral pieces which fall outside i 
this range. They are ail, in some sense, analytical but the scope of 
what I regard as analytical philosophy is wide. It allows for serious ; 

disagreement, not only over technical niceties, but on major points ! 

of doctrine, including the method and purpose of analysis itself. I 

The Vienna Circle came into being in the early 1920’s when , 

Moritz Schlick, around whom it centered, arrived from Kiel to be« ^ 

come professor of philosophy at the University of Vienna. On the j 

philosophical side its leading members, besides Schlick himself, j 

were Rudolf Carnap, Otto Neurath, Herbert Feigl, Friedrich Wais- t 

mann, Edgar Zilsel and Victor Kraft; on the scientific and mathe« | 

matical side, Philipp Frank, Karl Menger, Kurt G5del and Hans 
Hahn. At the beginning, it was more of a club than an organized 
movement. Finding that they had a common interest in, and a 1 


[33 



[ ] Editor's Introduction 

similar approach to, a certain set of problems, its members met 
regularly to discuss them. These meetings continued throughout the 
life of the Circle but they came to be supplemented by other activi- 
ties which transformed the club into something more nearly resem- 
bling a political party. This process began in 1929 with the publi- 
cation of a manifesto entitled “Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung, 
Der Wiener Kreis” — The Vienna Circle; Its Scientific Outlook — 
which gave a brief account of the philosophical position of the group 
and a review of the problems in the philosophy of mathematics and 
of the physical and social sciences that they were chiefly concerned 
to solve. This pamphlet, which was written by Carnap, Neurath and 
Hahn, is also of interest as showing how the Circle situated itself 
in the history of philosophy. After claiming that they were developing 
a Viennese tradition which had flowered at the end of the nineteenth 
century in the work of such men as the physicists Ernst Mach and 
Ludwig Boltzmann, and, in spite of his theological interests, the 
philosopher Franz Brentano, the authors set out a list of those 
Ihey regarded as their main precursors. As empiricists and 
positivists they named Hume, the philosophers of the enlightenment, 
Comte, Mill, Avenarius and Mach; as philosophers of science, Helm- 
holtz, Riemann, Mach, Poincare, Enriques, Duhem, Boltzmapn and 
Einstein; as pure and applied logicians, Leibniz, Peano, Frege, 
Schrdder, Russell, Whitehead and Wittgenstein; as axiomatists, Pasch, 
Peano, Vailati, Fieri and Hilbert; and as moralists and sociologists 
of a positivistic temper, Epicurus, Hume, Bentham, Mill, Comte,* 
Spencer, Feuerbach, Marx, Miiller-Lyer, Popper-Lynkeus and the 
elder Carl Menger. This list is surprisingly comprehensive, but it 
must be remembered that in most cases it is only a question of a 
special aspect of the author’s works. Thus Leibniz is included for 
his logic, not for his metaphysics; Karl Marx is included neither for 
his logic nor his metaphysics but for his scientific approach to history. 
If we exclude contemporaries from the list, those who stand closest 
to the Vienna Circle in their general outlook are Hume and Mach. It 
is indeed remarkable how much of the doctrine that is now thought 
to be especially characteristic of logical positivism was already 
stated, or at least foreshadowed, by Hume. 

Among contemporaries, Einstein, Russell, and Wittgenstein are 
singled out by the authors of the pamphlet for their kinship to the 
Vienna Circle and the extent of their influence upon it. Wittgenstein, 
indeed, stood to the Vienna Circle in a special relation. Having 
been a pupil of Russell’s at Cambridge before the first world war 
he returned to Vienna and was there when his Logisch-Philosophische 


Editor's Introduction [ 5 ] 

Abhandlung was published in 1921. This famous book, which is 
better known as Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, the title given to 
its English translation, had an enormous effect upon the positivist 
movement, both in Vienna and elsewhere. It would not be quite 
correct to say that the Vienna Circle drew its inspiration from it. 
Schlick himself, in his book on the theory of knowledge, Allgemeine 
Erkenntnislehre, of which the first edition appeared in 1918, had 
independently arrived at a similar conception of philosophy; and there 
is a hint of mysticism in the Tractatus w^hich some members of the 
Circle, especially Neurath, found disquieting; but as a whole they ac- 
cepted it, and it stood out as the most powerful and exciting, though 
not indeed the most lucid, exposition of their point of view. Wittgen- 
stein did not ofiicially adhere to the Circle but he maintained close 
personal relations at least with Schlick and Waismann whom he con- 
tinued to influence even after his departure for Cambridge in 1929. 
In Cambridge, where he taught until 1947, four years before his 
death, he exercised an almost despotic sway over his pupils, and 
though he published nothing during these years except one short 
article his influence was strongly, if in most cases indirectly, felt by 
almost all the younger generation of British philosophers. He himself 
modified the rigors of his early positivism to an extent that can be 
measured by comparing the Tractatus with his posthumously pub- 
lished Philosophical Investigations; and it is to his influence, com- 
bined with that of Moore, that one may largely attribute the pre- 
occupation of contemporar}^ British philosophers with the everyday 
uses of language, and their tendency to deal with philosophical ques- 
tions in an unsystematic, illustrative way, in contrast to the more 
rigorous would-be scientific method which was favored by the Vienna 
Circle. This is one reason w’hy they are not happy to be described 
as Logical Positivists. But I shall have more to say about these alter- 
native conceptions of analysis later on. 

It was in 1929 also that the Vienna Circle organized its first in- 
ternational congress. It was held at Prague and was followed at inter- 
vals throughout the thirties by further congresses at Konigsberg, 
Copenhagen, Prague, Paris and Cambridge. These meetings furthered 
the ambition of the Circle to develop Logical Positivism as an inter- 
national movement. It had formed an early alliance with the so-called 
Berlin school of which Hans Reichenbach, Richard von Mises, Kurt 
Grelling and at a later date Carl Hempel were the leading members. 
The congresses helped it to make contact also with Scandinavian 
philosophers such as Eino Kaila, Arne Naess, Ake Petzall, Joergen 
Joergensen, and the Uppsala school of empiricists, with the Dutch 


[ 6 ] Editor’s Introduction 

group around the philosopher Mannoury who pursued what they 
called the study of Signifies, with the Munster group of logicians 
under Heinrich Scholtz, with American sympathizers such as Nagel, 
Charles Morris and Quine, and with British analysts of various shades 
of opinion, such as Susan Stebbing, Gilbert Ryle, R. B. Braithwaite, 
John Wisdom and myself. The brilliant Cambridge philosopher F. P. 
Ramsey was marked as an adherent, but he died in 1930 at the early 
age of 26. An alliance was also formed with the very important Polish 
groups of philosophers and logicians, of whom Lucasiewicz, Les- 
nievsky, Chwistek, Kotarbinski, Ajduciewicz and Tarski were per- 
haps the most prominent. The influence of Tarski’s work, particularly 
on Carnap, was noticeably strong. 

The missionary spirit of the Circle found a further outlet in its 
publications. In 1930 it took over a journal called Annalen der 
Philosophie, renamed it Erkenninis and made it, under the editorship 
of Carnap and Reichenbach, the principal organ of the positivist 
movement. In the following years there also appeared a series of 
monographs with the collective title of Einheitswissenschaft — Unified 
Science — and a series of books, under the general editorship of 
Schlick and Philipp Frank, with the collective title of Schriften zur 
Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung. Schlick himself contributed to it a 
book on ethics, of which the first chapter is included in this volume, 
and Frank a book on the law of causality and its limitations. Among 
the other volumes to appear in it were an important book by Carnap 
on the logical syntax of language, to which I shall have occasion to 
refer again, a book on sociology by Neurath with somewhat Marxist 
leanings, and Karl Popper’s famous Logik der Forschung which was 
devoted to the philosophy of science. Popper was not in fact a mem- 
ber of the Circle and would at no time have wished to be classed as 
a positivist, but the affinities between him and tlie positivists whom 
he criticized appear more striking than the divergencies. In any case 
the members of the Circle did not in all points agree among them- 
selves. 

Though the logical positivist movement gathered strength through- 
out the thirties, the Vienna Circle itself was in the process of dissolu- 
tion. By 1933, when I attended its meetings, Carnap and Frank had 
accepted chairs at the University of Prague and the discussions were 
chiefly carried on by Schlick, Neurath, Waismann and Hahn. But 
Hahn died in 1934 and two years later Schlick was murdered, at the 
age of 54, by a demented student who shot him as he was entering 
the University. The hostile tone of the obituaries which were devoted 
to Schlick in the governmental press, implying almost that logical 


Editofs Introduction [ 7 ] 

positivists deserved to be murdered by their pupils, foreshadowed 
the troubles which were soon to fall upon the Circle, Except for 
Neurath, who had participated in the revolutionary Spaitacist Gov- 
emment in Munich at the end of the first world war, its members had 
not been conspicuously active in politics, but their critical and 
scientific temper made them suspect to the right-wing clerical govern- 
ments of Dolfuss and Schuschnigg and still more so to the Nazis. The 
majority of them were forced into exile. The advent of Nazism was 
fatd also to the Berlin school, and the Polish groups were disrupted 
by the war. Neurath, who had taken refuge in Holland, made a valiant 
attempt to keep the movement going. The title of Erkenntnis was 
changed to The Journal of Unified Science and its place of publica- 
tion to the Hague. Arrangements were made for the publication by 
the University of Chicago, where Carnap was established, of a series 
of brochures ambitiously entitled the International Encyclopedia of 
Unified Science, Further congresses were planned. But with the out- 
break of war and Neurath’s death in England some years later, the 
movement lost its cohesion. Most of the volumes which were designed 
to constitute the Encyclopedia have in fact appeared, but the Journal 
of Unified Science very soon ceased publication and has not been 
revived. Besides Carnap, Feigl, Godel, Frank, Hempel and Tarski are 
still at universities in the United States, and Waismann and Popper 
at universities in England. Scholtz has remained at Munster and 
Kotarbinski and Ajduciewicz in Poland; and Victor Kraft resumed 
his chair of philosophy at the University of Vienna. But, however 
much influence these philosophers may exert individually, they do 
not constitute a school In this sense, the logical positivist movement 
has been broken up. 

Nevertheless its tradition has been continued, especially in Eng-' 
land, Scandinavia and the United States. In Scandinavia, Kaila has 
been joined at Helsinki by Von Wright, a pupil of Wittgenstein's who 
succeeded him for a time as professor of philosophy at Cambridge, 
the Uppsala school still flourishes, under the direction of Hedenius, 
Segerstedt and Marc-Wogau, v,ith support from the logician 
Wedberg in Stockholm, and Ame Naess in Oslo pursues his sociologi- 
cal researches into the current uses of language. Petzall continued 
to teach at Lund until his death in 1957 and Joergensen is still teach- 
ing in Copenhagen, though his positivism has been modified by an 
injection of Marxism. In the United States a number of philosophers 
like Quine, Nagel and Nelson Goodman conduct logical analysis in 
a systematic scientific spirit that is probably closer to the original ideal 
of the Vienna Circle than anything that is now to be met with else- 


[ 8 ] Editor's Introduction 

where. In this connection Nelson Goodman’s book The Structure of 
Appearance (1951) and Quine’s collection of essays From a Logical 
Point of View (1953) are especially notable. Their active interest in 
symbolic logic brings Quine and Goodman also into relation with 
Tarski, Godel, Church and other members of the important con- 
temporary group of American logicians. The same outlook is main- 
tained by Carnap and his pupils, notably Bar Hillel, who is now 
teaching at the University of Jerusalem, and by Feigl and Hempel. 
Other philosophers in the United States such as Norman Malcolm, 
Max Black, Morris Lazerowitz and C. L. Stevenson owe more to 
the influence of G. E. Moore or the later Wittgenstein, and conse- 
quently display an approach to philosophical questions which is 
closer to that of the contemporary British schools. 

In spite of the example of Bertrand Russell, there is not now 
among British philosophers the same interest in formal logic, or 
belief in the utility of symbolic techniques for clarifying philosophical 
issues, as is to be found in the United States. Neitlier is there the 
same desire to connect philosophy with science. My own Language, 
Truth and Logic, of which the first edition appeared in 1936, did 
something to popularize what may be called the classical position of 
the Vienna Circle; but since the war the prevailing tendency in Eng- 
land has been to replace this uncompromising positivism wdth its 
blanket rejection of metaphysics, its respect for scientific method, 
its assumption that in so far as philosophical problems are genuine 
at all they can be definitely solved by logical analysis, by an approach 
to philosophy which is empirical in the political sense, tiie sense in 
which Burke was a champion of empiricism. Generalizations are dis- 
trusted, particular examples are multiplied and carefully dissected. 
An attempt is made to illuminate ever>^ facet of a problem rather than 
to hammer or carve out a solution, common sense reigns as a con- 
stitutional, if not an absolute, monarch, philosophical theories are 
put to tlie touchstone of the way in which words are actually used. 
The metaphysician is treated no longer as a criminal but as a patient: 
there may be good reasons why he says the strange things that he 
does. This therapeutic technique, as it has been called, is well dis- 
played in the work of John Wisdom, now a professor at Cambridge, 
whose collected volumes of articles. Other Minds and Philosophy and 
Psycho-Analysis, appeared in 1952 and 1953. A more robust form 
of therapy is practised by Gilbert Ryle, professor of metaphysics 
at Oxford, whose Concept of Mind (1949), with its attack on the 
Cartesian myth of “the ghost in the machine,” has had a very great 


Editors Introduction [ 9 ] 

influence. Ryle shares with Wisdom a taste, and a gift, for analogy 
and metaphor, and a fondness for piling up examples, but he is less 
afraid of a generalization, less tolerant of departures from ordin^ 
usage^ more direct in Ms method than any present-day Wittgenstein- 
ian, and more ready to assume that a philosophical problem has a 
correct solution. What is now sometimes called the Oxford school, 
wMcii takes its tone from J. L. Austin more than from Ryle, carries its 
interest in the ordinary use of language to a point where it may be 
thought that philosophical analysis has given way to the study of 
philology. But this tendency is not all-prevailing. The work of such 
philosophers as Stuart Hampshire, P. F. Strawson and David Pears 
shows diat even within the framework of the Oxford manner there is 
still room for a fairly wide latitude of approach. The charge of 
scholasticism which is brought against “Oxford philosophy” is not 
entirely baseless; but it is not a truly warranted indictment. 

At the present time, the philosophical world is curiously divided. 
If positivism be taken in its widest sense, the sense in which it em- 
braces all shades of analytical, linguistic, or radically empirical 
philosophy, it is dominant in England and in Scandinavia, and com- 
mands considerable allegiance in Holland and Belgium, in Australia 
and in the United States. Elsewhere, it makes hardly any showing at 
all. Theoretically, it is not in all respects at odds with Marxism: the 
two at least have certain enemies in common: but it cannot flourish 
under Communist reginies, since Lenin's Materialism ami Empirio- 
Criticism, an attack on Mach and his followers which appeared in 
1905, declares it to be a form of bourgeois idealism. In other coun- 
tries again, one finds philosophers subscribing to neo-Thomism or to 
neo-Kantianism or to neo-Hegelianism or to Existentialism or what- 
ever form of German metaphysics may be in fa.shion. The ascend- 
ancy of Germany over France in this respect is especially remarkable. 
Conversely, in English-speaking countries there has been throughout 
the present century an almost complete disregard of the current 
extravagancies of German speculative thought. Such national divisions 
are indeed regrettable. They do not occur to anything like the same 
extent in other branches of learning. It is especially characteristic of 
philosophers that they tend to disagree not merely about the solution 
of certain problems but about the very nature of their subject and the 
methods by which it is to be pursued. Like others before them, the 
Vienna Circle believed that this could and should be remedied. They 
thought that they had succeeded, where Kant bad failed, in finding a 
way “to set philosophy upon the sure path of a science.” This end 


[ 10 ] Edito/s Introduction 

has not been attained: it may, indeed, be unattainable. All the same, 
there can be progress in philosophy and in one way and another the 
positivist movement is achieving it. 

II. The Attack on Metaphysics 

‘‘When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what 
havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume; of divinity 
or school metaphysics, for instance; let us ask, Does it contain any 
abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it con- 
tain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and exist- 
ence? No. Commit it then to the flames: for it can contain nothing but 
sophistry and illusion.” This quotation is taken from David Hume's 
Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. It is an excellent state- 
ment of the positivist’s position. In the case of the logical positivists, 
the epithet “logical” was added because they wished to annex the dis- 
coveries of modern logic; they believed, in particular, that the logical 
symbolism which had been developed by Frege, Peano and Russell 
would be serviceable to them. But their general outlook was very 
much the same as Hume’s. Like him, they divided significant proposi- 
tions into two classes; formal propositions, like those of logic or pure 
mathematics, which they held to be tautological, in a sense that I 
shall presently explain, and factual propositions, of which it was re- 
quired that they should be empirically verifiable. These classes were 
supposed to be exhaustive: so that if a sentence succeeded neither 
in expressing something that was formally true or false nor in express-v 
ing something that could be empirically tested, the view taken was 
that it did not express any proposition at all. It might have emotive 
meaning but it was literally nonsensical. A great deal of philosophical 
talk was held to fall into this category: talk about the absolute, or 
transcendent entities, or substance, or the destiny of man. Such 
utterances were said to be metaphysical; and the conclusion drawn 
was that if philosophy was to constitute a genuine branch of know- 
ledge it must emancipate itself from metaphysics. The Viennese 
positivists did not go so far as to say that all metaphysical works 
deserved to be committed to the flames: they allowed, somewhat per- 
functorily, that such writing might have poetic merit or even that it 
nnght express an exciting or interesting attitude to life. Their point 
was that even so it did not state anything that was either true or false 
and consequently that it could contribute nothing to the increase of 
knowledge. Metaphysical utterances were condemned not for being 
emotive, which could hardly be considered as objectionable in itself, 
but for pretending to be cognitive, for masquerading as something 



Editofs Introduction [ ] 

that they were not. Attacks on metaphysics occur fairly frequently 
in the history of philosophy. I have quoted Hume and I might also 
have quoted Kant who mamtained that the human understanding lost 
itself in contradictions when it ventured beyond the bounds of pos- 
sible experience. The originality of the logical positivists lay in their 
making the impossibility of metaphysics depend not upon the nature 
of what could be known but upon the nature of what could be said. 
Their charge against the metaphysician was that he breaks the rules 
which any utterance must satisfy if it is to be literally significant. 

At the outset, their formulation of these rules was linked with 
a conception of language which Wittgenstein, who inherited it from 
Russell, made fully explicit in his Tractatus. The underlying assump- 
tion is that there are statements which are elementary in the sense 
that, if they are true, they correspond to absolutely simple facts. 
It may be that the language which we actually use does not contain 
the means of expressing these statements: the statements which it 
can serve to express may none of them be entirely elementary; but 
these more complex statements must still rest upon a foundation of 
elementary statements, even if the foundation be hidden. They are 
significant only in so far as they say what would be said by affirming 
certain elementary statements and denying certain others, that is, only 
in so far as they give a true or false picture of the ultimate ‘‘atomic” 
facts. They can, therefore, be represented as being constructed out 
of elementary statements by the logical operations of conjunction 
and negation, in such a way that their tmth or falsehood is entirely 
dependent on the truth or falsehood of the elementary statements in 
question. Thus, assuming p and q to be elementary statements, the 
“molecular” statement “p or q” is taken to be equivalent to “not 
(not-/; and not-r/)”; and this means that it is false if both p and q are 
false, but true in the three remaining cases, namely that in which 
p and q are both true, that in wffiich p is true and q false, and that in 
which p is false and q tme. In general, given n elementary statements, 
where ti is any finite number, there are 2” possible distributions of 
truth and falsehood among them: and the meaning of the more com- 
plex statements which can be constructed out of them is constituted 
by the selection of truth distributions with which they agree or 
disagree. 

As a rule, it will be found that a statement agrees with some truth 
distributions and disagrees with others: among the possible states 
of affairs with which it is concerned, some would make it true, and 
others would make it false. There are, however, two extreme cases; 
that in which a statement agrees with every truth distribution and 


[ ^2 ] Editor's Introduction 

that in which it agrees with none. In the former case it is true in any 
circumstances whatsoever, and in the latter case false. According to 
Wittgenstein, these two extremes are those of tautology and contra- 
diction. On this view, all the truths of logic are tautologies; and if 
Russell and Whitehead succeeded in their attempt to show that mathe- 
matics is reducible to logic, so are the truths of mathematics. Witt- 
genstein himself did not allow that mathematical statements were 
tautologies; he said that they were identities: but apart from technical 
considerations, this comes to much the same thing. The point is that 
neither say anything about the world. The only way in which they 
can add to our knowledge is by enabling us to derive one statement 
from another: that is, by bringing out the implications of what, in a 
sense, we know already. 

Tautologies say nothing because of their excessive modesty: since 
they agree with every possible state of affairs, they make no claim 
upon the facts. Thus, I obtain some information, whether true or 
false, about the habits of lions if I am told that they are carnivorous, 
and equally if I am told that they are not; but to tell me that they are 
either carnivorous or not is to tell me nothing about them at all. 
Similarly, contradictions say nothing because of their excessive can- 
tankerousness; to disagree with every possible state of affairs is again 
to be disqualified from giving any information. I learn nothing, not 
even anything false, about the habits of lions if I am told that they 
are and are not carnivorous. On this interpretation, tautologies and 
contradictions are degenerate cases of factual statements. Meta-; 
physical assertions, on the other hand, are meaningless because they 
bear no relation to fact. They are not constructed out of elementary 
statements in any way at all. 

Since Wittgenstein did not say what he took his elementary 
statements to be, he did not make it quite clear at what point one 
is deemed to enter into metaphysics. It would seem, however, that 
any attempt to characterize reality as a whole, any such assertion as 
that the Universe is spiritual, or that everything happens for the 
best in the best of all possible worlds, must for him be metaphysical; 
for such assertions do not discriminate between possible states of 
affairs within the world — no matter what happens, it is to be char- 
acterized as spiritual, or regarded as happening for the best — ^from 
which it follows that they are not factual. Neither do they seem to 
be constructed out of factual statements in the way that tautologies 
are. And even if they were they would still say nothing. 

Whatever may have been Wittgenstein’s own view, his followers 
took it for granted that the elementary statements which yielded this 


Editor's Introduction . [ ] 

criterion of meaning were reports of observations. As we ^all see 
later on, they soon came to disagree about the character of these 
reports. There was a dispute over the question whether they were 
infallible, and whether they referred to the private sensations of the 
speaker, or to public physical events. But it was agreed that, in one 
form or another, they provided the touchstone by reference to which 
all other statements were empirically verified. And since, according 
to Wittgenstein’s theory, they alone furnished these statements with 
their factual content, they were also responsible for their meaning. 
This view was then summed up in the famous slogan that the meaning 
of a proposition is its method of verification. 

The assumption behind this slogan was that everything that could 
be said at all could be expressed in terms of elementary statements. 
All statements of a higher order, including the most abstract scientific 
hypotheses, were in the end nothing more than shorthand descriptions 
of observable events. But this assumption was very difficult to sus- 
tain. It was particularly vulnerable when the elementary statements 
were taken to be records of the subject’s immediate experiences: for 
while it has sometimes been maintained that statements about physical 
objects can be faithfully translated into statements about sense-data, 
no such translation has ever been achieved: there are, indeed, good 
grounds for supposing that it is not feasible. Moreover this choice of 
a basis raised the question of solipsism; the problem of making the 
transition from the subject’s private experiences to the experiences of 
others and to the public world. Carnap, indeed, in his Der logische 
Aufbau der Welt (1928) made a valiant attempt to reconstruct our 
whole apparatus of empirical concepts on a solipsistic foundation, 
taking as his starting-point the single undefined notion of remembered 
similarity: but he later acknowledged that this enterprise did not 
succeed. The position was easier for those who treated elementary 
statements as descriptions of physical events, though their right to 
do this remained in question: they at least were not troubled by the 
problem of solipsism or by the difficulty of reducing physical objects 
to sense-data. But other difficulties remained. The most serious 
of all, perhaps, was presented by the case of universal statements 
of law. For while the truth of such a statement may be confirmed 
by the accumulation of favorable instances, it is not formally entailed 
by them; the possibility that a further instance will refute it must 
always remain open: and this means that statements of this sort 
are not conclusively verifiable. On the other hand, they can be 
conclusively falsified in the sense that a negative instance formally 
contradicts them. For this reason Karl Popper suggested in his 


[ 14 ] Editor's Introduction 

Logik der Forschung that what should be required of a factual 
statement was just that it be capable in theory of being falsified. 
And he argued that apart from the logical superiority of this cri- 
terion it was more in accord with scientific practice; for scientists 
set up hypotheses which they test by looking for counter-examples: 
when a counter-example is discovered the hypothesis is rejected or 
modified; otherwise it is retained. But Popper’s criterion has demerits 
of its own. For instance, as he himself recognizes, it allows one to 
deny an indefinite existential statement but not to aEBirm it. One 
can say that there are no abominable snowmen, for this could be 
falsified by finding them, but one cannot say that there are abominable 
snowmen, for this could not be falsified; the fact that one had 
failed to find any would not prove conclusively that none existed. 
What could be disproved would be that any of them existed at a 
particular place and time, and it is only if this further specification 
is given that the statement becomes legitimate: otherwise it is to 
be counted as metaphysical. But this is to bring the frontiers of 
metaphysics rather close. 

Because of this and other diflSculties the view^ which came to 
prevail among the logical positivists was that the demands that a 
statement be conclusively verifiable, or that it be conclusively fal- 
sifiable, were both too stringent as criteria of meaning. They chose 
instead to be satisfied with a weaker criterion by which it was re- 
quired only that a statement be capable of being in some degree con- 
firmed or disconfirmed by observation; if it were not itself an' 
elementar}' statement, it had to be such that elementary statements 
could support it, but they did not need to entail it or to entail its 
negation. Unfortunately, this notion of “support” or “confirmation” 
has never yet been adequately formalized. Various attempts have 
been made to give '’the verification principle,” in this weaker form, 
a thoroughlv precise expression, but the results have not been alto- 
gether satisf actor}'. However, the employment of the principle did 
not wait upon its proper formulation; its general purport was held 
to be sufficiently clear. I have already given examples of the kind of 
philosophical talk that it served to eliminate: but its destructiveness 
was not confined to what one might call the grosser forms of meta- 
physics. As employed by the Viennese positivists, it made short work 
of most of the perennial problems of philosophy. Thus, the questions 
at issue between monists and pluralists, or between realists and 
idealists, were accounted no less spurious than questions about the 
limitations of Being, or a transcendent world of values. For what 
empirical test could possibly go to decide whether the world is one 


Editofs Introduction [ ] 

or many, or whether the things that we perceive do or do not exist 
outside someone’s mind? It is characteristic of such rival philo- 
sophical theses as realism and idealism that each is consistent with 
all the appearances, whatever their content may happen to be. But, 
for the positivist, it is just this that condemns them. 

An obvious objection to the verification principle, which the 
positivists’ opponents were quick to seize on, is that it is not itself 
verifiable. I suppose that it might be taken as an empirical hypothesis 
about the way in which people actually use the word “meaning,” 
but in that case it would appear to be false; for it is not contrary 
to ordinary usage to say that metaphysical utterances are meaningful. 
Neither did its sponsors put the principle forward as the result of 
any such empirical investigation. But then what status did they think 
it had? Might it not itself be metaphysical? Surprisingly, Wittgenstein 
acceded to this charge. “My propositions,” he said at the end of the 
Tractatus, “are elucidatory in this way: he who understands me 
finally recognizes them as senseless, when he has climbed out through 
them, on them, over them. (He must so to speak throw away tlie 
ladder, after he has climbed up on it.) He must surmount these 
propositions; then he sees the world rightly.” But this is a vain 
attempt to have it both ways. No doubt some pieces of nonsense 
are more suggestive than others, but this does not give them any 
logical force. If the verification principle really is nonsensical, it 
states nothing; and if one holds that it states nothing, then one can- 
not also maintain tiiat what it states is true. 

The Vienna Circle tended to ignore this difficulty: but it seems 
to me fairly clear that what they were in fact doing was to adopt 
the verification principle as a convention. They were propounding a 
definition of meaning which accorded with common usage in the 
sense that it set out the conditions that are in fact satisfied by state- 
ments which are regarded as empirically informative. Their treatment 
of a priori statements was also intended to provide an account of the 
way in which such statements actually function. To this extent tlieir 
work was descriptive; it became prescriptive with the suggestion 
that only statements of these two kinds should be regarded as either 
true or false, and that only statements which were capable of being 
either true or false should be regarded as literally meaningful. 

But why should this prescription be accepted? The most that 
has been proved is that metaphysical statements do not fall into the 
same category as the laws of logic, or as scientific hypotheses, or as 
historical narratives, or judgments of perception, or any other 
common sense descriptions of the “natural” world. Surely it does not 



[ 16 ] Edito/s Introduction 

follow that they are neither true nor false, still less that they are 
nonsensical? 

No, it does not follow. Or rather, it does not follow unless 
one makes it follow. The question is whether one thinks the difference 
between metaphysical and common sense or scientific statements to 
be sufficiently sharp for it to be useful to underline it in this way. The 
defect of this procedure is that it tends to make one blind to the 
interest that metaphysical questions can have. Its merit is that it 
removes tlie temptation to look upon the metaphysician as a sort 
of scientific overlord. Neither is this a trivial matter. It has far too 
often been assumed that the metaphysician was doing the same work 
as the scientist, only doing it more profoundly; that he was uncover- 
ing a deeper layer of facts. It is therefore important to emphasize that 
he is not in this sense describing any facts at all 

But then what is he doing? What is the point of saying, like 
McTaggart, that time is unreal or, like Berkeley, that physical objects 
are ideas in the mind of God or, like Heidegger, that the “nothing 
nihilates itself’? It should not be assumed that there is a general 
answer to this question, that metaphysicians are always doing the 
same sort of thing. One must begin in any case by looking at the 
context in which such pronouncements occur. Heidegger’s remark is 
a piece of verbiage, but it contributes in its fashion to his ^'develop- 
ment of the theme that it is a matter for wonder that the world exists. 
“Why is there anything at all,” he asks, “and not rather nothing?” 
This is indeed the kind of question that people expect philosophers 
to put: it has an air of profundity about it. The trouble is that it 
does not admit of any answer. On the face of it, McTaggart’s con- 
tention that time is unreal seems hardly more sensible. If taken 
literally, as implying that nothing ever happens, it is grotesquely 
false. And if it is not to be taken literally, what does it mean? The 
answer is to be found by looking at IvfeTaggart's arguments. He shows 
himself there to be perplexed by the idea of the passage of time; he 
tries to prove that the notion of an event’s being successively future, 
present, and past involves a vicious infinite regress. The proof is 
invalid, but we can learn something from it. In defending our use 
of temporal expressions against McTaggart’s arguments we may reach 
a clearer understanding of all that it implies. Berkeley, again, was 
concerned to discover what could be meant by saying that physical 
objects exist: he convinced himself by plausible arguments that 
when we speak of physical objects we can be referring only to collec- 
tions of “sensible qualities,” the existence of which consists in their 
being perceived; and he then brought in God as the permanent sen- 


Editor's Introduction [ ] 

sorium which was needed to keep things in being. His arguments can 
be withstood; but they do raise important philosophical problems 
about the meaning and justification of the statements that we make 
about the “external world.” 

The Viennese positivists were chiefly interested in the formal and 
the natural sciences. They did not identify philosophy with science, 
but they believed that it ought to contribute in its own way to the 
advance of scientific knowledge. They therefore condemned meta- 
physics because it failed to meet this condition. The logical analysts 
of to-day are more indulgent. They too are opposed to metaphysics 
in so far as it is merely rhapsodical: even in the sphere of ethics 
they wish to dissociate philosophy from preaching. But they allow 
that the metaphysician may sometimes be seeing the world in a fresh 
and interesting way; he may have good reason for being dissatisfied 
with our ordinary concepts, or for proposing to revise them. In many 
cases no doubt he is the victim of a logical error; but such errors 
may be instructive. If philosophical problems arise, as Wittgenstein 
thought, because we are led astray by certain features of our lan- 
guage, the metaphysician, by his very extravagancies, may also 
contribute to their dissolution. 

in. Language and Fact 

With their elimination of metaphysics, the Viennese positivists 
hoped that they had also put the theory of knowledge behind tlieni, 
but in this they were deceived. The first source of trouble was the 
notion of elementary statements. Both their character and status 
became a matter of dispute. 

At the outset, as I have said, the prevailing view was that these 
statements referred to the subject’s introspectible or sensory experi- 
ences. This view was adopted because it seemed to follow from the 
equation of the meaning of a statement with the method of its veri- 
fication. For in the last resort it is only through someone’s having 
some experience that any statement is actually verified. In most cases, 
the verification would consist in the perception of some physical 
object; but it was held, following Russell and ultimately Berkeley, 
that perceiving physical objects was to be analyzed in terras of hav- 
ing sensations, or as Russell put it, of sensing sense-data. Though 
physical objects might be publicly accessible, sense-data were taken 
to be private. There could be no question of our literally sharing one 
another’s sense-data, any more than we can literally share one an- 
other’s thoughts or images or feelings. The result was that the truth 


[ 18 ] Editor's Introduction 

of an elemcBtary statement could be directly checked only by the 
person to whose experience it referred. And not only was his judg- 
ment sovereign; in the most favorable case, it was held to be infallible. 
One can indeed be mistaken about the experiences that one is going 
to have in the future, or even about those that one has had in the past; 
it is not maintained that our memories cannot deceive us: but if one 
sets out merely to record an experience that one is actually having, 
then, on this view, there is no possibility of error. Since one can lie, 
one’s statement may be false; but one cannot be in doubt or mistaken 
about its truth. If it is false one knows it to be so. A way in which 
this point is sometimes put is by saying that statements of this 
kind are “incorrigible.” 

This conception of elementary statements was exposed to attack 
on various grounds. There were some to whom it seemed that no 
empirical statement could be incorrigible, in the sense required. They 
were therefore inclined to maintain either that one could be mistaken 
about the character of one’s present experience, so that the statements 
which purported to record it were fallible like the rest, or that these 
“direct records of experience” were not genuine statements, since they 
purchased their security at the expense of sacrificing all descriptive 
content. But the most serious difficulty lay in the privacy of the 
objects to which the elementary statements were supposed to refer. If 
each one of us is bound to interpret any statement as bein^ ultimately 
a description of his own private experiences, it is hard to see how wb 
can ever communicate at all. Even to speak of “each one of us” is to 
beg a question; for it would seem that on this view the supposition 
that other people exist can have no meaning for me unless I construe 
it as a hypothesis about my own observations of them, that is, about 
the course of my own actual or possible experiences. It was maintained 
by Carnap and others that the solipsism which seemed to be involved 
in this position was only methodological; but this was little more than 
an avowal of the purity of their intentions. It did nothing to mitigate 
the objections to their theory. 

At first, it was thought that the difficult}- about communication 
could be met by drawing a distinction between the content of ex- 
periences and their structure. Content, it was maintained, was incom- 
municable. Since other people cannot sense my sense-data, or share 
my thoughts or feelings, tiiey cannot verify the statements that I 
make about them; neither can I verify the corresponding statements 
that they make about their experiences. And if I cannot verify them, I 
cannot understand them either. To this extent we inhabit entirely 
dijfferent worlds. What can be verified, however, is that these worlds 


Editor's Introduction [ ] 

have a similar structure. I have no means of telling that the feeling 
which another person records when he says that he is in pain is at 
all like the feeling that I call pain; I have no means of telling that 
the colors which he identifies by the use of certain words look at all 
the same to him as the colors for which I use these words look to me. 
But at least I can observe that we apply the words on the same occa- 
sions, that his classification of objects according to their color coin- 
cides with mine; I can observe that when he says he is in pain he 
displays what I regard as the appropriate signs. And this is all that 
is required for communication. It does not matter to me what my 
neighbour’s experiences actually are; for all that I can ever know they 
are utterly different from mine. What matters is that tlie structure of 
our respective worlds is sufficiently alike for me to be able to rely on 
the information that he gives me. And it is in this sense only that we 
have a common language; we have, as it were, the same canvas which 
each of us paints in his own private fashion. It follows that if there 
are propositions, like the propositions of science, which have an 
inter-subjective meaning, they must be interpreted as descriptions of 
structure. 

As I have already remarked, the fundamental objection to this 
view is that it inconsistently puts the '‘private worlds” of other people 
on a level with one’s own; it results in a curious, and indeed contra- 
dictory, theory of multiple solipsism. But, apart from this, the dis- 
tinction which it tries to make between content and structure does 
not seem to be tenable. For what would be an example of a statement 
which referred only to structure? There is an echo here of Locke’s 
“primai7 qualities.” But statements which refer to the “geometrical” 
properties of objects, to “figure, extension, number and motion” have 
to be interpreted in terms of content, just as much as statements which 
refer to colors and sounds. If I have no means of knowing that my 
neighbor means the same as I do by his use of color-words, I have 
equally no means of knowing that he means the same by his use of 
words which refer to spatial relations or to numerical quantities. I 
cannot tell even that what I take to be the same word really is the 
same for him. All that I am left with is the apparent harmony of our 
behavior. Moreover it seems that the attempt to draw a distinction 
within the boundaries of descriptive language between what can and 
cannot be communicated must be self-defeating. It leads to the 
absurdity to which Ramsey draws attention in his short paper on 
“Philosophy,” which is included in this volume: “the position of the 
child in the following dialogue: ‘Say breakfast.’ ‘Can’t.’ ‘What can’t 
you say?’ ‘Can’t say breakfast.’ ” 


[ 20 ] Editor's Introduction 

Because of such difficulties, Neurath, and subsequently Carnap, 
rejected this whole conception of elementary statements. They argued 
that if elementary statements were to serve as the basis for the inter- 
subjective statements of science, they must themselves be inter- 
subjective. They must refer, not to private incommunicable experi- 
ences, but to public physical events. More generally, statements which 
ostensibly refer to experiences, or to “mental” states or processes of 
any kind, whether one’s own or anybody else’s, must all be equiva- 
lent to “physical statements”: for it is only in this way that they 
can be publicly intelligible. This is the thesis of physicalism. I shall 
not dwell upon it here, as I have inserted an article by Carnap, 
“Psychology in Physical Language,” which sets it out at length. 

The view that they were included in “the physical language” took 
away from elementary, or, as Neurath and Carnap called them, 
“protocol,” statements their privileged position. They were no longer 
thought to be incorrigible. Their truth, like that of any other physical 
statements, was always open to question. But, more than this, they 
lost even their judicial status. If a protocol-statement conflicted with 
a statement of a higher order, such as a scientific hypothesis, one or 
other of them would have to be abandoned, but it need not necessarily 
be the scientific hypothesis: in certain circumstances it might be more 
convenient to reject the protocol-statement instead. 

As can be seen from his paper on the foundation of "knowledge 
(“Uber das Fundament der Erkenntnis”) Schlick found this con- 
clusion unacceptable. He argued that to treat the reports of observa- 
tion, which was what protocol-statements were supposed to be, in ihis 
cavalier fashion, was to put scientific hypotheses, and indeed all 
would-be empirical statements, outside the control of fact. Neurath 
and Carnap, however, were not impressed by this argument. They had 
decided by this time that it was metaphysical to talk of comparing 
statements with facts. For what could this “comparison” be if not 
a logical relation? And the only thing to which a statement could 
stand in any logical relation was another statement. Consequentl}^ 
they were led to adopt a coherence theory of truth. 

Their version of the coherence theory was in some ways less 
objectionable than that which the Hegelian idealists had made 
familiar. Even so, for the reasons which I set out in my paper on 
Verification and Experience, it seems to me quite untenable. Carnap 
himself abandoned it after he had been convinced by Tarski of the 
respectability of semantics; for semantics provides us with the means 
of referring to the relationship between sentences and what they are 
used to signify. It provides, as Tarski showed, an adequate reformu- 


Editor* s Introduction [ ] 

lation of the correspondence theory of truth. On the other hand 
Carnap has not, so far as I know, abandoned the thesis of physicalism. 
But, if he does still hold it, I think that he is mistaken. It now seems 
clear to me that statements about the experiences of others can not 
be logically equivalent to statements about their overt behavior; while 
to maintain that the statements which one makes about one’s own 
experiences are equivalent to statements about the publicly observ- 
able condition of one’s body is, as Ramsey put it, to feign anaesthesia. 
Nevertheless, the difficulties which this thesis was designed to meet 
remain. Neither is it easy to see how else they can be avoided. I 
suggest, however, that much of the trouble may arise from the ac- 
ceptance of two false assumptions, the first being that for a language 
to be public it must refer to public objects, and the second that in 
making an empirical statement one is always referring to one’s own 
experiences. I still think that empirical statements must refer to 
experiences, in the sense that they must be verifiable; but the reference 
need not be to the experiences of any one person, as opposed to any 
other. But I acknowledge that this attempt to “neutralize” the verifi- 
cation principle meets with considerable difficulties of its own. 

IV. Ethics 

One of the attractions, especially for Neurath, of the thesis of 
physicalism was that it supported the doctrine of the Unity of Science. 
In one aspect, this was less of a doctrine than a program; it was 
desired that scientists of different disciplines should collaborate more 
closely with each other and with philosophers than they usually do: 
but it was also maintained that they were, or should be, spealdng a 
common language, that the vocabulary of the sciences should be 
unified. Thus, the Vienna Circle rejected the view, which many still 
hold, that there is a radical distinction between the natural and the 
social sciences. The scale and diversity of the phenomena with which 
the social sciences dealt made them less successful in establishing 
scientific laws, but this was a difficulty of practice, not of principle: 
they too were concerned in the end with physical events. 

Even those who did not accept the thesis of physicalism agreed 
that there was no essential difference in aim or method between the 
various branches of science. In the social sciences, no less than in 
the natural, an attempt was made to formulate hypotheses which 
could be tested by observation. Thus Schlick, who included ethics 
among the social sciences, denied that its results depended upon the 
use of any special faculty of moral intuition. The questions which 


[ 22 ] Editors Introduction 

arise in ethics are, in his opinion, questions of fact; why people hold 
the principles that they do, what it is that they desire, and how their 
desires can be fulfilled. In short, his general position is very similar 
to that of the Utilitarians. It has much the same merits and much the 
same defects. 

The Vienna Circle as a whole was not very greatly interested in 
ethics; but it did not dispute Schlick’s view that if ethical statements 
were to be brought into the scientific fold, they must be handled in the 
way that he proposed. The only question was whether they belonged 
within the fold, whether they were statements of fact at aU. Carnap, 
for example, maintained that they were not; he said that they were 
disguised imperatives. He did not develop this suggestion, but it has 
since been given substance by R. M. Hare in his book on The 
Language of Morals (1952). This imperative theory of ethics may 
be regarded as a version of the so-called Emotive Theorv^ which, 
mainly through the work of English and American philosophers, has 
come to be most closely associated with logical positivism. The 
salient point is that ethical statements are not descriptive of natural 
facts, still less of an alleged non-natural world of values: they are 
not descriptive of anything at all. The problem is then to determine 
how they do function. In C. L. Stevenson’s book Ethics a^id Lan- 
guage (1944), where the emotive theor}^ was first worked out in 
detail, it argued that ethical statements served the dyai purpose 
of expressing their author’s approval, or disapproval, of whatever 
was in question and recommending others to share his attitude. He 
laid particular emphasis upon the persuasive use of ethical terms. His 
views have not passed without criticism even from those who share 
his general standpoint; but the alternative accounts of ethics which 
these critics have put forward belong, as it were, to the same family. 

In discussions of logical positivism, this theory of ethics is apt 
to receive a disproportionate measure of attention, considering that it 
stands on the periphery of the system. One reason for this is that it 
has been thought, quite wrongly, that it was an onslaught upon 
morals. It has even been asserted, without a shadow of empirical 
evidence, that its advocates were corrupters of youth. In fact, the 
theory only explores the consequences of a sound and respectable 
point of logic which was already made by Hume; that normative 
statements are not derivable from descriptive statements, or, as Hume 
puts it, that “ought” does not foUow from “is.” To say that moral 
judgments are not fact-stating is not to say that they are unimportant, 
or even that there cannot be arguments in their favor. But these 
arguments do not work in the way that logical or scientific arguments 
do. It is not as if the intuitionists had discovered grounds for moral 


Bditor^s Introduction [ 23 ] 

judgments which the emotivists tried to take away. On the contrary, 
as Mr. Strawson shows in his paper on '‘Ethical Intnitionism/" the 
intnitiomsts themselves do not supply any foundation for moral 
judgments. It is therefore only on personal grounds that they can be 
entitled to put themselves forward as the guardians of virtue. 

V. Philosophical Analysis 

Some of the dissatisfaction that is aroused by the emotive theory 
of ethics, and indeed by logical positivism in general, may be due to 
the fact that people are still inclined to look to philosophy for guid- 
ance as to the way they ought to live. When this function is denied 
to it, and when it is denied even the possibility of penetrating the veil 
of appearance and exploring the hidden depths of reality, they feel 
that it is being trivialized. If this time-honored program is nonsensical, 
what remains? As Ramsey says, “philosophy must be of some use, 
and we must take it seriously.” But what function do the positivists 
leave it to perform? 

From the point of view of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus, its function 
would appear to be purely negative, though not for that reason un- 
important. “The right method of philosophy,” said Wittgenstein, 
“would be this. To say nothing except what can be said, i.e. the 
propositions of natural science, i.e. something that has nothing to do 
with philosophy: and then always, when someone wished to say 
something metaphysical, to demonstrate to him that he had given no 
meaning to certain signs in his propositions. This method would be 
unsatisfying to the other — he would not have the feeling that we 
were teaching him philosophy — but it would be the only strictly 
correct method.” This rather depressing view of the philosopher's 
duty was not stiictly maintained by Wittgenstein himselL The Philo- 
sophical Investigations contains a great deal more than a series of 
proofs that people have failed to attach any meaning to certain signs 
in their propositions. Nevertheless it still gives the impression 
that to philosophize is to get into a muddle, or to rescue oneself or 
others from one. Philosophy is “a battle against the bewitchment of 
our intelligence by means of language.” “What is your aim in philos- 
ophy? To show the &y the way out of the fly bottle.” All the same, it 
is meritorious of the fly to be there. It is the critical intelligences that 
get themselves bewitched. 

The Tractatus left no room for philosophical propositions. The 
whole field of significant discourse was covered by formal statements 
on the one hand and empirical statements on the other. There re- 
mained nothing for philosophy to be about. It was for this reason 


[ 24 ] Editor’s Introduction 

that Wittgenstein, and also Schlick, maintained that philosophy was 
not a doctrine bnt an activity. The result of philosophizing, said 
Schlick, would not be to accumulate a stock of philosophical propo- 
sitions, but to make other propositions clear. 

But to make propositions clear it must be possible to talk about 
them. As Russell points out in his introduction to the Tractatus, 
Wittgenstein appeared not to allow for this, or to allow for it only to 
a limited extent. He implied that an attempt to describe the structure 
of language, as opposed to exhibiting it in use, must result in non- 
sense. But though this conclusion may have been formally accepted 
by Schlick, it was in practice disregarded by the Vienna Circle. Thus, 
Carnap, in his Der Logische Aufbau der Welt, explicitly set himself 
to describe the structure of language by devising what he called a 
‘‘Konstitution-System,’' in which the various types of linguistic ex- 
pressions, or concepts, were assigned their proper places in a de- 
ductive hierarchy. If he had been questioned about the status of his 
own propositions, I suppose that he would have said that they were 
analytic; consisting, as they did, of definitions and their logical con- 
sequences, they would belong to the realm of formal truths. However 
this may be, he certainly believed that these propositions were sig- 
nificant; and he carried the Vienna Circle with him in holding that 
they were the sort of propositions that a philosopher should be ex- 
pected to put forward. 

The attempt to bring philosophy within the domain of logic was 
carried further by Carnap in his book on the Logical Syntax of 
Language, '‘Philosophy,” he says in the forev/ord to this book, “is- to 
be replaced by the logic of science — that is to say by the logical 
analysis of the concepts and sentences of the sciences, for the logic 
of science is nothing other than the logical syntax of the language 
of science.” Though he speaks here of the language of science, he 
does not hold that there need be only one. Alternative language- 
systems may be devised, and the choice between them is a matier of 
convenience; this is an important departure from the position of 
Wittgenstein’s Tractatus. According to Carnap, a language is char- 
acterized by its formation-rules, which specify what sequences of 
signs are to count as proper sentences of the language, and by its 
transformation-rules, which lay down the conditions under w'hich 
sentences are validly derivable from one another. It might be thought 
that if the language was to have any empirical application it must 
also contain meaning-rules; rules which would correlate its expres- 
sions with observable states of affairs: but Carnap, in this formalist 
stage of his philosophy, thought that he could dispense with them. 
He believed, quite mistakenly, that statements of verbal equiva- 


■TEdit<fffs introduction \ [ I 

Jeflces coold do the work not only of semantic statements but even 
of ostensive definitions. 

. . It is in this book that Carnap makes his famous distinction be- 
tween the material and the formal modes of speech. He distinguishes 
three kinds of sentences: “object-sentences,” such as “5 is a prime 
number” or “Babylon was a big town,” “pseudo-object sentences,” 
such as “Five is not a thing, but a number” “Babylon was treated of 
in yesterday’s lecture,” and “syntactical sentences” such as “ ‘Five’ 
is not a thing-word, but a number word” “The word ‘Babylon’ 
occurred in yesterday’s lecture.” The pseudo-object sentences are 
said to be “quasi-syntactical,” because they are syntactical sentences 
masquerading as object-sentences. They are “quasi-syntacticai sen- 
tences of the material mode of speech.” Translation from the material 
into the foimai mode replaces them by their syntactical equivalents. 
To put it less technically, when one speaks in the formal mode one 
is overtly speaking about words; when one speaks in the materia! 
mode one is speaking about words while seeming to speak about 
things. This distinction does not of course apply to object-sentences. 
Carnap was not maintaining, as some critics have supposed, that all 
discourse is about words. What he did appear to overlook, liowever, 
was the existence of a further category, that of pseudo-syntactical 
sentences; sentences which were about things but seemed to be about 
words. As a result, he was apt to fall into the error of treating these 
sentences as if they were syntactical. 

It is with the opposite error that he reproached most other philos- 
ophers. He maintained that philosophical statements were syntactical, 
but that they had been treated as if they were object-statements, be- 
cause of the fashion for expressing them in the material mode of 
speech. Thus, to take a selection of his examples, he argued that 
"The world is the totality of facts, not of things,” the first proposition 
of Wittgenstein’s Tractatiis, was equivalent to “Science is a system 
of sentences, not of names”: “This circumstance is logically neces- 
sary; . . . logically impossible; . . . logically possible” became 
“This sentence is analytic; . . . contradictory; . . . not contradictory”: 
Kronecker’s epigram “God created the natural numbers; everything 
else in mathematics is the work of man” was a way of saying “The 
natural-number symbols are primitive symbols; other numerical 
expressions are introduced by definition.” “The only primitive data 
are relations between experiences” was equivalent to “Only two-or 
more-termed predicates whose arguments belong to the genus oi 
experience-expressions occur as descriptive primitive symbols”: “Time 
is infinite in both directions” to “Every positive or negative real- 
number expression can be used as a time-co-ordinate.” Even the 


r 26 1 

^ Edito/s Introduction 

question of determinism was said to “concern a syntactical difference 
m Ae system of natural laws.” In this way rival philosophical theses 
If they made any sense at all, were represented as alternative pro- 
poses about die way one’s language should be formed. They were 
not true or false, but only more or less convenient. 

I think that Carnap’s distinction between the material and formal 
modes was frmtful, in that it caUed attention to the fact that many 
pMosoeucal statements are disguised statements about language. 
Where he went wrong for the most part was in supposing that they 
were synt^tical. For what they are concerned with is not the form 
or order of words, but their use. This does not come out in Carnap’s 
examples because he illicitly smuggles semantics into syntax. Thus 
expenence-expressions” is not a syntactical term. What makes ari 
expression an “experience-expression” is not its having any particular 
form but rte being used to refer to an experience. But then the 
quesbon what is to count as an experience becomes important. 
Neither is it to be settled by an arbitr£iry decision. 

In his more recent works, Carnap has recognized the legitimacy 
ot semantics, and indeed devoted considerable attention both to the 
development of semantic theory and to building up semantic sys- 
tems. interesting effect of this has been a marked relaxation of 
his philosophical austerity. Having acquired the right to speak of 
the reference of words to things, he has allowed almost any type 
or word to denote its special sort of object, thus recreating the 
baroque universe which RusseU had labored to depopulate. His defense 
of this apparent extravagance is to be found in his paper on “Em- 
piricism Semandcs and Ontology,” where he distinguishes between 
mtemal questions which arise within a given conceptual frame- 
work and external” questions which concern the status and legiti- 
macy of the framework itself. He himself has always been chiefly 
interested in the external questions: he has thought it his business 
as a philosopher to devise linguistic systems and elaborate concepts 
that will be useful to the scientist. And no one should deny that this 
IS a senous and legitimate activity. Where he is wrong, I think, is 
m assummg that the external questions present no serious problem: 
hat nothing more is at issue than a choice of linguistic forms. 

It is ^s ^sregard of questions about the status of his linguistic 
fram^orks that separates Carnap from the American philosophers, 
like Quine and Goodman, who resemble him in their systematic 
^proach to philosophy and in their preference for formal techniques. 
Ihese philosophers are interested in what they call ontology, that 
is, m the question how far one’s choice of language commits one to 
saymg that certain things exist. “To be,” says Quine, “is to be 


I 


7’''' ’*■ \MUofs Introduction [ ] 

j . ‘ the value of a variable”: aad this means that the extent of what 
i Russell called the "‘furniture” of the world depends upon the range 

I of predicates that are needed to describe it. Both Quine and Good- 

man wish this furniture to be as hard and spare as possible. They 
"denounce abstract entities” not just because they wish to exercise 
their logical ingenuity in seeing how well they can do without them, 
but because they cannot bring themselves to believe that they exist. 
In the same spirit, Goodman forgoes making any use of the notion 
! of possible, as opposed to actual, things, or of the distinction be- 
I tween causal and accidental connections, or of that between analytic 
I and synthetic statements. “You may,” he says, “decry some of these 

I scruples and protest that there are more things in heaven and earth 

I than are dreamt of in my philosophy. I am concerned, rather, that 
there should not be more things dreamt of in my philosophy than 
there are in heaven or earth.” It is not clear, however, cither in his 
case or in Quine’s, on what diis demand for stringent economy is 
based. Quine, indeed, allows in the end that the question of what 
there is must be settled on pragmatic grounds. And so he rejoins 
Carnap; but his pragmatism is much less serene. 

An interest in categories, which is another way of approaching 
the problem of what there is, is characteristic also of the British 
philosophers who have been influenced by the later work of Witt- 
genstein. But, for the most part, they are concerned not so much with 
trying to eliminate certain types of entity, or to “reduce” one to 
another, as with bringing out the resemblances and differences in the 
functioning of the statements which ostensibly refer to them. A 
technique which Wittgenstein himself uses for this purpose is that 
of derising what he calls language games. The idea is that by studying 
distorted or simplified models of our actual language we can obtain 
a clearer insight into the way it really works. This is one w^ay of 
protecting us against the error, into which we so easily fall, of as- 
suming that something must be the case, instead of looking and seeing 
what actually is the case. “Where our language suggests a body and 
there is none, there, we should like to say, is a spirit.'' But tiiis is 
to forsake description for bogus explanation. Very often the mental 
processes which we are led to postulate just do not occur. For in- 
stance, “it is no more essential to the understanding of a proposition 
that we should imagine anything in connection with it than that 
we should make a sketch from it.” Such remarks foreshadow Ryle’s 
attack upon the myth of “the ghost in the machine.” And much as 
Wittgenstein disliked Carnap’s methods, there is an echo of physi- 
calism in his dictum that “an ‘inner process’ stands in need of out- 
ward criteria.” 


[ 28 ] 

~ Editor’ s 

has also to be taken of the influence ^ o'" E 

seem to me, Iiowever that u * , Moore. It does not 

cemed with ordinary usage as sudi He^h?s 
upholding the “commonsefse view” of fte 
the propositions which exemolifv it- hnt h !f with analyzing 
we limit ourselves to orHino ^ insisted that 

When he does appLl to ^ ““^y^is. 

for dealing with other Dhiln<!nnh'^^ mainly as a weapon 

taken htefaS thw are S ftf®' ^ words are 

manifestly false It remainc ^ -ki™ muke statements which are 

from w™ 

the discovery of their meani/o- n appear to be saying, but then 
using words in any ordinarv sfn£- ^ problern. K they are not 

them has to be made cl^ ’ *®y rising 

schTO?” hLS acWevement of the “ordinary-language 

tific” uses of language. t^issection of the “unscien- 

description of what he calls nerfru^^?^^ ^ -Austin’s 

“I know . . .» or “I pJJ^se statements like 

assert a fact but to ccLmit the ’<:rv. purpose is not to 

some sort of guarantee To wha^ ° ^^y^ 

flexibility in the approach to Hna ™^§^^hve lengths this greater 
WaismaL’s pSer S by Dr. 

current conception of nhiincn v ^t shows that the 

Ramsey’s ide^ of philmoSiv^f ^Pmad far beyond 

Ramsey was right in savimr toac .®™P.y m definitions. But 

clarifying 

VI. 

devetopS“?tojc“£:SL'’r “=•““=' 

main points of coS^SS ^ , and the 

over many pieces that I sLu have wSf 1“ T’ 

CoweSton,’’°in^wWch^toe°oo’^ 5 

is effectively criticized or for Cani?’ pf 'i Priori statements 

bilify and Me^n^ IfTq 1/ f ^ ® ^uential articles on “Testa- 
contoins nothing of Witt^ens^l^^I T be regretted that the volume 
PA/toxopW ni the^JS T: r’' 

sodic charter Ts a wS to S’ H for all their epi- 

passages. They have to be read a^fwSe!'^ 









Logical Atomism 

BY BERTRAND RUSSELL 


The philosophy which I advocate is generally regarded as a species 
of realism, and accused of inconsistency because of the elements 
in it which seem contrary to that doctrine. For my part, I do not 
regard the issue between realists and their opponents as a funda- 
mental one; I could alter my view on this issue witiiout changing 
my mind as to any of the doctrines upon which I wish to lay stress. 
I hold that logic is what is fundamental in philosophy, and that 
schools should be characterized rather by their logic than by their 
metaphysic. My own logic is atomic, and it is this aspect upon 
which I should wish to lay stress. Therefore I prefer to describe 
my philosophy as “logical atomism,” rather than as “realism,” 
whether with or without some prefixed adjective. 

A few words as to historical development may be useful by way 
of preface. I came to philosophy through mathematics, or rather 
through the wish to find some reason to believe in the truth of 
mathematics. From early youth, I had an ardent desire to believe 
that there can be such a thing as knowledge, combined with a great 
dfficulty in accepting much that passes as knowledge. It seemed 
clear that the best chance of finding indubitable truth would be in 
pure mathematics, yet some of Euclid’s axioms were obviously doubt- 
ful, and the infinitesimal calculus, as I was taught it, was a mass 
of sophisms, which I could not bring myself to regard as anything 
else. I saw no reason to doubt the truth of arithmetic, but I did not 
then know that arithmetic can be made to embrace all traditional 
pure mathematics. At the age of eighteen I read Mill’s Logic, but 
was profoundly dissatisfied with his reasons for accepting arithmetic 
and geometiy. I had not read Hume, but it seemed to me that pure 
empiricism (which I was disposed to accept) must lead to scep- 

This essay was RusselFs contribution to Contsmporary British Philosophy, first 
series (ed. J. H, Muirhead), a book published in 1924. It is here reprinted by the 
kind pennission of the author and George Alien and Unwin Ltd., London. 



■fm- 






j 


[ 31 ] 


[ 32 ] BERTRAND RUSSELL 

ticism rather than to Mill’s support of received scientific doctrines. 
At Cambridge I read Kant and Hegel, as well as Mr. Bradley’s 
Logic, which influenced me profoundly. For some years I was a 
disciple of Mr. Bradley, but about 1898 I changed my views, largely 
as a result of arguments with G. E. Moore. I could no longer believe 
that knowing makes any difference to what is known. Also I found 
myself driven to pluralism. Analysis of mathematical propositions 
persuaded me that they could not be explained as even partial 
truths unless one admitted pluralism and the reality of relations. 
An accident led me at this time to study Leibniz, and I came to the 
conclusion (subsequently confirmed by Couturat’s masterly re- 
searches) that many of his most characteristic opinions were due 
to the purely logical doctrine that every proposition has a subject 
and a predicate. This doctrine is one which Leibniz shares with 
Spinoza, Hegel, and Mr. Bradley; it seemed to me that, if it is 
rejected, the whole foundation for the metaphysics of all these 
philosophers is shattered. I therefore returned to the problem which 
had originally led me to philosophy, namely, the foundations of 
mathematics, applying to it a new logic derived largely from Peano 
and Frege, which proved (at least, so I believe) far more fruitful 
than that of traditional philosophy. 

In the first place, I found that many of the stock philosophical 
arguments about mathematics (derived in the main from Kant)’ 
had been rendered invalid by the progress of mathematics in the 
meanwhile. Non-Euclidean geometry had undermined the argument 
of the transcendental aesthetic. Weierstrass had shown that the 
differential and integral calculus do not require the conception of 
the infinitesimal, and that, therefore, all that had been said by 
philosophers on such subjects as the continuity of space and lime 
and motion must be regarded as sheer error. Cantor freed the 
conception of infinite number from contradiction, and thus disposed 
of Kant’s antinomies as well as many of Hegel’s. Finally Frege 
showed in detail how arithmetic can ho deduced from pure logic, 
without the need of any fresh ideas or axioms, thus disproving Kanf s 
assertion that “7 4-5 = 12” is synthetic — at least in the obvious 
interpretation of that dictum. As all these results were obtained, not 
by any heroic method, but by patient detailed reasoning, I began 
to think it probable that philosophy had erred in adopting heroic 
remedies for intellectual difficulties, and that solutions were to be 
found merely by greater care and accuracy. This view I have come 
to hold more and more strongly as time went on, and it has led me 
to doubt whether philosophy, as a study distinct from science and 



Atomism [ 33 ] 

‘ pxsesseh of a method of its own, is anything more than an nn- 
^omte legacy from theology. 

Fiege’s work was not JBnal, in the first place because it applied 
only to arithmetic, not to other branches of mathematics; in the 
second place because his premises did not exclude certain contra- 
dictions to which ail past systems of formal logic turned out to be 
liable. Dr. Whitehead and I in collaboration tried to remedy these 
two defects,! in Frincipia Mathematical which, however, still falls 
short of finality in some fundamental points (notably the axiom 
of reducibilit>0 • spite of its shortcomings I think that no 

one who reads this book will dispute its main contention, namely, 

I that from certain ideas and axioms of formal logic, by the help of 
the logic of relations, all pure mathematics can be deduced, with- 
out any new undefined idea or unproved propositions. The technical 
methods of mathematical logic, as developed in this book, seem to 
me very powerful, and capable of providing a new instrument for 
the discussion of many problems that have hitherto remained sub- 
ject to philosophic vagueness. Dr. Whitehead's Concept of Nature 
and Principles of Natural Knowledge may serv'e as an illustration 
of what I mean. 

When pure mathematics is organized as a deductive system — 
i.e. as the set of all those propositions that can be deduced from 
an assigned set of premises — it becomes obvious that, if we are 
to believe in the truth of pure mathematic.s. it cannot be solely because 
we believe in the truth of the set of premises. Some of the premises 
are much less obvious than some of their consequences, and are 
believed chiefly because of their consequences. This will be found 
to be always the case when a science is arranged as a deductive 
system. It is not the logically simplest propositions of the system 
that are the most obvious, or that provide the chief part of our 
reasons for believing in the system. With the empirical sciences this 
is evident. Electro-dynamics, for example, can be concentrated into 
Maxwell’s equations, but these equations are believed because of 
the observed truth of certain of their logical consequences. Exactly 
the same thing happens in the pure realm of logic; the logically 
first principles of logic — at least some of them — are to be believed, 
not on their own account, but on account of their consequences. 
The epistemological question: “Why should I believe this set of 
propositions?” is quite different from the logical question: “What 
is the smallest and logically simplest group of propositions from 
which this set of propositions can be deduced?” Our reasons for 
believing logic and pure mathematics are, in part, only inductive and 


[ 34 ] 

. BERTRAND RUSSELL 

StSJof ? f order, the propo- 

irf hir ^ ™P°rtaBt, sirens 

ordor ^ i assimilating the logical to the epistemolo<ncaI 

w Iram assimilating a, apisteSSS 

(hSro^t J® falsehood of mathematics is by 

STSa^VnTr'h ““\™» “I-ows aat maaamatics 

that mathematics is true would require 
otner methods and other considerations. ^ 

T f important heuristic maxim which Dr. Whitehead and 

I found, by exi^ijnce, to be applicable in mathemafe^lS Sd 
have sm^ applied in various other fields, is a form of Sam’s 
t£°k supposed entities has neat logical proper- 

Im be r^nlao^H 'h ^ instances, that the supposed Ltities 

whirh K ^ ^ purely logical structures composed of entities 

« have not sneh neat properties. In that case, in interpretog a 
body of propositions hitherto believed to be about the Lnnosed 

in^i» detail of the body of propositions in question. This is 

infern°Tnd properties are always 

f rred, and if the propositions in which they occur cab be inter- 

doubtful stTo ThJ P™P°^dions is secured against the need of a 
aoubdul step. The pnnciple may be stated in the form: “Wherever 

possible, substitute constructions out of known entities for inferences 
to unknown entities.” fmcicnccs 

.. diis principle are very various, but are not intelli- 

gib e m detail to those who do not know mathematical logic. The 
first iiKtance I came across was what I have called “the principle 
^abstraction, or “the principle which dispenses with abstraction^”! 
SLiivT*"' w- '' ‘^ase of any symmetrical and 

StTnm / r’ “ ^P‘ to i”for that such 

otheTBu? S “ some'cases'^and uo“S 

^'iT ^ all the formal purposes of a common quality can be 
rved by membership of the group of terms having the said rela- 
tion to a given term. Take magnitude, for example. Let us suppose 

Sa ^ is easy to su^ose 

sW But ll n r quality caUed their length, which th?y all 
Share. But all propositions m which this supposed quality occurs will 

1. Our Knowledge of the External World, p. 42. 


Atomisfk [ 35 ] 

'' rciaiii their toith-valiie unchanged if, instead of ‘length of the rod x” 
wi take “membership of the group of all those rods which are as 
long as In various special cases — e.g. the definition of real num- 
bers — ^a simpler construction is possible* 

A very important example of the principle is Frege’s definition 
of the cardinal number of a given set of terms as the class of all 
sets that are “similar” to the given set — where two sets are “similar” 
wlien there is a one-one relation whose domain is the one set and 
wliose converse domain is the other. Thus a cardinal number is 
the class of all those classes which are similar to a given class. This 
definition leaves unchanged the truth-values of all propositions in 
which cardinal numbers occur, and avoids the inference to a set of 
entities called “cardinal numbers,” which were never needed except 
for the purpose of making arithmetic intelligible, and are now no 
longer needed for that purpose. 

i Perhaps even more important is the fact that classes themselves 
can be dispensed with by similar methods. Mathematics is full of 
propositions which seem to require that a class or an aggregate 
should be in some sense a single entity — e.g. the proposition “the 
number of combinations of n things any number at a time is 2”.” 
Since 2^ is always greater than n, this proposition leads to difficulties 
if classes are admitted because the number of classes of entities in 
the universe is greater than the number of entities in the universe, 
which would be odd if classes were some among entities. Fortunately 
all the propositions in which classes appear to be mentioned can 
be interpreted without supposing that there are classes. This is 
perhaps the most important of all the applications of our principle. 
(See Frincipia Mathematica, *20.) 

Another important example concerns what I call “definite 
descriptions,” i.e. such phrases as “the even prime,” “the present 
King of England,” “the present King of France.” There has always 
been a difficulty in interpreting such propositions as “the present 
King of France does not exist.” The difficulty arose through suppos- 
ing that “the present King of France” is the subject of this proposi- 
tion, which made it necessary to suppose that he subsists although he 
does not exist. But it is difficult to attribute even subsistence to “the 
round square” or “the even prime greater than 2.” In fact, “the 
round square does not subsist” is just as true as “the present King 
of France does not exist.” Thus the distinction between existence 
and subsistence does not help us. The fact is that, when the words 
“the so-and-so” occur in a proposition, there is no corresponding 
single constituent of the proposition, and when the proposition is 


I Jt)J 

,,, , j , BERTRAND RUSSELL 

so-and-so to sT^ “r J so-and-so exists, and x is the 

which it is ascribed nonsense Existence, in the sense in 

frS^ the hst of altogether 

S Tts refutations ontological argument and most 

Principia Mathematica, * 14 ) grammar. (See 

tionJforinfr^p™^^- examples of the substitution of construc- 

physics. examples la 

f sS£S 

time pervaded all aU time, and an instant of 

wants^as nehhS SSal mathematical physics 

are constructed bv E thr extension.) Event-particles 

and insS?s were Points 

UeiTTherefo”" *="o»n ”4?nS“’if'tt'S'' 

be constructed If tL wnfident that event-particles can 

as to meet those nf troJrf requirements 

two pieces of matter cannot he at tt. TOnstniction; first, that 

re”Se,'‘£ 

ettces mates one snspicions of^SS“^rcr!S.t,'; 


.’■■r ' ' , , I 

^ ' I 

togicai Atomism | [ 37 ] 

bannot help feeling that impenetrability is not an empirical fact, 
derived from observation of billiard-balls, but is something logically 
necessary. This feeling is wholly justified, but it could not be so 
if matter were not a logical construction. An immense number of 
occurrences coexist in any little region of space-time; when we are 
speaking of what is not logical construction, we find no such prop- 
erty as impenetrability, but, on the contrary, endless overlapping 
of the events in a part of space-time, however small. The reason 
that matter is impenetrable is because our definitions make it so. 
Speaking roughly, and merely so as to give a notion of how this 
happens, we may say that a piece of matter is all that happens in 
a certain track in space-time, and that we construct the tracks called 
bits of matter in such a way that they do not intersect. Matter 
is impenetrable because it is easier to state the laws of physics if 
we make our constructions so as to secure impenetrability. Impene- 
trability is a logically necessary^ result of definition, though the fact 
that such a definition is convenient is empirical. Bits of matter are 
not among the bricks out of which the world is built. The bricks 
are events, and bits of matter are portions of the structure to which 
we find it convenient to give separate attention. 

In the philosophy of mental occurrences there are also oppor- 
tunities for the application of our principle of constructions versus 
inferences. The subject, and the relation of a cognition to what is 
known, both have that schematic quality that arouses our suspicions. 
It is clear that the subject, if it is to be preserved at all, must be 
preserved as a construction, not as an inferred entity; the only question 
is whether the subject is sufficiently useful to be worth constructing. 
The relation of a cognition to what is known, again, cannot be a 
straightforward single ultimate, as I at one time believed it to be. 
Although I do not agree with pragmatism, I think William James 
was right in drawing attention to the complexity of “knowing.” It 
is impossible in a general summary, such as the present, to set out 
the reasons for this view. But whoever has acquiesced in our prin- 
ciple wiU agree that here is prima facie a case for applying it. 
Most of my Analysis of Mind consists of applications of this prin- 
ciple. But as psychology is scientifically much less perfected than 
physics, the opportunities for applying the principle are not so good. 
The principle depends, for its use, upon the existence of some fairly 
reliable body of propositions, which are to be interpreted by the 
logician in such a way as to preserve their truth while minimizing 
the element of inference to unobserved entities. The principle there- 
fore presupposes a moderately advanced science, in the absence 


1 J 

f I,. , , BERTRAND RUSSELL 

lTa»°Lr “« l» P-rely pmvisionl “ 

1 liave been speaking hitherto of what it is not neri^<^^ur^r t 

corr^Z",? ““r" of tha wZd S l^eS 

are w'te ^'° ^ ^“estioii, as to what these mateiiak 

to repLett ^ “ ''!■« <l^y tiy 

influence of language on philosophy has, I believe been 

i T„~rh=' “ •“ 

ask ourselves detoSy how tar U " Sttaare Th“’ “u*? “ 
brought 

be used tia^ifican% TtanS for^?^ ^ nameAvhich can 

there is a certnfn L . ^ suppose that 

because tVie persistent being called “Socrates ” 

we are led to're^vard^'^ applied to a series of occurrences which 
gro4 “re aSfr S , ‘“"S' As language 

nare^ .h„e repres;ntd“; “1!!^ 

there ™ Inv’Tr uuiversals b:, c rtainly 

" "ria„Shri« ri''"';- ““r"" “bi- 

mieleads uj boik^y "J “caSw Sd k T '“P““ 

be on our suard in hntfi syntax. We must 

false rnktaph^"" '“P^ ■« «« 'ogle is not to lead to a 

s«l“£s:~rS" — ■ 

hVS':he%t'.o“S”r' wZ'kt-” 

sense is influenced by flte existent TtewMd^Tid’toiTS,^ 


Atomism ^ [ 39 ] 

■ pose that one word must stand for one object, which will be a 
uiiiversai in the case of an adjective or an abstract word. Thus the 
lufluence of vocabulary is towards a kind of platonic pluralism of 
things and ideas. 

The influence of syntax, in the case of the Indo-European lan- 
guages, is quite different. Almost any proposition can be put into 
a form in which it has a subject and a predicate, united by a copula. 
It is natural to infer that every fact has a corresponding form, and 
consists in the possession of a quality by a substance. This leads, 
of course, to monism, since the fact that there were several sub- 
stances (if it were a fact) would not have the requisite form. 
Philosophers, as a rule, believe themselves free from this sort of 
influence of linguistic forms, but most of them seem to me to be 
mistaken in this belief. In thinking about abstract matters, the 
fact that the words for abstractions are no more abstract than ordin- 
ary words always makes it easier to think about the words than 
about what they stand for, and it is almost impossible to resist 
consistently the temptation to think about the words. 

Those who do not succumb to the subject-predicate logic are 
apt to get only one step further, and admit relations of two terms, 
such as before-^md-after, greater-and-less, right-and-left. Language 
lends itself to this extension of the subject-predicate logic, since 
we say precedes U/' exceeds B/' and so on. It is easy to 
prove that the fact expressed by a proposition of this sort cannot 
consist of the possession of a quality by a substance, or of the 
possession of two or more qualities by two or more substances. 
(See Principles of Mathematics, § 214.) The extension of the sub- 
ject-predicate logic is therefore right so far as it goes, but obviously 
a further extension can be proved necessary^ by exactly similar 
arguments. How far it is necessary' to go up the series of three- 
term, four-term, five-term . . . relations I do not know. But it is 
certainly necessary to go beyond two-term relations. In projective 
geometry, for example, the order of points on a line or of planes 
through a line requires a four-term relation. 

A very unfortunate effect of the peculiarities of language is in 
connection with adjectives and relations. All words are of the same 
logical type; a word is a class of series, of noises or shapes according 
as it is heard or read. But the meanings of words are of various 
different types; an attribute (expressed by an adjective) is of a 
different type from the objects to which it can be (whether truly 
or falsely) attributed; a relation (expressed perhaps by a preposi- 
tion, perhaps by a transitive verb, perhaps in some other way) is 


[40] 

BERTRAND RUSSELL 

TOt\oM^Th! v°“ between which it holds or does 

of tit f’ ^^^bon of a logical type is as follows: A and B are 
the same logical type if, and only if, given any fact of which A 

iorntimenf h ^ corresponding fact which has 5 as a 

*d ArlsS illustration, Socrates 

® s^ibe type, because “Socrates was a philos- 

Sd Cal,^!l ^ philosopher” are both facts; S^l:rates 

ODhe?^S “rT 1 “Socrates was a philos- 

t I af Cahgula was not a philosopher” are both facts. To love 

“Pl.,to *yPC’ because “Plato loved Socrates” and 

fmm tht^ Socrates” are both facts. It follows formally 

trom the defimtion that, when two words have meanings of differ- 

dHT-^Sm ^hey mean are of 
iTurent tjpes, that is to say, there is not one relation of meanincr 

between words and what they stand for, but as many relations of 
of a different logical type, as there are logical types 
amon^ the objects for which there are words. Tliis fact is a very 
potent source of error and confusion in philosophy. In particular, 
t has made it extraordinarily difficult to express in words any 
theory' of relations which is logically capable of being true, because 
language cannot preserye the difference of type between a relation 
and Its terms. Most of the arguments for and against the reality of 
relations have_ been yitiated through this source^ of confusion. 

At this point. 1 propo.se to digress for a moment, and to say. as 
shortly- as I can, what I belieye about relations. My own yiews on 
the subject of relations in the past were less clear than I thought 
hem. but were by no means the yiews which my critics supposed 
them to be. Owing to lack of clearness in my own thoughts, I was 
unable to conyey my meaning. The subject of relations 'is difficult, 
and i am far from claiming to be now dear about it. But .1 think 
certain points arc clear to me. At the time when I wrote The 
Principles o; Mathematics, I had not yet seen the necessity of lo.gical 
types. The doctrine of types profoundly affects logic, and I think 
shows what, exactly, is the yalid element in the arguments of those 
who oppose “external” relations. But so far from strengthening 
their mam position, the doctrine of types leads, on the contrary, 
to a more complete and radical atomism than any that I conceived 
to possible twenty years ago. The question of relations is one 
of the most important that arise in philosophy, as most other issues 
turn on it: momsm and pluralism; the question whether anything 
IS wholly trae except the whole of truth, or wholly real except the 


Logical Atomism [ ] 

wliole of reality; idealism and realism, in some of their forms; 
perhaps the very existence of philosophy as a subject distinct from 
science and possessing a method of its own. It will serve to make 
my meaning clear if I take a passage in Mr. Bradley’s Essays on 
Truth and Reality, not for controversial purposes, but because it 
raises exactly the issues that ought to be raised. But first of all I 
will try to state my own view, without argument.^ 

Certain contradictions — of which the simplest and oldest is the 
one about Epimenides the Cretan, who said that all Cretans were 
liars, which may be reduced to the man who says “I am lying” — 
convinced me, after five years devoted mainly to this one question, 
that no solution is technically possible without the doctrine of types. 
In its technical form, this doctrine states merely that a word or 
symbol may form part of a significant proposition, and in this 
sense have meaning, without being always able to be substituted 
for another word or symbol in the same or some other proposition 
without producing nonsense. Stated in this way, the doctrine may 
seem like a truism. “Brutus killed Caesar” is significant, but “Killed 
killed Caesar” is nonsense, so that we cannot replace “Brutus” by 
“killed,” although both words have meaning. This is plain common 
sense, but unfortunately almost all philosophy consists in an 
attempt to forget it. The follow'ing words, for example, by their 
very nature, sin against it: attribute, reiaiion, complex, fact, truth, 
falsehood, not, liar, omniscience. To give a meaning to these wx)rds, 
we have to make a detour by way of words or symbols and the 
different ways in which they may mean; and even then, we usually 
arrive, not at one meaning, but at an infinite series of different 
meanings. Words, as we saw, are all of the same logical type; there- 
fore when the meanings of two words are of different types, the 
relations of the two words to what they stand for are also of different 
types. Attribute-words and relation-words are of the same type, 
therefore we can say significantly “attribute-words and relation- 
words have different uses.” But we cannot say significantly “attributes 
are not relations.” By our definition of types, since relations are 
relations, the form of words “attributes are relations” must be not 
false, but meaningless, and the form of w^ords “attributes are not 
relations,” similarly, must be not true, but meaningless. Nevertheless, 
the statement “attribute-words are not relation-words” is significant 
and true. 


2. I am much indebted to my friend Wittgenstein in this matter. See his Trac- 
iatus Logico-Philosophicus, BCegan Paul, 1922. I do not accept all his doctrines, 
but my debt to him will be obvious to those who read his book. 


[ 42 ] 

BERTRAND RUSSELL 

tJr>r,c question of internal and external rein 

are S"^1.T “S 

'° 'iMrine of external relatioiis It is 2de^ to 

say terns are independent of their relations ” bec?ui “Si 

tetu” Inv toZ" r “ TWO events^ar^ s “dt 

Se oS thTs to one to 

die sepaition beK tte ewniTk spSto OMoS th ° 
ae^se of "fadepeadem” is relevant. If, sav"?^ ^ 

two sSnSnst 1. H ^ third term between the other 

the utmost ^care. ^ "^lust be avoided with 

PriiSfv °f external relations'? 

equTvaTeL foil's f°° P'-oPO^ition is not, in general, logically 
sited morirJi- SvS ^^^i^fP^dicate propositions" 

2’^ 5 “ general the case that we can findoredicateci S 

f^here'r of x and j', xi?y is equivalent to xc, y(i (x y)y 

me or consisting of x and v)! or to any 

one or mo of these. This, and this only, is what I mean to nffirJ 

ipart oihal relations; and this, clearly', ^ at 

iutei riai torine of 

In place of “unities” or “complexes,” I prefer to sneak of “fqptc ” 
?andv1n^ Understood that the word “fact” cannofoccur signifi- 
^ position m a sentence where the word “simnle” can 

^ur si^cantly, nor can a fact occur where a simple c^ occT 
We must not say “facts are not simples ” We can cav “Thf. c k i 
for a fact must not replace the sSl fo7: 

^ ^ P^®s®rved.” But it should be observed that’ 

in this sentence, the word “for” has different meanings on the^o 
occasions of its use. If we are to have a language wiSh is to sS- 


Atomism [ 43 ] 

guard us from errors as to types, the symbol for a fact must be a 
proposition, not a single word or letter. Facts can be asserted or 
denied, but cannot be named. (When I say “facts cannot be named/" 
this is, strictly speaking, nonsense. What can be said without falling 
into nonsense is: “The symbol for a fact is not a name.”) This 
illustrates how meaning is a different relation for different types. 
The way to mean a fact is to assert it; the way to mean a simple is 
to name it. Obviously naming is different from asserting, and 
similar differences exist where more advanced types are concerned, 
though language has no means of expressing the differences. 

There are many other matters in Mr. Bradley’s examination of 
my views which call for reply. But as my present purpose is explan- 
atoiy rather than controversial, I will pass them by, having, I hope, 
already said enough on the question of relations and complexes 
to make it clear what is the theory that I advocate. I will only add, 
as regards the doctrine of types, that most philosophers assume 
it now and then, and few would deny it, but that all (so far as I 
know) avoid formulating it precisely or drawing from it those 
deductions that are inconvenient for their systems. 

I come now to some of Mr. Bradley’s criticisms (Joe. cit,, 
p. 280 ff.). He says: 

“Mr. Russell’s main position has remained to myself incomprehen- 
sible. On the one side I am led to think that he defends a strict pluralism, 
for which nothing is admissible beyond simple terms and external rela- 
tions. On the other side Mr. Russell seems to assert emphatically, and 
to use throughout, ideas which such a pluralism surely must repudiate. 
He throughout stands upon unities which arc complex and which cannot 
be analysed into terms and relations. These two positions to my mind 
are irreconcilable, since the second, as I understand it, contradicts the 
first flatly.” 

With regard to external relations, my view is the one I have just 
stated, not the one commonly imputed by those who disagree. But 
with regard to unities, the question is more difficult. The topic is 
one with which language, by its very nature, is peculiarly unfitted 
to deal. I must beg the reader, therefore, to be indulgent if what I 
say is not exactly what I mean, and to try to see what I mean in 
spite of unavoidable linguistic obstacles to clear expression. 

To begin with, I do not believe that there are complexes or 
unities in the same sense in which there are simples. I did believe 
this when I wrote The Principles of Mathematics, but, on account 
of the doctrine of types, I have since abandoned this view. To 


[44 1 

■* BERTRAND RUSSELL 

speak loosdy, I regard simples and complexes as always of differ- 
ent types. That is to say, the statements “There are simples” and 
There are complexes” use the words “there are” in different senses 
But if I use the words “there are” in the sense which they have in 
the statement there are simples,” then the form of words “there 
are not complexes” is neither true nor false, but meaningless. This 
shows how difficult It is to say clearly, in ordinary language, what 
ir, Jr say about complexes. In the language of mathematical 
logic It IS much easier to say what I want to say, but much harder 
to induce people to understand what I mean when I say it 

When I speak of “simples” I ought to explain that I am speaking 
of somethmg not experienced as such, but known only inferentially 
as he limit of analysis. It is quite possible that, by greater logical 
skill, the need for assuming them could be avoided. A logical lan- 
page will not lead to error if its simple symbols (i.e. those not 
aving any parts that are symbols, or any significant structure) all 
sand fc^ objects of some one type, even if these objects are not 
simple The only drawback to such a language is that it is incapable 
of dealing with anything simpler than the objects which it repre- 
sente by simple symbols. But I confess it seems obvious to me (as 
1 did to Leibniz) that what is complex must be composed of 
smples, though the number of constituents may be^ infinite. It is 
also obvious that the logical uses of the old notion of substance 
ae. those uses which do not imply temporal duration) can only 
tw applied, if at all, to simples; objects of other types do not have 
mat land of being which one associates with substances. The 
essence of a substance, from the symbolic point of view, is that it 
can only be named — in old-fashioned lanauaae, it never occurs in a 
proposition except as the subject or as one of the terms of a rela- 
tion. If what we take to be simple is really complex, we may get 
into trouble by naming it, when what we ought to do is to assert 
It For example, if Plato loves Socrates, there is not an entity 
Plato s loye for Socrates.” but only the fact that Plato loves 
Socrates. And in speaking of this as “a fact,” we are already making 
It more substantial and more of a unity than we have any right to do 
Attributes Md relations, though they may be not susceptible 
of analysis, differ from substances by the fact that they suggest a 
structure, and that_ there can be no significant symbol which 
symbolizes them in isolation. AH propositions in which an attribute 
or a relation seems to be the subject are only significant if they can 
be brought into a form in which the attribute is attributed or the 
relation relates. If this were not the case, there would be significant 






Atomism [ 45 ] 

' pioiK)sitiom in wMch an attribute or a relation would occupy a 
position appropriate to a substance, which would be contrary to 
i the doctrine of types, and would produce contradictions. Thus 
the proper symbol for “yellow” (assuming for the sake of illustration 
that this is an attribute) is not the single word “yellow,” but the 
propositional function “x is yellow,” where the structure of the 
symbol shows the position which the word “yellow” must have if 
it is to be significant. Similarly the relation “precedes” must not be 
represented by this one word, but by the symbol '"x precedes y,” 
showing the way in which the symbol can occur significantly. (It 
is here assumed that values are not assigned to x and y when we 
are speaking of the attribute or relation itself.) 

The symbol for the simplest possible kind of fact will still be of 
the form ''x is yellow” or “x precedes y/' only that “x” and will be 
no longer undetermined variables, but names. 

In addition to the fact that we do not experience simples as such, 
there is another obstacle to the actual creation of a correct logical 
language such as I have been trying to describe. This obstacle is 
vagueness. All our words are more or less infected with vagueness, 
by which I mean that it is not always clear whether they apply to 
a given object or not. It is of the nature of words to be more or less 
general, and not to apply only to a single particular, but that 
would not malce them vague if the particulars to which they applied 
were a definite set. But this is never the case in practice. The defect, 
however, is one which it is easy to imagine removed, however 
dfficult it may be to remove it in fact. 

The purpose of the foregoing discussion of an ideal logical lan- 
guage (which would of course be whoHy useless for daily life) is 
twofold: first, to prevent inferences from the nature of language 
to the nature of the world, which are fallacious because they 
depend upon the logical defects of language; secondly, to suggest, 
by inquiring what logic requires of a language which is to avoid 
contradiction, what sort of a structure we may reasonably suppose 
the world to have. If I am right, there is nothing in logic that can 
help us to decide between monism and pluralism, or between the 
view that there are ultimate relational facts and the view that there 
are none. My own decision in favor of pluralism and relations is 
taken on empirical grounds, after convincing myself that the a 
priori arguments to the contrary are invalid. But I do not think 
these arguments can be adequately refuted without a thorough 
treatment of logical types, of which the above is a mere sketch. 

This brings me, however, to a question of method which I 






believe to be very important What a + tjund russell 

ophy? What shS hf? i« PMos- 

bein^ tn>t> ,u . ® ^ the greatest likelihood of 

ii other evidence? Tt ^ prop®^ to be rejected if it conflicts with 
likelihood of betog trSrin 

advanced rr Hn “the mam than any philosophy hitherto 

I L “y them 

there 2 nZe “ PMosophy 

mafb^ ^ proposition in a scieni 

a^fat St ’ ?i n there are some thS 

because tife rick nf^ ^ um philosophy upon science, 

at , . error m philosophy is pretty sure to be ereater 

X^^oXb. «r ““’“.‘■“P' ‘o' X? in pMos^rS 

coumL^hZ^ those philosophers whose theories, prirmi facie, run 
thaT t chal be able to interpret science so 

S rith 1- °wn level, with that minor degree 

of truth which ought to content the humble scientist. Those who 

how In defa^rr 1^" ^t seems to me-to 

show m detail how the mterpretation is to be effected In manv 

for'1mtaScS''ASlh^'' would be quite impossible. I do not believe", 
or instance, that those who disbelieve in the reality of relations 

Even if r^M '”P'“y asymmetricai iriations. 
tyen If I could see no way of answering the objections to relations 

hkdv th?n St”!w^ ^ still think it more 

likely than not that some answer was possible, because I should 

think an error in a very subtle and abstract argument more probable 

thimr we f falsehood in science. Admittine that everv- 

thmg we beheve ourselves to kmow is doubtful, it seems, nevertheless 

Si thlnlhl det n “ philosophy is more doubt- 

itc Snci* ^ though perhaps not more doubtful than 

Its most sweeping generalizations. 

nkti question of interpretation is of importance for almost every 
feSidtc and I am not at all inclined to deny that manv scientifc 
results require interpretation before they can be fitted into a co- 
herent philosophy. The maxim of “constructions ver.ur Serences^ 

IS itseff a m^im of interpretation. But I think that any valid kind 
of mterpretation ought to leave the detaff unchangeth though 
ay give a new meanmg to fundamental ideas. In practice this 
meMs that structure must be preserved. And a test of this is that 
all the propositions of a science should remain, though new mean- 




[ 47 ] 

be found for their terms, A case in point, on a non- 
level, is the relation of the physicd theory of light 
our perceptions of color. This provides different physical occur- 
rences corresponding to different seen colors, and thus makes the 
structure of the physical spectrum the same as that of what we see 
when we look at a rainbow. Unless structure is preserved, we cannot 
validly speak of an interpretation. And structure is just what is 
destroyed by a monistic logic. 

I do not mean, of course, to suggest that, in any region of science, 
structure revealed at present by observation is exactly that 
actually exists. On the contrary, it is in the highest degree 
that the actual structure is more fine-grained than the 
observed structure. This applies just as much to psychological as 
to physical material. It rests upon the fact that, where we perceive 
a difference (e.g. between two shades of color), there is a differ- 
ence, but where we do not perceive a difference it does not follow 
that there is not a difference. We have therefore a right, in all inter- 
pretation, to demand the preservation of observed differences, and 
the provision of room for hitherto unobserved differences, although 
we cannot say in advance what they will be, except when they can 
be inferentially connected with observed differences. 

In science, structure is the main study. A large part of the im- 
portance of relativity comes from the fact that it has substituted a 
single four-dimensional manifold (space-time) for the two mani- 
folds, three-dimensional space and one-dimensional time. This is a 
change of structure, and therefore has far-reaching consequences, 
but any change which does not involve a change of structure does 
not make much difference. The mathematical definition and study 
of structure (under the name of ‘Velation-numbers”) form Part IV 
of Principia Mathematical 

The business of philosophy, as I conceive it, is essentially that 
of logical analysis, followed by logical synthesis. Philosophy is more 
concerned than any special science with relations of different sciences 
and possible conflicts between them; in particular, it cannot acquiesce 
in a conflict between physics and psychology, or between psychology 
and logic. Philosophy should be comprehensive, and should be bold 
in suggesting hypotheses as to the universe which science is not 
yet in a position to confirm or confute. But these should always 
be presented as hypotheses, not (as is too often done) as immutable 
certainties like the dogmas of religion. Although, moreover, com- 
prehensive construction is part of the business of philosophy, I do 
not believe it is the most important part. The most important part, 


r 48 1 

-* BERTRAND RUSSELL 

to my I^d, consists in criticizing and clarifying notions which are 
apt to be regarded as fundamental and accepted uncritically. As 
instances I might mention: mind, matter, consciousness, knowledge 
experience, causality, will, time. I believe all these notions to be 
inexact and approximate, essentially infected with vagueness in- 
capable of forming part of any exact science. Out of the oririnal 
manifold of events, logical structures can be budt which will have 
properties sufficiently like those of the above common notions to 
account for their prevalence, but sufficiently unlike to allow a great 
deal of error to creep in through their acceptance as fundamental. 

the following as an outline of a possible structure of 
the world; it is no more than an outline, and is not offered as more 
than possible. 

'ae world consists of a number, perhaps finite, perhaps infinite, 
ot entities which have various relations to each other, and perhaps 
also vanous quafities. Each of these entities may be called an 
event , from the point of view of old-fashioned physics, an event 
occupies a short finite time and a small finite amount of space, but 
as we are not going to have an old-fashioned space and an old- 
rashioned time, this statement cannot be taken at its face value. 
Eveiy event has to a certain number of others a relation which may 
be called compresence”; from the point of view of physics, a col- 
lection of compresent events all occupy one small region in space- 
time. One example of a set of compresent events is what would 
be called the contents of one man’s mind at one time — i.e. all his 
sensations, images, memories, thoughts, etc., which can coexist 
temporally. His visual field has, in one sense, spatial extension, but 
this must not be confused with the extension of physical space-time; 
every part of his visual field is compresent with every' other part 
and with the rest of “the contents of his mind” at that time, ‘and 
a collection of compresent events occupies a minimal region in 
pace-time. There are such collections not only where there are 
brains, but everywhere. At any point in “empty space,” a number 
OT stars could be photographed if a camera were introduced- we 
believe thOT light travels over the regions intermediate between its 
source and our eyes, and therefore something is happening in these 
regions. If fight from a number of different sources reaches" a certain 
minimal region in space-time, then at least one event corresponding 
o each of these sources exists in this minimal region, and all these 
events are compresent. 

«r compresent events as a “minimal region.” 

e find that mmimal regions form a four-dimensional maffifold, 


Atomism 

that,'. by a little logical manipulation, we can construct from 
* ' ^tm the manifold of space-time that physics requires. We find also 
. / that, from a number of different minimal regions, we can often 
^ ' pick out a set of events, one from each, which are closely similar 
when they come from neighboring regions, and vary from one region 
" to another according to discoverable laws. These are the laws of the 
propagation of light, sound, etc. We find also that certain regions 
in space-time have quite peculiar properties; these are the regions 
which are said to be occupied by "‘matter.” Such regions can be 
collected, by means of the laws of physics, into tracks or tubes, very 
much more extended in one dimension of space-time than in the 
other three. Such a tube constitutes the “history” of a piece of 
matter; from the point of view of the piece of matter itself, the 
dimension in which it is most extended can be called “time,” but 
it is only the private time of that piece of matter, because it does 
not correspond exactly with the dimension in which another piece of 
matter is most extended. Not only is space-time very peculiar within 
a piece of matter, but it is also rather peculiar in its neighborhood, 
growing less so as the spatio-temporal distance grows greater; the 
law of this peculiarity is the law of gravitation. 

All kinds of matter to some extent, but some kinds of matter 
(viz. nervous tissue) more particularly, are liable to form “habits,” 
i.e. to alter their structure in a given environment in such a way that, 
when they are subsequently in a similar environment, they react 
in a new way, but if similar environments recur often, the reaction 
in the end becomes nearly uniform, while remaining different from 
the reaction on the first occasion, (When I speak of the reaction 
of a piece of matter to its environment, I am thinking both of the 
constitution of the set of coinpresent events of which it consists, 
and of the nature of the track in space-time which constitutes what 
we should ordinarily call its motion; these are called a “reaction 
to the environment” in so far as there are laws correlating them 
with characteristics of the environment.) Out of habit, the peculiari- 
ties of what we call “mind” can be constructed; a mind is a track 
of sets of compresent events in a region of space-time where there 
is matter which is peculiarly liable to form habits. The greater the 
liability, the more complex and organized the mind becomes. Thus 
a mind and a brain are not really distinct, but when we speak of a 
mind we are thinking chiefly of the set of compresent events in the 
region concerned, and of their several relations to other events form- 
ing parts of other periods in the history of the spatio-temporal tube 
which we are considering, whereas when we speak of a brain we 


m 


[ 50 ] 

BERTRAND RUSSELL 

compresent events as a whole, and considerinE 
Its eternal relations to other sets of compresent events alS talcpf 
^ wholes; m a word, we are considering the shape of the tube not 
the events of which each cross-section of it is composed. 

summary hypothesis would, of course, need to be 
amplified and refined m many ways in order to fit in comoletelv 

forward as a finished theo^ but 
nf r ^ ^ suggestion of the kind of thing that may be true It is 

of course easy to imagine other hypotheses which may be true for 
example, the hypoteia that there is oothiag outsSfthe Ss 3 

SSf m °® hypothesis, and therefore 

rmraWSy-r^hTosS^^^ tItaTr 






From time to time prizes have been established for essays on the 
question what progress philosophy has made in a given period. The 
period tends to be limited on the one side by the name of some great 
thinker, on the other by ‘‘the present.’’ It was thus assumed that there 
is some degree of clarity regarding the philosophic progress of man- 
kind up to the time of that thinker, but that it is dubious what further 
contributions have been made in recent times. 

Such questions clearly express a certain mistrust concerning the 
philosophy of the period which had recently elapsed. One has the 
impression of being presented only with an embarrassed formulation 
of the question: Has philosophy in that period made any progress 
whatever? For if one were sure that contributions had been made one 
would also know in what they consisted. 

If the more remote past is regarded with less scepticism and 
one is rather inclined to see in its philosophy a continuous devel- 
opment, the explanation may be that one’s attitude towards every- 
thing whose place is established in history is tinged with greater re- 
spect. A further point is that the older philosophers have at least 
demonstrated their historical influence. Hence in considering them 
one can take as one’s base their historical rather than their substantive 
importance, especially since one often does not venture to distinguish 
between the two. 

But it is just the ablest thinkers who most rarely have believed 
that the results of earlier philosophizing, including that of the classical 
models, remain unshakable. This is shown by the fact that basically 
ever}' no^w system starts again from the beginning, that every thinker 

“Die Wende Der Pliiiosophie,” as this piece is called in German, opened the 
first number of Volume I of Brkenntnis (1930/31). It is here published with the 
kind permission of Mrs. Schiick and Professor Carnap, the co-editor of Brkenntnis. 


The Turning Point in Philosophy 


BY MORITZ SCHLICK 


(TRANSLATED BY DAVID RYNIN) 


[ 53 ] 


[ ] MORITZ SCHLICKI 

seeks Ms own foundation and does not wish to stand on the shoul- 
ders of his predecessors. Descartes (not without reason) felt himself 
to be making a wholly new beginning; Spinoza believed that in 
introducing the (to be sure quite adventitious) mathematical form 
he had found the ultimate philosophical method; and Kant was 
convinced that on the basis of the way taken by him philosophy 
would at last adopt the sure path of a science. Further examples 
are superfluous, for practically all great thinkers have sought for 
a radical reform of philosophy and considered it essential. 

TMs peculiar fate of philosophy has been so often described 
and bemoaned that it is indeed pointless to discuss it at all. Silent 
scepticism and resignation seem to be the only appropriate attitudes. 
Two thousand years of experience seem to teach that efforts to put 
an end to the chaos of systems and to change the fate of philosophy 
can no longer be taken seriously. To point out that man has finally 
succeeded in solving the most stubborn problems, for example that of 
Daedelus, gives an informed person no comfort; for what he fears is 
just that philosophy will never arrive at a genuine “problem.” 

I refer to this anarchy of philosophical opinions which has so 
often been described, in order to leave no doubt that I am fully con- 
scious of the scope and weighty significance of the conviction that I 
should now like to express. For 1 am convinced that we now find 
ourselves at an altogether decisive turning point in philosophy, and 
that we are objectively justified in considering that an end has come 
to the fruitless conflict of systems. We are already at the present time, 
in my opinion, in possession of methods which make every auch con- 
flict in principle unnecessary. What is now required is their resolute 
application. 

These methods have been quietly developed, unnoticed by the 
majority of those who teach or write philosophy; and thus a situation 
has been created which is not comparable to any earlier one. That 
the situation is unique and that the turning embarked upon is really 
decisive can be understood only by becoming acquainted with the 
new paths and by looking back, from the standpoint to which they 
lead, upon all those efforts that have ever passed as “philosophiciii.” 

The paths have their origin in logic. Leibniz dimly saw their 
beginning. Bertrand Russell and Gottlob Frege have opened up im- 
portant stretches in the last decades, but Ludwig Wittgenstein (in 
his Tractatus Logico-Fhilosophicus, 1922) is the first to have pushed 
forward to the decisive turning point. 

It is well known that in recent decades mathematicians have 
developed new logical methods, at first primarily for the solution 




Turning Faint in Philosophy [ 55 ] 

:“‘j\ ^ own problems wMcb could not be overcome by the tradi- 
.'■''''"lional methods of logic. But the logic thus developed has also long 
ginoe shown its superiority in other ways over the old forms, and 
doubtless will very soon supplant them. Was I referring to this logic 

" 25 ifje powerful means which is in principle capable of raising us above 

‘ ‘ all philosophical coEflicts? Does it give us general rules with those 
help aU the traditional problems of philosophy can at least in prin- 
! ! ' ciple be 'resolved? 

. , If tins were so I should hardly have had the right to say that a 
wholly new situation had been created. For then there would have 
been only a gradual, as it were, technical progress, as for example, 
when the invention of the intemal combustion engine finally made 
possible the solution of the problem of flight. However highly the 
value of the new methods is to be esteemed, it is plain that nothing 
so fundamental can be brought about by the mere development of 
a method. The great turning point is therefore not to be attributed 
to logic itself but to something quite difierent wiiich was indeed stim- 
ulated and made possible by it, but which proceeds on a much 
deeper level: the insight into the nature of logic itself. 

That the logical is in some sense the purely formal has been 
expressed early and often; however, one was not really clear con- 
cerning the nature of pure forms. The clue to their nature is to be 
found in the fact that every cognition is an expression or repre- 
sentation. That is, it expresses a fact which is cognized in it. This 
can happen in any number of ways, in any language, by means of 
any arbitrary^ system of signs. All these possible modes of repre- 
sentation — if they otherwise actually express the same knowledge — 
must have something in common; and what is common to them is 
their logical form. 

So all knowledge is such only by virtue of its form. It is through 
its form that it represents the fact known. But the form cannot itself 
in turn be represented. It alone is concerned in cognition. Everything 
else in the expression is inessential and accidental material, not 
different, say, from the ink by means of which we write down a 
statement. 

This simple insight has consequences of the very greatest im- 
portance. Above all, it enables us to dispose of the traditional prob- 
lems of “the theory of knowledge.” Investigations concerning the 
human “capacity for knowledge,” in so far as they do not become 
part of psychology, are replaced by considerations regarding the 
nature of expression, of representation, i.e. concerning every pos- 
sible “language” in the most general sense of the term. Questions 


[56 1 

^ ^ MORITZ SCHLICR 

regardmg the “vahdity and Umits of knowledge” disappear Everv- 
thmg IS knowable which can be expressed, and this is the total 
^bject matter concerning which meaningful questions can be raised 
Ihere are consequently no questions which are in principle un- 
answerable, no problems which are in principle insoluble. What 
aye been considered such up to now are not genuine questions 
but meaningless sequences of words. To be sure, they look like ques- 
lons from the outside, since they seem to satisfy the customary rules 
of grammar but in truth they consist of empty sounds, because they 
ransgress the profound inner rules of logical syntax discovered by 
the new analysis. ^ 

Wherever there is a meaningful problem one can in theory always 
c,ive e path that leads to its solution. For it becomes evident that 
giving this path coincides with the indication of its meanin». The 
practical following out of this path may of course be hindered by 
factual circumstances-by deficient human capacities, for example. 

■ , ^ ^ verification in which the path to the solution finally ends 

us alwip of the same sort: it is the occurrence of a definite fact tha't 
IS confirmed by observation, by means of immediate experience. In 
us manner^ the truth (or falsity) of even,- statement, of daily life 
or science, ,s determined. There is thus no other testing and' cor- 
roboration of truths e.xcept through observation and empirical science 
Exeiy^ science, (m so far as we take tills word to refcr'to thccontent 
and not to the human arrangements for arriving at it) is a system of 
cognitions, that is, of true experiential statements. And the totaiitv 
ol sciences, including the statements of daily life, is the system of 
cognitions. There is, in addition to it, no domain of ^philo^yphical” 
tniths. 1 hilosophy is not a system of statements: it is not a iience. 

But what IS It then? Well, certainly not a science, but neverthc- 

•itb‘dbrrh"f important tiiat it mav henceforth, 

tritn th-i o' “ the Queen of the Sciences. For'it is nowhere 
ynttwi. that the Queen of the Sciences must itself be a science The 
great contemporaQ^ turning point is characterized bv the fact that 
wc see in philosophy not a system of cognitions, but a'svstem of aciv 
philosophy IS tluit activity through which the meaning of statements 
IS revealed or determined. By means of philosophy ^statemenS Tre 
explained by means of science they are verified. The latter is con- 

Th ^ the truth of statements, the former with what they actually 

hat in the last analysis its statements actually mean; the philo- 
sophical activity of giving meaning is therefore the Alpha and Omega 
of aU scientific knowledge. This was indeed correctly surmised when 


Turning Point in Philosophy [ 57 J 

■ it was saidi that philosophy supplied both the foundation and the 
apex of the edifice of science. It was a mistake, however, to suppose 
that the foundation was made up of “philosophical’' statements (the 
statements of theory of knowledge), and crowned by a dome of 
philosophical statements (called metaphysics). 

It is easy to see that the task of philosophy does not consist in 
asserting statements — that bestowing meaning upon statements can- 
not be done in turn by statements. For if, say, I give the meaning 
of my words through explanatoiv^ statements and definitions, that is 
by help of other words, one must ask further for the meaning of 
these words, and so on. This process cannot proceed endlessly. It 
I always comes to an end in actual pointings, in exhibiting what is 
I meant, thus in real acts; only these acts are no longer capable of, 

: or in need of, further explanation. The final giving of meaning always 
I takes place therefore, through deeds. It is these deeds or acts which 
1 constitute philosophical activity. 

“ It was one of the most serious errors of former times to have 
I believed that the actual meaning and ultimate content was in turn 
to be formulated in statements, and so was representable in cognitions. 
This was the error of “metaphysics.'' The efforts of metaphysicians 
were always directed upon the absurd end of expressing the content 
of pure quality (the “essence" of things'! by means of cognitions, 
hence of uttering the unutterable.'^ Qualities cannot be “said." They 
can only be shown in experience. But with this showing, cognition has 
nothing to do. 

Thus metaphysics collapses not because the solving of its tasks 
is an enterprise to which the human reason is unequal (as for ex- 
ample Kant thought) but because there is no such task. With the 
disclosure of the mistaken formuiaiion of the problem the histoiw 
of metaphysical conflict is likewise explained. 

If our conception is in general correct we must be able to establish 
it historicaliy. It would have lo be capable of gffang some account 
of the change in meaning of the word “philosophy." 

Now this is actually the case. If in ancient times, and actually 
until recently, philosophy was simply identical with eveiy^ purely 
theoretical scientific investigation, this points to the fact that science 
found itself in a state in which it saw its main task still in the clari- 
' fication of its fundamental concepts. The emancipation of the special 
sciences from their common mother, philosophy, indicates that the 
' meaning of certain fundamental concepts became clear enough to 
make successful further work with them possible. If, today, ethics 

1. See my article “Erleben, Erkennen, Meiaphysik/’ Kantstudien, Vol. 31 (1930). 


ist be able to establish 
ai\anc some account 






MORITZ SCHLICK 


[ 58 ] 

and aesthetics, and frequently also psychology, are considered branches 
of philosophy, this is a sign that these studies do not yet possess 
sufficiently clear basic concepts, that their efforts are still chieiy 
directed upon the meaning of their statements. Finally, if within 
a well-established science the necessity suddenly arises at some 
point of reflecting anew on the true meaning of the fundamental 
concepts, and thereby a more profound clarification of their mean- 
ing is achieved, tins will be felt at once as an eminent philosophical 
achievement. All are agreed that, for instance, Einstein’s work, pro- 
ceeding from an analysis of the meaning of statements about time and 
space, was actually a philosophical achievement. Here we should add 
that the decisive epoch-making forward steps of science are always 
of this character; they signify a clarification of the meaning of the 
fundamental statements and only those succeed in them who are 
endowed for philosophical activity. The great investigator is also 
always a philosopher. 

Frequently also the name of philosophy is bestowed on mental 
activities which have as their concern not pure knowledge but the con- 
duct of life. This is readily understandable. For the wise man rises 
above the uncomprehending mass just by virtue of the fact that he 
can point out more clearly than they the meaning of statements and 
questions concerning life relationships, facts and desires. 

The great turning point of philosophy signifies also a decisive 
turning away from certain erroneous paths which have been embarked 
upon since the second half of the 19 th century and which must lead 
to quite a wrong assessment and evaluation of philosophy. I mean 
the attempts to claim for it an inductive character and accordingly to 
believe that it consists solely of statements of hypothetical validity. 
The idea of claiming only probability for its statements was remote 
from earlier thinkers. They would have rejected it as incompatible 
with the dignity of philosophy. In this was expressed a healthy instinct 
for the fact that philosophy must supply the ultimate support of knowl- 
edge. The reverse side of the medal is the dogma that philosophy 
supplies unconditionally true a priori axioms, which we must regard 
as an extremely unfortunate expression of this instinct, particularly 
since philosophy does not consist of statements at all. But we too be- 
lieve in the dignity of philosophy and deem incompatible with it the 
character of being uncertain and only probable; and we are happy that 
the decisive turning point makes it impossible to attribute any such 
character to it. For the concept of probability or uncertainty is simply 
not applicable to the acts of giving meaning which constitute philos- 
ophy. It is a matter of positing the meaning of statements as something 


Tht\Turmng Point in Philosophy [ 59 ] 

simply final. Either we have this meaning, and then we know what is 
meant by the statement, or we do not possess it, in which case mere 
empty words confront ns, and as yet no statement at all. There is noth- 
ing in between and there can be no talk of the probability that the 
meaning is the right one. Thus after the great turning point philosophy 
shows its decisive character even more clearly than before. 

It is only, indeed, because of this character that the conflict of 
systems can be ended. I repeat: in consequence of the insights which 
I have sketched we may today consider it as in principle already ended. 
I hope that this may become increasingly clear in the pages of this 
journal^ in the new period of its existence. 

Certainly there will still be many a rear-guard action. Certainly 
many will for centuries continue to wander further along the traditional 
paths. Philosophical writers will long continue to discuss the old 
pseudo-questions. But in the end they will no longer be listened to; 
they will come to resemble actors who continue to play for some 
time before noticing that the audience has slowly departed. Then 
it will no longer be necessary to speak of “philosophical problems” 
for one will speak philosophicaliy concerning all problems, that is: 
clearly and meaninghiUy. 


^ Sc. Erkenntnis, Ed. 


3 


The Elimination of Metaphysics 
Through Logical Analysis 

of Language 
BY RUDOLF CARNAP 
(translated by ARTHUR PAP) 


1. Introduction 

There have been many opponents of metaphysics from the Greek 
skeptics to the empiricists of the 19th century'. Criticisms of very 
diverse kinds have been set forth. Many have declared that the doc- 
trine of metaphysics is false, since it contradicts our empirical knowl- 
edge. Others have believed it to be uncertain, on the ground that its 
problems transcend the limits of human knowledge. Many anti- 
metaphysicians have declared that occupation with metaphysiciil ques- 
tions is sterile. Whether or not these questions can be answered, it is at 
any rate unnecessary^ to worry about them; let us devote ourselves 
entirely to the practical tasks which confront active men every day 
of their lives! 

The development of modern logic has made it possible to give a 
new and sharper answer to the question of the validity and justi- 
fication of metaphysics. The researches of applied logic or the theory 
of knowledge, which aim at clarifying the cognitive content of sci- 
entific statements and thereby the meanings of the terms that occur 
in the statements, by means of logical analysis, lead to a positive 
and to a negative result. The positive result is worked out in the 
domain of empirical science; the various concepts of the various 
branches of science are clarified; their formal-logical and epistemo- 
logical connections are made explicit. In the domain of metaphysics, 

This artide, originally entitled *‘Uberwindung der Metaphysik durch Logische 
Analyse der Sprache/’ appeared in Erkenntnis, Vol. H (1932). It is published here 
with the kind permission of Professor Carnap. 


[ 60 ] 


the EUmination of Metaphysics [ 61 ] 

'indiidiiig aH philosophy of value and normative theory, logical 
analysis yields the negative result that the alleged statements in this 
domain are entirely meaningless. Therewith a radical elimination of 
metaphysics is attained, which was not yet possible from the earlier 
antlmetaphysical standpoints. It is true that related ideas may be 
found already in several earlier trains of thought, e.g. those of a 
nominalistic jtind; but it is only now when the development of logic 
during recent decades provides us with a sufficiently sharp tool that 
the decisive step can be taken. 

In saying that the so-called statements of metaphysics are mean- 
ingless, we intend this word in its strictest sense. In a loose sense 
of the word a statement or a question is at times called meaningless 
if it is entirely sterile to assert or ask it. We might say this for in- 
stance about the question ‘'what is the average weight of those inhabi- 
tants of Vienna w^hose telephone number ends with ‘3’?” or about 
a statement which is quite obviously false like “in 1910 Vienna had 
6 inhabitants” or about a statement which is not just empirically, 
but logically false, a contradictory statement such as “persons A 
and B are each a year older than the other.” Such sentences are 
really meaningful, though they arc pointless or false; for it is only 
meaningful sentences that are even divisible into (theoretically) fruit- 
ful and sterile, true and false. In the strict sense, however, a sequence 
of words is meaningless if it does not. within a specified language, 
constitute a statement. It may happen that such a sequence of words 
looks like a statement at first glance; in that case we call it a pseudo- 
statement. Our thesis, now, is that logical analysis reveals the alleged 
statements of metaphysics to be pseudo-statements. 

A language consists of a vocabulaiy' and a syntax, i.e. a set of 
words which have meanings and rules of sentence formation. These 
rules indicate how sentences may be formed out of the various sorts 
of words. Accordingly, there are two kinds of pseudo-statements: 
either they contain a w^ord which is erroneously believed to have 
meaning, or the constituent words are meaningful, yet are put together 
in a counter-symtactical w^ay, so that they do not yield a meaningful 
statement. We shall show in terms of examples that pseudo-statements 
of both kinds occur in metaphysics. Later we shall have to inquire 
into the reasons that support our contention that metaphysics in its 
entirety consists of such pseudo-statements. 

2. The Significance of a Word 

A word which (within a definite language) has a meaning, is 
usually also said to designate a concept; if it only seems to have a 


I «>^i 


• 1 . RUDOLF CARNAP 

Sn? r- “ -mnlo^nccpt.” 

evere w„Si hSf ? . Ps/udo^ncept to be explained? Has TOt 

guage contain meaningless word<:‘? To hf> c, ’ traditional Ian- 
(ex«pdn. rate cases whi^ iS:-,a“.eS”S Se 

£ meaSTAnd > word freqnen.^"S5; 

sense without t^u a* Omes that a word loses its old 

arises. ^ ^ ^ pseudo-concept 

S Sn:fbe”Zj?in“'ordeTg; 

ex^L^yfaM'do™ TiT'SeTase” f"''''*'’" ••>- 

Modern science, or X XX 2 

ot the word°LM'brfi2d°Vr'thf”** riret, the syntax 

simplest sentence fnrm ; ^ts occurrence in the 

this entenS forl occurring; we call 

form for th? worf is ?' Is““', 

♦ . ^'cr>* X is <1 stone I m sentences nf thtc 

place of™V’^e?^^?v category of things occupies the 

pxace ot X, e.g. this diamond,” “this apnle ” Sernndiv fmr- 

SThe°fo2,w““°“ ^ “"‘“”‘"6 «>' word an'^answe, mn, V° ven 
(I m7sf ,“"™' fortPolated in varied w"^s 

ere dedneS frS ““ 

wha[ wndMoS Se?“"‘“‘'°"' “ ® “ I-' “"*r 

(3.) How is S to be verifiedl 
(4.) What is the meaning of S'^ 

knowledge (4) with"th«P«f ?, ^ Phraseology of the theoiy of 

ae •WtaTS’" f ‘ th-coTSn ( a , t 

tSedTxpisS “ P'ooo'tf to give elsewhere a dl 

i.e. relatims of dedudSii,?T “ ““ 

wheL:^'mTorSSS'S?f I '"oSL'-S T- 

Ptoanntg by rednetion to other wori cSro^TSnT 


■■ of Metaphysics [ 63 ] 

E.g. ‘“‘arthropodes’ are animals with segmented bodies and jointed 
legs.” Thereby the above-mentioned question for the elementary sen- 
tence form of the word ‘"arthropode,” that is for the sentence form 
‘"the thing x is an arthropode,” is answered: it has been stipulated 
that a sentence of this form is deducible from premises of the form 
“x is an animal,” ‘‘x has a segmented body,” '‘x has jointed legs,” 
and that conversely each of these sentences is deducible from the 
former sentence. By means of these stipulations about deducibility 
(in other words: about the truth-condition, about the method of veri- 
fication, about the meaning) of the elementary sentence about "'arthro- 
pode” the meaning of the word “arthropode” is fixed. In this way 
every word of the language is reduced to other words and finally to 
the words which occur in the so-called "‘observation sentences” or 
“protocol sentences.” It is through this reduction that the w^ord 
acquires its meaning. 

For our piiqi^oses we may ignore entirely tlie question concerning 
the content and form of the primary sentences (protocol sentences) 
which has not yet been definitely settled. In the theory of knowledge 
it is customary to say that the primary sentences refer to “the given”; 
but there is no unanimity on the question what it is that is given. At 
times the position is taken that sentences about the given speak of the 
simplest qualities of sense and feeling (e.g. “wami,” “blue,” “joy” 
and so forth); others incline to the view that basic sentences refer to 
total experiences and simiiarities between them; a still diflercnt 
view has it that even the basic sentences speak of things. Regardless 
of this diversity of opinion it is certain that a sequence of words has 
a meaning only if its relations of deducibility to the protocol sen- 
tences are fixed, whatever the characteristics of the protocol sen- 
tences may be; and similarly, that a word is significant only if the 
sentences in which it may occur are reducible to protocol sentences. 

Since the meaning of a word is determined by its criterion of 
application (in other words: by the relations of deducibility entered 
into by its elementary sentence-form, by its truth-conditions, by 
the method of its verification), the stipulation of the criterion takes 
away one’s freedom to decide what one wishes to “mean” by the 
word. E the word is to receive an exact meaning, nothing less than 
the criterion of application must be given; but one cannot, on the 
other hand, give more than the criterion of application, for the 
latter is a sufficient determination of meaning. The meaning is im- 
plicitly contained in the criterion; all that remains to be done is to 
make the meaning explicit. 

Let us suppose, by way of illustration, that someone invented 


I 64 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

the new word “teavy” and maintained that there are things which 
are teavy and things which are not teavy. In order to learn the 
meaning of this word, we ask him about its criterion of application: 
how is one to ascertain in a concrete case whether a given thing is 
teavy or not? Let us suppose to begin with that we get no answer 
from him: there are no empirical signs of teavyness, he says. In 
that case we would deny the legitimacy of using this word. If the 
person who uses the word says that all the same there are things 
which are teavy and there are things which are not teavy, only it 
remains for the weak, finite intellect of man an eternal secret which 
things are teavy and which are not, we shall regard this as empty 
verbiage. But perhaps he will assure us that he means, after all, 
something by the word “teavy.” But from this we only learn the 
psychological fact that he associates some kind of images and feel- 
ings with the word. The word does not acquire a meaning through 
such associations. If no criterion of application for the word is 
stipulated, then nothing is asserted by the sentences in which it 
occurs, they are but pseudo-statements. 

Secondly, take the case when we are given a criterion of appli- 
cation for a new word, say “toovy”; in particular, let the sentence 
“this thing is too\y” be true if and only if the thing is quadrangular (It 
is irrelevant in this context whether the criterion is '"explicitly 'stated 
or whether we derive it by observing the affirmative and the nega- 
tive uses of the word). Then we will say: the word “tooyj^” is synon- 
ymous with the word “quadrangular.” And we will not allow its 
users to tell us that nevertheless they “intended” something else by 
it than “quadrangular”; that though every quadrangular thing is also 
toov>' and conversely, this is only because quadrangularity is the 
visible manifestation of toovyness, but that the latter itself is a 
hidden, not itself observable property. We would reply that after 
the criterion of application has been fixed, the synonymy of “toovy” 
and “quadrangular” is likewise fixed, and that we are no further 
at liberty to “intend” this or that by the word. 

Let us briefly summarize the result of our analysis. Let “a” be 
any word and “S(a)” the elementary sentence in which it occurs. 
Then the sufficient and necessary condition for “a” being meaningful 
may be given by each of the following formulations, which ulti- 
mately say the same thing: 

1. The empirical criteria for a are known. 

2. It has been stipulated from what protocol sentences “S(a)” 
is deducihle. 


” EUmxnation of Metaphysics 

3, The truth-conditions for “S(a)” are fixed. 

4, The method of verification of “S(a)” is known.^ 


[65] 


3. Metaphysical Words Without Meaning 

Many words of metaphysics, now, can be shown not to fulfill the 
atx 5 ve requirement, and therefore to be devoid of meaning. 

Let us take as an example the metaphysical term ‘"principle” 
(in the sense of principle of being, not principle of knowledge or 
axiom). Various metaphysicians offer an answer to the question 
which is the (highest) “principle of the world” (or of “things,” of 
“existence,” of “being”), e.g. water, number, form, motion, life, the 
spirit, the idea, the unconscious, activity, the good, and so forth. In 
order to discover the meaning of the word “principle” in this meta- 
physical question we must ask the metaphysician under what con- 
ditions a statement of the form “x is the principle of y” would be 
true and under what conditions it would be false, in other words: 
we ask for the criteria of application or for the definition of the word 
“principle.” The metaphysician replies approximately as follows: 
“x is the principle of y” is to mean “y arises out of x,” “the being 
of y rests on the being of x,” “y exists by virtue of x” and so forth. 
But these words are ambiguous and vague. Frequently they have a 
clear meaning; e.g., we say of a thing or process y that it “arises out 
of’ X when we observe that things or processes of kind x arc fre- 
quently or invariably followed by things or processes of kind y (causal 
connection in the sense of a lawful succession). But the metaphysician 
tells us that he does not mean this empirically observable relationship. 
For in that case his metaphysical theses would be merely empirical 
propositions of the same kind as those of physics. The expression 
“arising from” is not to mean here a relation of temporal and causal 
sequence, which is what the word ordinarily means. Yet, no criterion 
is specified for any other meaning. Consequently, the alleged “meta- 
physical” meaning, which the word is supposed to have here in con- 
trast to the mentioned empirical meaning, does not exist. If we 
reflect on the original meaning of the word “principium” (and of the 
corresponding Greek word apx^^), we notice the same development. 
The word is explicitly deprived of its original meaning “beginning”; 
it is not supposed to mean the temporally prior any more, but the 
prior in some other, specifically metaphysical, respect. The criteria 
for this “metaphysical respect,” however, are lacking. In both cases, 

1. For the logical and epistemological conception which underlies our exposition, 
but can only briefly be intimated here, cf. Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philoso- 
pkicus, 1922, and Carnap, Der logische Aufbau der Welt, 1928. 


f 3 RUDOLF CARNAP 

then, the word has been deprived of its earlier meaning without bem<r 
given a new meaning; there remains the word as an empty shell. From 
an earlier period of significant use, it is still associatively connected 
with various mental images; these in turn get associated with new 
mental images and feelings in the new context of usage. But the word 
does not thereby become meaningful; and it remains meaningless 
as long as no method of verification can be described. 

AnoAer example is the word “God.” Here we must, apart from 
the variations of its usage within each domain, distinguish the 
linguistic usage in three different contexts or historical epochs, which 
how:iver overlap temporally. In its mythological use the word has 
a clear meaning. It, or parallel words in other languages, is some- 
dmes used to denote physical beings which are enthroned on Mount 
Olympus, in Heaven or in Hades, and which are endowed with 
power, wisdom, goodness and happiness to a greater or lesser extent. 
Sometimes the word also refers to spiritual beings which, indeed^ 
do not have manlike bodies, yet manifest themselves nevertheless’ 
somehow m the things or processes of the visible world and are 
therefore empirically verifiable. In its metaphysical use, on the other 
hand, the word “God” refers to something beyond experience. The 
word is deliberately divested of its reference to a physical being or to 
a spiritual being that is immanent in the physical. And as it is not 
given a new meaning, it becomes meaningless. To be sure, it often 
lookj as though the word God had a meaning even in metaphysics. 
But the definitions which are set up prove on closer inspection to be 
pseudo-definitions. They lead either to logicaUy illegitimate combina- 
tions of words (of which we shall treat later) or to other meta- 
physical words (e.g. “primordial basis,” “the absolute,” “the uncon- 
ditioned,” “the autonomous,” “the self-dependent” and so forth), 
but in no case to the truth-conditions of its elementary sentences.’ 
In the case of this word not even the first requirement of loaic is met, 
that is the requirement to specify its sy^ntax, i.e. the form of its 
occurrence in elementary sentences. An elementary sentence would 
hvre have to be of the form x is a God”; yet, the metaphysician 
either rejects this form entirely without substituting another, or if 
he accepts it he neglects to indicate the syntactical category 'of the 
variable x. (Categories are, for example, material things, properties 
of things, relations between things, numbers etc.). 

The theological usage of the word “God” falls between its mytho- 
logical and its metaphysical usage. There is no distinctive meaning 
here, but an oscillation from one of the mentioned two uses to the 
other. Several theologians have a clearly empirical (in our termin- 


- 'fhe''Bimlnation of Metaphysics [ 67 ] 

ology, ‘^mytliologicar’) concept of God. In this case there are no 
psendo-statements; but the disadvantage for the theologian lies in 
the circumstance that according to this interpretation the statements 
of theology are empirical and hence are subject to the judgment of 
empirical science. The linguistic usage of other theologians is clearly 
metaphysical. Others again do not speak in any definite way, whether 
this is because they follow now this, now that linguistic usage, or 
because they express themselves in terms whose usage is not clearly 
classifiable since it tends towards both sides. 

Just like the examined examples ‘"principle” and ""God,” most of 
the other specifically metaphysical terms are devoid of meaning, e.g. 
“the Idea,” “the Absolute,” ""the Unconditioned,” “the Infinite,” 
“the being of being,” “non-being,” "‘thing in itself,” “absolute spirit,” 
“objective spirit,” “essence,” “being-in-itself,” “being-in-and-for- 
itseif,” “emanation,” “manifestation,” “articulation,” “the Ego,” 
“the non-Ego,” etc. These expressions are in the same boat with 
“teavy,” our previously fabricated example. The metaphysician tells 
us that empirical truth-conditions cannot be specified; if he adds that 
nevertheless he “means” something, we know that this is merely an 
allusion to associated images and feelings which, however, do not 
bestow a meaning on the word. The alleged statements of meta- 
physics which contain such words have no sense, assert nothing, are 
mere pseudo-statements. Into the explanation of their historical origin 
we shall inquire later. 

4. The Significance of a Sentence 

So far we have considered only those pseudo-statements which 
contain a meaningless word. But there is a second kind of pseudo- 
statement. They consist of meaningful words, but the words are put 
together in such a way that nevertheless no meaning results. The 
syntax of a language specifies which combinations of words are 
admissible and which inadmissible. The grammatical syntax of 
natural languages, however, does not fulfill the task of elimination of 
senseless combinations of words in all cases. Let us take as examples 
the following sequences of words: 

1. “Caesar is and” 

2. “Caesar is a prime number” 

The word sequence (1) is formed countersyntacticaliy; the rules 
of syntax require that the third position be occupied, not by a 
conjunction, but by a predicate, hence by a noun (with article) or by 
an adjective. The word sequence “Caesar is a general,” e.g., is 


[ 68 ] , RUDOLF CARNAP 

formed in accordance with the rules of syntax. It is a meaningful 
word sequence, a genuine sentence. But, now, word sequence (2) is 
Ekewise syntactically correct, for it has the same grammatical form as 
the sentence just mentioned. Nevertheless (2) is meaningless. ‘Trime 
number” is a predicate of numbers; it can be neither affirmed nor 
denied of a person. Since (2) looks Eke a statement yet is not a 
statement, does not assert anything, expresses neither a true nor a 
false proposition, we call this word sequence a '‘pseudo-statement.” 
The fact that the rules of grammatical syntax are not violated easEy 
seduces one at first glance into the erroneous opinion that one still 
has to do with a statement, albeit a false one. But “a is a prime 
number” is false if and only if a is divisible by a natural number 
different from a and from 1 ; evidently it is Elicit to put here "Caesar” 
for "a.” This example has been so chosen that the nonsense is 
easily detectable. Many so-caEed statements of metaphysics are not 
so easily recognized to be pseudo-statements. The fact that natural 
languages allow the formation of meaningless sequences of words 
without violating the rules of grammar, indicates that grammatical 
syntax is, from a logical point of view, inadequate, li grammatical 
syntax corresponded exactly to logical syntax, pseudo-statements could 
not arise. If grammatical syntax differentiated not only the word- 
categories of nouns, adjectives, verbs, conjunctions etc., but within 
each of these categories made the funher distinctions that are 
logically indispensable, then no pseudo-statements could be formed. 
If, e.g., nouns were grammatically subdivided into several kinds of 
words, according as they designated properties of physical objects, 
of numbers etc., then the words "general” and ‘"prime number” 
would belong to grammatically different word-categories, and (2) 
would be just as linguistically incorrect as (1). In a correctly con- 
structed language, therefore, all nonsensical sequences of words 
would be of the kind of example (1). Considerations of grammar 
would already eliminate them as it were automatically; i.e. in order 
to avoid nonsense, it would be unnecessary to pay attention to 
the meanings of the individual words over and above their syn- 
tactical type (their "syntactical category^” e.g. thing, property 
of things, relation betw^een things, number, property of numbers, 
relation between numbers, and so forth). It foEows that if our 
thesis that the statements of metaphysics are pseudo-statements 
is justifiable, then metaphysics could not even be expressed in a 
logically constructed language. This is the great phEosophical im- 
portance of the task, which at present occupies the logicians, of 
building a logical syntax. 







Jhe Elimination of Metaphysics [ 69 ] 

5, Metaphysical Pseudo-statements 

Let us now take a look at some examples of metaphysical pseudo- 
statements of a kind where the violation of logical syntax is especially 
obvious, though they accord with historical-grammatical syntax. We 
select a few sentences from that metaphysical school which at present 
exerts the strongest influence in Germany.^ 

“What is to be investigated is being only and — nothing else; 
being alone and further — nothing; solely being, and beyond being — 
nothing. What about this Nothing? . . . Does the Nothing exist only 
because the Not, i.e. the Negation, exists? Or is it the other way 
around? Does Negation and the Not exist only because the Nothing 
exists? . . . We assert: the Nothing is prior to the Not and the Nega- 
tion. . . , Where do we seek the Nothing? How do we find the 
Nothing. . . . We know the Nothing. . . . Anxiety reveals the Nothing. 

. . . That for which and because of which we were anxious, was 
‘really’ — nothing. Indeed: the Nothing itself — as such — was present, 

. . . What about this Nothing? — The Nothing itself nothings^ 

In order to show that the possibility of forming pseudo-statements 
is based on a logical defect of language, wc set up the schema bclow^ 
The sentences under I are grammatically as well as logically im- 
peccable, hence meaningful. The sentences under II (excepting B3) 
are in grammatical respects perfectly analogous to those under I, 
Sentence form 11 A (as question and answer) does not, indeed, satisfy 
the requirements to be imposed on a logically correct language. But 
it is nevertheless meaningful, because it is translatable into correct 
language. This is shown by sentence IIIA, which has the same mean- 
ing as IIA. Sentence form JIA then proves to be undesirable because 
w^e can be led from it, by means of grammatically faultless operations, 
to the meaningless sentence forms IIB, which are taken from the 
above quotation. These forms cannot even be constructed in the 
correct language of Column HI. Nonetheless, their nonsensicality is 
not obvious at first glance, because one is easily deceived by the 
analogy with the meaningful sentences IB. The fault of our language 
identified here lies, therefore, in the circumstance that, in contrast 
to a logically correct language, it admits of the same grammatical 
form for meaningful and meaningless word sequences. To each 
sentence in words we have added a corresponding formula in the 

2. The following quotations (original italics) are taken from M. Heidegger, 
Was 1st Metaphysik? 1929. We could just as well have selected passages from any 
other of the numerous metaphysicians of the present or of the past; yet the selected 
passages seem to us to illustrate our thesis especially well. 


r ^ RUDOLF CARNAP 

notation of symbolic logic; these formulae facilitate recoanition of 
the undesirable analogy between lA and HA and therewTth of the 
origin of the meaningless constructions HB. 


/. 

Meaningful 
Sentences of 
Ordinary 
Language 

A. What is outside? 

Ou(?) 

Rain is outside 

Ou(r) 


n. 

Transition from 
Sense to 
Nonsense in 
Ordinary 
Language 

A. What is outside? 

Ou(?) 

Nothing is outside 
Ou(no) 


111 , 

Logically 

Correct 

Language 

A. There is nothing 
(does not exist any- 
thing) which is 
outside. 

-^(Hx) .Ou(x) 


B. What about this rain? 
(i.e. what does the 
rain do? or: what 
else can be said 
about this rain? 

?(r) 


B. “What about this 
Nothing?” ?(no) 


B. None of these fonns 
can even be 
constructed. 


I. W^e know the rain 1. “We seek the 
K(r) Nothing” 

“We find the 
Nothing” 
“We know the 
Nothing” 

K(no) 


2. “The Nothing 
nothings” 

No(no) 

3. “The Nothing 
exists only 
because . . .” 

Ex(no) 

On closer inspection of the pseudo-statements under IIB, w^e also 
find some differences. The construction of sentence (1) is simply 
based on the mistake of employing the word “nothing” as a noun, 
because it is customary in ordinary language to use it in this form in 
order to construct a negative existential statement (see HA). In 
a correct language, on the other hand, it is not a particular name 
but a certain logical form of the sentence that serves this purpose 


2. The rain rains 
R(r) 



> . The Elimination of Metaphysics [ M 

(see IIIA). Sentence IIB2 adds something new, viz. the fabrication 
of the meaningless word “to nothing.” This sentence, therefore, is 
senseless for a twofold reason. We pointed out before that the mean- 
ingless words of metaphysics usually owe their origin to the fact 
that a meaningfui word is deprived of its meaning through its meta- 
phorical use in metaphysics. But here we confront one of those rare 
cases where a new word is introduced which never had a meaning 
to begin with. Likewise sentence IIB3 must be rejected for two rea- 
sons. In respect of the error of using the word “nothing” as a noun, 
it is like the previous sentences. But in addition it involves a contra- 
diction. For even if it were admissible to introduce “nothing” as 
a name or description of an entity, still the existence of this entity 
would be denied in its very definition, whereas sentence (3) goes on 
to affirm its existence. This sentence, therefore, would be contradic- 
tory, hence absurd, even if it were not already meaningless. 

In view of the gross logical errors which we find in sentences 
IBB, we might be led to conjecture that perhaps the word “nothing” 
has in Heidegger’s treatise a meaning entirely different from the 
customary one. And this presumption is further strengthened as we 
go on to read there that anxiety reveals the Nothing, that the Nothing 
itself is present as such in anxiety. For here the word “notliing” seems 
to refer to a certain emotional constitution, possibly of a religious 
sort, or something or other that underlies such emotions. If such 
were the case, then the mentioned logical errors in sentences IIB 
would not be committed. But the first sentence of the quotation 
at the beginning of this section proves that this interpretation is not 
possible. The combination of “only” and “nothing else” shows un- 
mistakably that the word “nothing” here has the usual meaning of 
a logical particle that sei*ves for the formulation of a negative exis- 
tential statement. This introduction of the word “nothing” is then 
immediately followed by the leading question of tlie treatise: “What 
about this Nothing?”. 

But our doubts as to a possible misinterpretation get completely 
dissolved as we note that the author of the treatise is clearly aware 
of the conflict between his questions and statements, and logic. 
''Question and answer in regard to the Nothing are equally absurd 
in themselves. . . . The fundamental rule of thinking commonly 
appealed to, the law of prohibited contradiction, general logic/ 
destroys this question.” All the worse for logic! We must abolish its 
sovereignty: “If thus the power of the understanding in the field of 
questions concerning Nothing and Being is broken, then the fate of 
the sovereignty of logic’ within philosophy is thereby decided as 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


[ 72 ] 

well. The vtry idea of ‘logic’ dissolves in the whirl of a more basic 
qiiestioning.” But will sober science condone the whirl of counter- 
logical questioning? To this question too there is a ready answer: 
‘"The alleged sobriety and superiority of science becomes ridiculous 
if it does not take the Nothing seriously.” Thus we find here a good 
confirmation of our thesis; a metaphysician himself here states that 
his questions and answers are irreconcilable with logic and the sci- 
entific way of thinking. 

The difference between our thesis and that of the earlier anti- 
fnetaphysicians should now be clear. We do not regard metaphysics 
as “mere speculation” or “fairy tales.” The statements of a fair\^ 
tale do not conflict with logic, but only with experience; they are 
perfectly meaningful, although false. Metaphysics is not ''supersti- 
tion”; it is possible to believe true and false propositions, but not 
to believe meaningless sequences of v^ords. Metaphysical statements 
are not even acceptable as "working hypotheses"; for an h}'pothesis 
must be capable of .entering into relations of deducibility with (true 
or false) empirical statements, which is just what pseudo-statements 
cannot do. 

With reference to the so-called limitation of hmnan knowledge 
an attempt is sometimes made to save metaphysics by raising the 
following objection: metaphysical statements are not. indeed, veri- 
fiable by man nor by any other finite being; nevertli^less they might 
be construed as conjectures about the answers which a being with 
higher or even perfect powers of knowledge would make to our 
cjuestions, and as such conjectures they would, after all, be mean- 
ingful. To counter this objection, let us consider the following. If 
the meaning of a word cannot be specified, or if the sequence of 
words does not accord with the rules of syntax, then one has not 
even asked a question. {'Just think of the pesudo-quesnons: "Is this 
table teavy?”, “is the number 7 holy?”, “which numbers are darker, 
the even or the odd ones?”). Where there is no quesiion, not even 
an omniscient being can give an answer. Now the objecior may say: 
jnst as one who can see may communicate new knowledge to the 
blind, so a higher being might perhaps communicate to us meta- 
physical knowledge, e.g. whether the visible world is the manifesta- 
tion of a spirit. Here we must reflect on the meaning of “new knowl- 
edge,” It is, indeed, conceivable that we might encounter animals 
who tell us about a new sense. If these beings were to prove to us 
Fermat’s theorem or were to invent a new physical instrument or 
were to establish a hitherto unknown law of nature, then our knowl- 
edge would be increased with their help. For this son of thing we 


pl0: 


The Elimination of Metaphysics [ ] 

' can test, jnst the way even a blind man can understand and test the 
whole of physics (and therewith any statement made by those who 
can see). But if those hypothetical beings tell us something which 
we cannot verify, then we cannot understand it either; in that case 
no information has been communicated to us, but mere verbal sounds 
devoid of meaning though possibly associated with images. It fol- 
lows that our knowledge can only be quantitatively enlarged by 
other beings, no matter whether they know more or less or every- 
thing, but no knowledge of an essentially different kind can be 
added. What we do not know for certain, we may come to know with 
greater certainty through the assistance of other beings; but what 
is unintelligible, meaningless for us, cannot become meaningful 
through someone else’s assistance, however vast his knowledge might 
be. Therefore no god and no devil can give us metaphysical knowledge. 



6. Meaninglessness of ai.l Metaphysics 

The examples of metaphysical statements which we have anal- 
yzed were all taken from just one treatise. But our results apply with 
equal validity, in part even in verbally identical ways, to other meta- 
physical systems. That treatise is completely in the right in citing 
approvingly a statement by Hegel (“pure Being and pure Nothing, 
therefore, are one and the same”). The metaphysics of Hegel has 
exactly the same logical character as this modern system of meta- 
physics. And the same holds for the rest of the metaphysical systems, 
though the kind of phraseology and therewith the kind of logical 
errors that occur in them deviate more or less from the kind that 
occurs in the examples we discussed. 

It should not be necessary^ here to adduce further examples of 
specific metaphysica! sentences in diverse systems and submit them 
to analysis. Wc confine ourselves to an indication of the most fre- 
quent kinds of errors. 

Perhaps the majority of the logical mistakes that are committed 
when pseudo-statements are made, are based on the logical faults 
infecting the use of the word “to be” in our language (and of the 
corresponding words in other languages, at least in most European 
languages). The first fault is the ambiguity of the word “to be.” It 
is sometimes used as copula prefixed to a predicate (“I am hungry”), 
sometimes to designate existence (‘T am”). This mistake is ag- 
gravated by the fact that metaphysicians often are not clear about 
this ambiguity. The second fault lies in the form of the verb in its 
second meaning, the meaning of existence. The verbal form feigns 







RUDOLF CARNAP 


^ ] 

% v'® where there is none. To be sure, it has been known for 

that existence is not a property (cf. Kant’s refutation 
proof of the existence of God). But it was not 
^ ^ modem logic that full consistency on this point 

the syntactical form in which modern logic introduces 






existence is such that it cannot, like a predicate, be ap- 


^igns for objects, but only to predicates (cf. e.g. sentence 
V above table). Most metaphysicians since antiquity have 
themselves to be seduced into pseudo-statements by the 
c ^ therewith the predicative form of the word “to be,” e.g. 

>od is.” 

f \ illustration of this error in Descartes’ “cogito, ergo 

ijts disregard here the material objections that have been 
^inst the premise — viz. whether the sentence “I think” ade- 


5 

th(x 




"^^presses the intended state of affairs or contains perhaps an 




-and consider the tvv'o sentences only from the formal- 


witnoui preaicate; maeea, uescanes' ”i am ' nas always 
th^ in this sense. But in that case this sentence violates 

^^■'tnentioned logical mle that existence caii be predicated 
^^junction with a predicate, not in conjunction with a name 
' proper name) ' • . ^ . 


of view. We notice at once two essential logical mis- 
first lies in the conclusion “I am.” The verb “to be” is 
fflly meant in the sense of existence here; for a copula can- 
without predicate; indeed, Descartes’ “I am” has always 


An existential statement does not have 


exists” (as in “I am,” i.e. “I exist”), but “there exists 
K of such and such a kind.” The second error lies in the 

^5?^\w^^from ‘T think” to ‘T exist.” If from the statement “F(a)” 


property P”) an existential statement is to be deduced, 


V \ \ l^^tter can assert existence only with respect to the predicate 
respect to the subject a of the premise. What follows 
. a European” is not “I exist,” but “a European exists.” 
from “I think” is not “I am” but “there exists some- 
^^^'^Uhinks.” 

Circumstance that our languages express existence by a verb 
“to exist”) is not in itself a logical fg 


Col 


''hie 


lav^ 

;Ot 


fault; it is only inap- 


dangerous. The verbal form easily misleads us into the 


^v^l^tion that existence is a predicate. One then arrives at such 


^ V ^correct and hence senseless modes of expression as were 

a ^ J T t_ £ CeXT_x TTV-* _ » 


Nned. Likewise such forms as “Being” or “Not-Being,’ 


time immemorial have played a great role in metaphysics, 
^ame origin. In a logically correct language such forms can- 


constructed. It appears that in the Latin and the German 


-'The Bimnation of Metaphysics [ ] 

/*' laliigiiages the forms “ens” or ‘‘das Seiende” were, perhaps under the 
seductive influence of the Greek example, introduced specifically for 
BSC by metaphysicians; in this way the language deteriorated logically 
whereas the addition was believed to represent an improvement. 

Another very frequent violation of logical syntax is the so-called 
*'type confusion"' of concepts. While the previously mentioned mis- 
take consists in the predicative use of a symbol with non-predicative 
meaning, in this case a predicate is, indeed, used as predicate yet as 
predicate of a different type. We have here a violation of the rules 
of the so-called theory of types. An artificial example is the sentence 
we discussed earlier: “Caesar is a prime number.” Names of persons 
and names of numbers belong to different logical types, and so do 
accordingly predicates of persons (e.g. “general”) and predicates of 
numbers (“priine number”). The error of type confusion is, unlike 
the previously discussed usage of the verb “to be,” not the preroga- 
tive of metaphysics but already occurs veiy often in conversational 
language also. But here it rarely leads to nonsense. The typical 
ambiguity of words is here of such a kind that it can be easily removed. 

Example: 1. “Tnis table is larger than that.” 2. “The height of this table 
is larger than the height of that table.” Here the word “larger” is used in 
(1) for a relation bervveen objects, in (2) for a relation between num- 
bers, hence for two distinct syntactical categories. The mistake is 
here unimportant; it could, e.g., be eliminated by writing “larger!” and 
“larger2”; “largerl” is then defined in terms of “larger2” by declaring 
statement form (1 » to be synonymous with (2) (and others of a similar 
kind). 

Since the confusion of types causes no harm in conversational 
language, it is usually ignored entirely. This is, indeed, expedient for 
the ordinar}’ use of language, but has had unfortunate consequences 
in metaphysics. Here the conditioning by everyday language has led 
to confusions of types which, unlike those in everyday language, are 
no longer translatable into logically correct form. Pseudo-statements 
of this kind are encountered in especially large quantity, e.g., in the 
writings of Hegel and Heidegger. The latter has adopted many pe- 
culiarities of the Hegelian idiom along with their logical faults (e.g. 
predicates which should be applied to objects of a certain sort are 
instead applied to predicates of these objects or to “being” or to 
“existence” or to a relation between these objects). 

Having found that many metaphysical statements are meaning- 
less, we confront the question whether there is not perhaps a core 
of meaningful statements in metaphysics which would remain after 
elinmiation of all the meaningless ones. 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


[76] 

Indeed, the results we have obtained so far might give rise to 
the view that there are many dangers of falling into nonsense in 
metaphysics, and that one must accordingly endeavor to avoid these 
traps with great care if one wants to do metaphysics. But actually 
the situation is that meaningful metaphysical statements are impos- 
sible. This follows from the task which metaphysics sets itself: to 
discover and formulate a kind of knowledge which is not accessible 
to empirical science. 

We have seen earlier that the meaning of a statement lies in the 
method of its verification. A statement asserts only so much as is 
verifiable with respect to it. Therefore a sentence can be used only 
to assert an empirical proposition, if indeed it is used to assert any- 
thing at all. If something were to lie, in principle, beyond possible 
experience, it could be neither said nor thought nor asked, 

(Meaningful) statements are divided into the following kinds. 
First there are statements which are true solely by virtue of their 
form ('‘tautologies” according to Wittgenstein; they correspond ap- 
proximately to Kant’s “analytic judgments”). They say nothing 
about reality. The formulae of logic and mathematics are of this 
kind. They are not themselves factual statements, but serve for the 
transformation of such statements. Secondly there are the negations of 
such statements {''contradictions''). They are self-contradictory, 
hence false by virtue of their form. With respect" to all other state- 
ments the decision about truth or falsehood lies in the protocol sen- 
tences. They are therefore (true or false) empirical statements and 
belong to the domain of empirical science. Any statement one desires 
to construct which does not fall within these categories becomes 
automatically meaningless. Since metaphysics does not want to assert 
analytic propositions, nor to fall within the domain of empirical 
science, it is compelled to employ words for which no criteria of 
application are specified and which are therefore devoid of sense, 
or else to combine meaningful words in such a way that neither an 
analytic (or contradictory) statement nor an empirical statement is 
produced. In either case pseudo-statements are the inevitable product. 

Logical analysis, then, pronounces the verdict of meaningless- 
ness on any alleged knowledge that pretends to reach above or behind 
experience. This verdict hits, in the first place, any speculative meta- 
physics, any alleged knowledge by pure thinking or by pure intuition 
that pretends to be able to do without experience. But the verdict 
equally applies to the kind of metaphysics which, starting from ex- 
perience, wants to acquire knowledge about that which transcends 
experience by means of special inferences (e.g, the neo-vitalist thesis 



'''Yhe Elimination of Metaphysics [ 77 ] 

of the directive presence of an “entelechy" in organic processes, which 
supposedly cannot be understood in terms of physics; the question 
concerning the ‘'essence of causaiity/' transcending the ascertain- 
ment of certain regularities of succession; the talk about the ‘‘thing 
in itself’). Further, the same judgment must be passed on all philos- 
ophy of norms, or philosophy of value, on any ethics or esthetics as 
a normative discipline. For the objective validity of a value or norm 
is (even on the view of the philosophers of value) not empirically 
verifiable nor deducible from empirical statements; hence it cannot 
be asserted (in a meaningful statement) at aD. In other words: Either 
empirical criteria are indicated for the use of ‘‘good” and “beauti- 
ful” and the rest of the predicates that are employed in the normative 
sciences, or they are not. In the first case, a statement containing 
such a predicate turns into a factual judgment, but not a value judg- 
ment; in the second case, it becomes a pseudo-statement. It is alto- 
gether impossible to make a statement that expresses a value judgment. 

Finally, the verdict of meaninglessness also hits those meta- 
physical movements which are usually called, improperly, epistemo- 
logical movements, that is realism (insofar as it claims to say more 
than the empirical fact that the sequence of events exhibits a certain 
regularity, which makes the application of the inductive method pos- 
sible) and its opponents: subjective idealism, solipsism, phenomenal- 
ism, and positivism (in the earlier sense). 

But what, then, is left over for philosophy, if all statements what- 
ever that assert something are of an empirical nature and belong to 
factual science? What remains is not statements, nor a theory, nor 
a system, but only a method: the method of logical analysis. The 
foregoing discussion has illustrated the negative application of this 
method: in that context it serves to eliminate meaningless words, 
meaningless pseudo-statements. In its positive use it serves to clarify 
meaningful concepts and propositions, to lay logical foundations for 
factual science and for mathematics. The negative application of the 
method is necessar}' and important in the present historical situation. 
But even in its present practice, the positive application is more 
fertile. We cannot here discuss it in greater detail. It is the indicated 
task of logical analysis, inquir}^ into logical foundations, that is meant 
by ''scientific philosophy'' in contrast to metaphysics. 

The question regarding the logical character of the statements 
which we obtain as the result of a logical analysis, e.g. the state- 
ments occurring in this and other logical papers, can here be an- 
swered only tentatively: such statements are partly analytic, partly 
empirical. For these statements about statements and parts of state- 


if 


■■ 'I i'i' 

lii I 


jli ! 








[ 78 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

ments belong in pure metalogic (e.g. “a sequence consisting 

of the existence-sy^^t>oi and a noun, is not a sentence”), in part 
to descriptive word sequence at such and such 

a place in such aXtd such a book is meaningless”). Metalogic will 
be discussed eisewb^^^- ^Iso be shown there that the metalogic 

wiiich speaks about the sentences of a given language can be for- 
mulated in that vety language itself. 

7. Metaphysi<7^ Expression of 

AN Attitude toward Life 

Our claim that the statements of metaphysics are entirely mean- 
ingless, that they do not assert anything, will leave even those who 
agree intellectually our results with a painful feeling of strange- 
ness: how could it explained that so many men in ail ages and 
nations, among thoni eminent minds, spent so much energ}', nay 
veritable fervor, oU metaphysics if the latter consisted of nothing 
but mere words, nonsensically juxtaposed? And how could one ac- 
count for the fact tb^t metaphysical books have exerted such a strong 
influence on readers up to the present day, if they contained not even 
errors, but nothing ut all? These doubts are justified since metaphysics 
does indeed have a content; only it is not theoretical content. The 
(pseudo) statements of metaphysics do not serve for the description 
of states of affairs, neither existing ones (in that case they would be 
true statements) nor non-existing ones (in that case they v/ould be 
at least false statements). They serve for the expression 'of the gen- 
eral attitude of a parson towards life (“Lebenseinstellung, Lebens- 
gefiiiil”)- 

Perhaps we may assume that metaphysics originated from myth- 
ology^- The child is ungry at the ‘'wicked table” which hurt him. 
Primitive man endeavors to conciliate the threatening demon of 
earthquakes, or he v/orships the deity of the fertile rains in gratitude. 
Here we confront personifications of natural phenomena, which are 
the quasi-poetic cf man’s emotional relationship to his 

environment. The heritage of mythology is bequeathed on the one 
hand to poetry, whiob produces and intensifies the effects of myth- 
ology on life in a dcli^oidtc way; on the other hand, it is handed down 
to theology, which develops mythology into a system. Which, now, 
is the historical role metaphysics? Perhaps we may regard it as a 
substitute for theology systematic, conceptual think- 

ing. The (supposedly) transcendent sources of knowledge of theol- 
ogy axe here replaoed by natural, yet supposedly trans-empirical 










[ 79 ] 

_ inspection the same content as that 

of iii34liology is here still recognizable behind the repeatedl}^ varied 
dreeing: we find that metaphysics also arises from the need to give 
expression to a man’s attitude in life, his emotional and volitional 
reaction to the environment, to society, to the tasks to which he 
devotes himself, to the misfortunes that befall him. TMs attitude 
mamfests itself, unconsciously as a rule, in everything a man does 
or says. It also impresses itself on his facial features, perhaps even 
on the character of his gait. Many people, now, feel a desire to 
create over and above these manifestations a special expression of 
their attitude, through which it might become visible in a more suc- 
cinct and penetrating way. If they have artistic talent they are'- able 
to express themselves by producing a work of art. Many writers 
have already clarified the way in which the basic attitude is mani- 
fested through the style and manner of a work of art (e.g. Dilthey 
and his students). [In this connection the term “world view*’ (‘“Welt- 
anschauung”) is often used; we prefer to avoid it because of its 
ambiguity, which blurs the difference between attitude and theory, 
a difference which is of decisive importance for our analysis.] What 
is here essential for our considerations is only the fact that art is an 
adequate, metaphysics an inadequate means for the expression of ti>e 
basic attitude. Of course, there need be no intrinsic objection to one’s 
using any means of expression one likes. But in the case of meta- 
physics we find this situation: through the form of its works it pre- 
tends to be something that it is not. Ttie form in question is that 
of a system of statements which are apparently related as premisCvS 
and conclusions, that is, the form of a theory^ In this way the fiction 
of theoretical content is generated, w'hereas, as we have seen, there 
is no such content. It is not only the reader, but the metaphysician 
himself who suffers from the illusion that the metaphysical state- 
ments say something, describe states of affairs. The metaphysician 
believes that he travels in territory^ in which truth and falsehood are 
at stake. In reality, however, he has not asserted anything, but only 
expressed something, like an artist. That the metaphysician is thus 
deluding himself cannot be inferred from the fact that he selects 
language as the medium of expression and declarative sentences as 
the form of expression; for lyrical poets do the same without suc- 
cumbing to self-delusion. But the metaphysician supports his state- 
ments by arguments, he claims assent to their content, he polenncizes 
against metaphysicians of divergent persuasion by attempting to 
refute their assertions in his treatise. Lyrical poets, on the other hand, 
do not try to refute in their poem the statements in a poem by some 


fhk EUminatian of Metaphysics 
. ' cjrtiirces of knowledge. On closer 



j- gQ ] RU!X)LF CARNAP 

Other lyrical poet; for they know they are in the domain of art and 
not in the domain of theory. 

Perhaps music is the purest means of expression of the basic 
attitude because it is entirely free from any reference to objects. The 
harmonious feeling or attitude, which the metaphysician tries to ex- 
press in a monistic system, is more clearly expressed in the music 
of Mozart. And when a metaphysician gives verbal expression to 
his dualistic-heroic attitude towards life in a dualistic system, is it not 
perhaps because he lacks the ability of a Beethoven to express this 
attitude in an adequate medium? Metaphysicians are musicians with- 
out musical ability. Instead they have a strong inclination to work 
within the medium of the theoretical, to connect concepts and 
thouglits. Now, instead of activating, on the one hand, this inclina- 
tion in the domain of science, and satisfying, on the other hand, the 
nec^d for expression in art, the metaphysician confuses the two and 
produces a structure which achieves nothing for knowledge and some- 
thing inadequate for the expression of attitude. 

Our conjecture that metaphysics is a substitute, albeit an inade- 
quate one, for art, seems to be further confirmed by the fact that 
the metaphysician who perhaps had artistic talent to the highest 
degree, viz. Nietzsche, almost entirely avoided the errpr of that con- 
fusion. A large part of his work has predominantly empirical con- 
tent. We find there, for instance, historical analyses of specific artistic 
p>henomena, or an historical-psychological analysis of morals. In the 
work, however, in which he expresses most strongly that which others 
express through metaphysics or ethics, in Thus Spake Zarathustra, 
he does not choose the misleading tlieoretical form, but openly the 
form of art, of poetr>^ 


REMARKS BY THE AUTHOR (1957) 

To section 7, ^'metaphysics/' This term is used in this paper, as 
usually in Europe, for the field of alleged knowledge of the essence of 
tilings which transcends the realm of empirically founded, inductive 
science. Metaphysics in this sense includes systems like those of Fichte, 
Schelling, Hegel, Bergson, Heidegger. But it does not include endeavors 
towards a synthesis and generalization of the results of the various 
sciences. 

To section 1, ''meaning/' Today we distinguish various kinds of 
rfieaning, in particular cognitive (designative, referential) meaning on 
ttie one hand, and non-cognitive (expressive) meaning components, 
e-g. emotive and motivative, on the other. In the present paper, the word 


loll 

Jhe Elimination of Metaphysics i ■* 

“meaning” is always understood in the sense of “co^itive meanmg.” 
The thesis that the sentences of metaphysics are meanmgless, 
he understood in the sense that they have no cognitive meaning, no asser- 
tive content. The obvious psychological fact that they have expressi 
Lanin- is thereby not denied; this is explicitly stated m Section 7. 

6, “metalogicr This term refers to the theoir of ex^«- 
cions of a language and, in particular, of their logical relations. Tod y 
we would distinguish between logical syntax as the theory of y 
formal relations and semantics as the theory of meaning and truth- 

contoons.^^^ 6, realism and idealism. That both the affirmative and ffie 
negative theses concerning the reality of the external world are pseudo- 
Ltements, I have tried to show in the monograph Schemprobleme m 
der Philosophic: Das Fremdpsrychische and der Reahsmusstreit, BeiUn. 
1928 The similar nature of the ontological theses about the reality or 
unreality of abstract entities, e.g., properties, relations propositions, is 
discussed in “Empiricism, .Semantics, and Ontology, Revue 
Philos. 4, 1950, 20-40, reprinted in: Meaning and Necessity, secona edi- 

tion, Chicago, 1956. 




4 


Positivism and Realism 
BY MORITZ SCHLICK 
(translated by DAVID RYNIN) 


1. Preliminary Questions 

Every philosophical poimt of view is defined by the principles 
which it considers fundamental and to which it constantly recurs in 
argument. But in the course of the historical development of such a 
view these principles tend to change — whether they be reformulated, 
extended, or restricted, or even gradually altered in meaning- At 
some time then the question arises whether we should still speak of 
the development of the one point of view at all, and retain its old 
name; or whether a new viewpoint has arisen. 

If, along with the developed view there also exists an “orthodox” 
viewpoint which retains the first principles in their original form and 
meaning, sooner or later some terminological distinction between tlie 
old and the new will arise automatically. But where tliis is not clearly 
the case, where rather the different exponents of a “viewpoint” em- 
ploy extremely different, even contradictory, formulations and mean- 
ings of the principles, confusion arises; the adherents and opponents 
of the view talk at cross purposes; each selects those statements 
which can be used in defense of his own opinions, and all ends in fatal 
misunderstanding and obscurity. These confusions disappear only 
when the different principles are distinguished, and each is tested sep- 
arately for its meaning and truth. In such an examination of prin- 
ciples one quite ignores, for the time, the question of the historical 
contexts of their origins, and of their names. 

I should like to apply these considerations to the modes of think- 

Tiiis article first appeared in Erkenntnis, Volume III (1932/33) and is here re- 
published with the kind permission of Mrs. SchHck and Professor Carnap. It was 
written in response to criticisms of positivism in a lecture by Max Planck entitled 
“Positivismus und Reaie Aussenwelt,” published in 1931 by the Akademische Ver- 
lagsgeseilschaft, Leipzig. 


C 82 ] 


■vl */'.'' ' Positivism and Realism [ ] 

^ ' iBg grouped together under the name “positivism.” They have, from 
the time August Comte invented the term until the present, under- 
gone a development which furnishes a good example of what has 
just been said. But I do not do this with the historical aim, say, of 
determining a strict concept of positivism as it has appeared in his- 
tory, but rather in order to contribute something to a positive settle- 
ment of the dispute carried on nowadays concerning certain prin- 
ciples which pass as fundamental to positivism. Such a settlement 
concerns me the more because I myself advocate some of these 
principles. I am concerned here only to make their meaning as clear 
as possible; whether or not one will, after this clarification, attribute 
tliem to “positivism’'* is a question of very little importance. 

If one wishes to characterize every view which denies the possi- 
bility of metaphysics as positivistic this is quite unobjectionable, as 
a mere definition; and I should in this sense call myself a strict 
positivist. But this holds, of course, only under the presupposition 
of a special definition of “metaphysics.” WTiat the definition of meta- 
physics is which must be adopted here need not interest us at the 
moment; but it hardly agrees with the formulations usual in philo- 
sophic literature, and further determinations of positivism which 
refer to such formulations lead at once into confusions and difficulties. 

If we say, as frequently has been said, that metaphysics is the the- 
ory^ of “trae being,” of “reality in itself.” of “transcendent being” this 
obviously implies a (contradictory) spurious, lesser, apparent being; 
as has indeed been assumed by all metaphysicians since the time of 
Plato and the Elcatics, This apparent being is the realm of “appear- 
ances,” and while the true transcendent reality is to be reached only 
with difficulty, by the efforts of the metaphysician, the special 
sciences have to do exclusively with appearances w'hich are perfectly 
accessible to them. The difference between the ways in wliich these 
two “modes of being” are to be known, is then explained by the 
fact that the appearances are immediately present, “given,” to us, 
while metaphysical reality must be inferred from them in some 
roundabout manner. And thus we seem to arrive at a fundamental 
concept of the positivists, for they always speak of the “given,” and 
usually formulate their fundamental principle in the proposition that 
the philosopher as well as the scientist must always remain within 
the given, that to go beyond it, as the metaphysician attempts, is 
impossible or senseless. 

Thus it amounts to identifying the “given” of the positivist with 
the “appearances” of metaphysics, and to believing that positivism 
is at l^ttom a metaphysics, from which one has left, or stricken, 





[ 84 I MORITZ SCHLICK 

out the transcendent; and such an opinion may indeed often enough 
have inspired the arguments of the positivists, as well as those of 
their opponents. But this belief finds us well on our way to dangerous 
errors. 

The term “the given” itself is a cause of grave misunderstandings, 
“To give” usually connotes a three term relation: it presupposes 
first, someone who gives, secondly, one to whom is given, and thirdly, 
something given. The metaphysician finds this quite in order, for 
what gives is the transcendent reality, what receives is the knowing 
mind, which makes what is given to it into its “content.” But evi- 
dently the positivist will from the very outset have nothing to do 
with such notions; the given is for him but a word for what is most 
simple and no longer questionable. No matter what word we choose, 
every one will be capable of misinterpretations; if we speak of 
“experiences” we seem to presuppose the distinction between what 
experiences and what is experienced; with the use of the phrase “con- 
tent of consciousness” we seem burdened with a similar distinction, 
and in addition with the complicated concept of “consciousness,” 
which in any case did not exist until invented by philosophy. 

But even apart from such difficulties it is perhaps stiU not clear 
what is actually meant by the given. Do only such “qualities” as 
“blue,” “warm,” “pain,” come under this heading, or e.g. also 
relations between them, or their order? Is the similarity of two 
qualities “given” in the same sense as the qualities themselves? And 
if the given is somehow worked up or interpreted or judged is 
this working-up or judging not also in some sense something given? 

But it is not obscurities of this sort that give rise to the current 
matter of dispute: the bone of contention appears among the various 
parties only with the question of “reality.” 

If the rejection of metaphysics by positivism signifies the denial 
of transcendent reality then it seems the most natural conclusion in 
the world that the positivist attributes reality only to non-transcendent 
being. The fundamental principle of the positivist then seems to run: 
“Only the given is real.” If one enjoys word-play one can lend to 
this proposition the semblance of tautological self-evidence by 
making use of a peculiarity of the German language in thus formu- 
lating it: “Es gibt nur das Gegebene.” (There is only the given.) 

What shall we make of this proposition? Many positivists may 
have expressed and advocated it (especially, perhaps, those who 
represented physical objects as “mere logical constructions,” or 
“mere auxiliary concepts”), while this view has been attributed to 
others by their opponents. We must insist, however, that whoever 


Positivism and Realism [ ] 

States this proposition seeks to establish an assertion which is 
metaphysical in exactly the same sense and degree as its apparent 
contradictory: “There is a transcendent reality.” 

The problem about which the matter revolves here is evidently 
the so-called problem of the reality of the external world, and there 
seem to be two parties: that of “realism” which believes in the 
reality of the external world, and that of “positivism” which does 
not. In truth, I am convinced that it is quite senseless to set two 
views in opposition in this manner, for neither party really knows 
what it wants to say (which is the case v/ith every metaphysical 
proposition.) But before I explain this I should like to show how 
the more obvious interpretations of the proposition “only the given 
is real” actually lead at once to well-known metaphysical views. 

This problem can take the form of the question about the existence 
of the “external” world only if somehow we can distinguish between 
inner and outer; and this distinction is made by considering the 
given as a “content” of consciousness, as belonging to one or several 
subjects to whom it is given. Thus the immediate datum would have 
attributed to it some sort of mental character, the character of a 
representation or an idea; and the proposition would then state that 
this character pertained to all reality: no being outside of conscious- 
ness. But this is nothing but the fundamental principle of metaphysical 
idealism. If the philosopher thinks himself able to speak only of 
what is given to himself we have before us a solipsistic metaphysics, 
but if he thinks he may assume that the given is distributed among 
many subjects we have a metaphysics of the Berkeleyan variety. 

On this inteipretation fX)sitivism would be simply identical wnth 
the older idealistic metaphysics. But since its founders certainly 
desired something quite ditTerent from a renewal of that idealism, 
this interpretation is to be rejected as contrary to the anti-metaphysicai 
attitude of positivism. Idealism and positivism are incompatible. 
The positivist Ernst Laas has written a work of several volumes to 
demonstrate the irreconcilable opposition which exists on all points 
between them; and if his student Hans Vaihinger gave to his “Philos- 
ophy of As If” the subtitle an “idealistic positivism” it is but one of 
the contradictions from which this work suffers. Ernst Mach es- 
pecially emphasized that his own positivism developed in an opposite 
direction to that of Berkeleyan metaphysics; and he and Avenarius 
laid great stress upon not taking the given as a content of conscious- 
ness. They tried to exclude this concept from their philosophy 
altogether. 

In view of the uncertainty in the camp of the positivists them- 





[ 86 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

selves it is no wonder that the “realist” fails to observe the distinctions 
we have discussed, and directs his arguments against the thesis: 
“There is nothing but the contents of consciousness,” or “There is only 
an internal world.” But this proposition belongs to idealistic meta- 
physics, and has no place in an anti-metaphysical positivism, which is 
not affected by these realistic arguments. 

Of course the realist can think that it is simply inevitable to 
conceive the given as contents of consciousness, as subjective, as 
mental — or whatever expression is used; and he will then consider 
as a failure the attempt of Mach and Avenarius to take the given 
as neutral and to resolve the distinction between inner and outer, 
and will believe that a view free of any metaphysical basis is im- 
possible. But this line of thought is rarely met with. And however 
it may fare, in any case, the whole business is much ado about 
nothing, for the “problem of the reality of the external world” is a 
meaningless pseudo-problem. This must now be made evident. 

2. On the Meaning of Propositions 

It is the peculiar business of philosophy to ascertain and make 
clear the meaning of statements and questions. The chaotic state 
in which philosophy has found itself during the greater part of its 
history is due to the unfortunate fact that, in the first place, it took 
certain formulations to be real questions before carefully ascertaining 
whether they really made any sense, and, in the ''second place, it 
believed that the answers to the questions could be found by the aid 
of special philosophical methods, different from those of the special 
sciences. But we cannot by philosophical analysis decide whether 
anything is real, but only what it means to say that it is real; and 
whether this is then the case or not can be decided only by the usual 
methods of daily life and of science, that is, through experience. Hence 
we have here the task of making clear to ourselves whether any mean- 
ing can be attached to the problem of the reality of the “external 
world.” 

When, in general, are we sure that the meaning of a question is 
clear to us? Evidently when and only when we are able to state 
exactly the conditions under which it is to be answered in the 
aSirmative, or, as the case may be, the conditions under which it is 
to be answered in the negative. By stating these conditions, and by 
this alone, is the meaning of a question defined. 

It is the first step of any philosophizing, and the foundation of 
all reflection, to see that it is simply impossible to give the meaning 
of any statement except by describing the fact which must exist if 



.'p^ and Realism ' [ H7 ] 

' 'the statement is to be true. If it does not exist then the statement is 
” ■ false. The meaning of a proposition consists, obviously, in this 

; alone, that it expresses a definite state of affairs. And this state of 
'' ' ■ affairs must be pointed out in order to give the meaning of the 
proposition. One can, of course, say that the proposition itself 
already gives this state of affairs. This is true, but the proposition 
indicates the state of affairs only to the person who understands it. 
But when do I understand a proposition? When I understand the 
meanings of the words which occur in it? These can be explained 
by definitions. But in the definitions new words appear whose meanings 
cannot again be described in propositions, they must be indicated 
directly: the meaning of a word must in the end be shown, it must be 
given. This is done by an act of indication, of pointing; and what 
is pointed at must be given, otherwise I cannot be referred to it. 

Accordingly, in order to find the meaning of a proposition, we 
must transform it by successive definitions until finally only such 
words occur in it as can no longer be defined, but whose meanings 
can only be directly pointed out. The criterion of the truth or falsity 
of the proposition then lies in the fact that under definite conditions 
(given in the definition) certain data are present, or not present. 
If this is determined then everything asserted by the proposition is 
determined, and I know its meaning. If I am unable, in principle, 
to verify a proposition, that is, if I am absolutely ignorant of how to 
proceed, of what I must do in order to ascertain its truth or falsity, 
then obviously I do not know what the proposition actually states, 
and I should then be unable to interpret the proposition by passing 
from the words, with the aid of the definitions, to possible experiences. 
For in so far as I am able to do this I am also able in the same way to 
state at least in principle the method of verification (even though, 
often, because of practical difficulties I am unable to carry it out) . The 
statement of the conditions under which a proposition is true is 
the same as the statement of its meaning, and not something different. 

And these conditions,'' we have already seen, must finally be 
discoverable in the given. Different conditions mean differences in 
the given. The meaning of every proposition is finally to be determined 
by the given, and by nothing else. 

I do not know if this insight ought to be called positivistic; but 
of course I should like to believe that it underlay ffil those efforts 
which appear by this name in the history of philosophy, whether or 
not it was ever clearly formulated. We may indeed assume that it 
constitutes the real nucleus and motive force of many quite perverted 
formulations which we find among positivists. 


[ 88 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

If we but once attain the insight that the meaning of every prop- 
osition can be determined only by means of the given we can no 
longer conceive the possibility of another opinion, for we see that 
we have discovered simply the conditions under which opinions in 
general can be formulated. Hence it would be quite mistaken to see, 
somehow, in what we have said a “theory of meaning” (in Anglo- 
Saxon countries this insight, that the meaning of a proposition is 
determined wholly and alone by its verification in the given, is often 
called the “experimental theor}^ of meaning”). What precedes every 
formulation of a theory cannot itself be a theory. 

The content of our insight is indeed quite simple (and this is the 
reason why it is so sensible). It says: a proposition has a statable 
meaning only if it makes a verifiable difference whether it is true or 
false. A proposition which is such that the world remains the same 
whether it be true or false simply says nothing about the world; it is 
empty and communicates nothing; I can give it no meaning. We have a 
verifiable difference, however, only when it is a difference in the 
given, for verifiable certainly means nothing but “capable of being 
exhibited in the given.” 

it is obvious that verifiabiiitx^ is used here in the sense of “verifi- 
able in principle,” for the meaning of a proposition is, of coarse, 
independent of whether the conditions under which we find ourselves 
at a specified time allow or prevent the actual verificadon. There is 
not the least doubt that the proposition “there is a mountain of a 
height of 3000 meters on the other side of the moon” makes good 
sense, even though we lack the technical means of verifying it. And 
it would remain just as meaningful if one knew with certainty, on 
scientific grounds, that no man would ever reach the other side of 
the moon. The verification remains conceivable; we are always able 
to state what data we should have to experience in order to decide 
the truth or falsity of the proposition; the verification is logically 
possible, whatever be the case regarding its practical feasibility, 
and this alone concerns us. 

But if someone should say: within every electron there is a 
nucleus, which, though always present, never has in any way any 
external effects, so that its existence never manifests itself in nature — 
this would be a meaningless assertion. For we should have to ask 
the maker of the hypothesis: what do you really mean by the presence 
of that “nucleus”?; and he could answer only: I mean that something 
exists there in the electron. We should inquire further: what does 
that mean? What would be the case if it didn’t exist? And he would 
have to answer: everything would remain exactly the same as before. 



r'- positivi^^ and Realism [ j 

\ P0|. according to his assertion, the “somewhat” in the electron has 

' 20 effects, and there would simply be no observable change: the 

/ lealin of the given would not be affected in any way. We should 
judge that he had not succeeded in communicating the meaning of 
his hypothesis, and that therefore it made no sense. In this case the 
: impossibility of verification is not factual, but logical, for by reason 
of the utter ineffectiveness of that nucleus a decision regarding it 
based on differences in the given is in principle excluded. 

One cannot here suppose that the distinction between the im- 
possibility of verifying something in principle and the mere factual, 
empirical impossibility is not clear, and is therefore sometimes 
difficult to draw; for the impossibility in principle is logical impos- 


sibility which does not differ in degree from empirical impossibility, 
but in very essence. What is empirically impossible still remains 
conceivable, but what is logically impossible is contradictory, and 
cannot therefore be thought at all As a matter of fact we find that in 
scientific thinking this distinction is always clearly and instinctively 
felt. The physicists were the first to reject the statement given in our 
example regarding the forever hidden nucleus of the electron, with 
the criticism that it was no hypothesis at all, but mere empty word 
play. And in all times the most successful scientific investigators 
have adopted this standpoint with respect to the meaning of their 
statements, since they have acted in accordance with it, even if for the 
most part unconsciously. 

For science, then, our standpoint does not represent something 
foreign and out of the ordinary, but it has in a certain sense always 
been more or less taken for granted. It could not be othei-wise, because 
only from this standpoint is a proposition verifiable at all; and since 
all the activities of science consist in examining the truth of propo- 
sitions, it continuously acknowledges the correctness of our insight 
by its practice. 

If express confirmation were still necessary^ it would be found 
most conspicuously at critical points in the development of sci- 
ence where investigation is forced to bring the self-evident pre- 
suppositions to light. This is the case where difficulties of principle 
lead one to suppose that something may be wrong with these pre- 
suppositions. The most famous example of this sort, which will 
remain forever memorable, is Einstein’s analysis of the concept of 
time, which consists in nothing but the analysis of the meaning of our 
statements about the simultaneity of spatially separate events. 
Einstein said to the physicists (and to the philosophers): you must 
first state what you mean by simultaneity, and you can do this only 



* '4' -It’.-’ 


t ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

by showing how the proposition “two events are simultaneous” is 
verified. But with this you have completely determined its meaning. 
What is true of the concept of simultaneity holds of every other 
concept: every proposition has meaning only in so far as it can be 
verified, and it says only what is verified, and simply nothing more. 
If one should say that it did contain something more he must be able 
to say what more this is, and to do this he would have to tell us how 
the world would differ if he were mistaken. But this cannot be done, 
since by assumption all the observable differences are already in- 
cluded in the verification. 

In the example of simultaneity the analysis of the meaning, as is 
appropriate for the physicist, is carried only to the point where the de- 
cision regarding the truth or falsity of a proposition about time is based 
on the occurrence or non-occurrence of a definite physical event (e.g. 
the coincidence of a pointer with a point on a scale). But it is clear 
that one can ask further: what does it mean to say that the pointer 
indicates a definite point on the scale? And the answer can only be 
made by reference to the occurrence of certain data, or as one gen- 
erally says, certain ‘^‘sense-impressions.’* This will be generally ad- 
mitted, especially by physicists. “For positivism will always be right 
in this, that there is no other source of knowledge than sense-impres- 
sions says Planck^ and this evidently means that the truth or 
falsity of a physical statement depends entirely upon the occurrence 
of certain sense-impressions (which constitute a soecia! class of data). 

But there will always be many who are inclined to sav: granted 
that the truth of a physical statement can be tested only bv the occur- 
rence of certain sense-impressions, this is not the same as asserting 
that the meaning of the statement is also therebv exhaustively sjiven. 
This latter must be denied: a proposition can contain more than can 
be verified; that the pointer stands at a definite point on the scale 
means more than the existence of certain sensations (namely “the 
existence of a definite fact in the external world”). 

In answer to this denial of the identity of meaning and verifica- 
tion we must point out the following: 1) This denial is found among 
physicists only when they leave the actual sphere of physical state- 
ments and begin to philosophize. (In physics, obviously, there occur 
only statements about the properties or behavior of things or events, 
an express statement concerning their “reality” is not" a scientific 
statement but a philosophical one). In his own sphere the physicist 
adinits entirely the correctness of our standpoint. We mentioned this 
earlier, and illustrated it in the example of simultaneity. There are 

1. Positivismus und Reale Aussenwelt, p. 14. 



and Realism [ ] 

indeed many philosophers who say: of course we can determine only 
illative simultaneity, but it does not follow from this that there is 
I 00 such thing as absolute simultaneity, and we continue to believe 
in it! The falsity of this statement cannot in any sense be demon- 
- strated, but the overwhelming majority of physicists is rightly of the 
I opinion that it is meaningless. However it must be sharply empha- 
I sized that in both cases we have to do with the same situation. There 
I is in principle no difference whether I ask: does the proposition “two 
; events are simultaneous” mean more than can be verified? Or whether 
I ask: does the proposition “the pointer points toward the fifth line 
on the scale” mean more than can be verified? The physicist who 
; handles these two cases differently is guilty of an inconsistency. He 
will of course justify himself, believing that in the second case where 
; the question concerns the “reality of the external world” much more 
; is at stake, philosophically. Tliis argument is too vague for us to 
attach much weight to it, but we shall see presently whether anything 
lies behind it. 

2 ) It is perfectly true that every statement about a physical 
object or an event means more than is verified, say, by the occurrence 
■ of a single experience. It is rather presupposed that the experience 
occurred under very^ definite conditions, whose realization of course 
can only be verified by something given, and it is presupposed farther 
that ever more verifications are possible (confirmations etc.), which 
in their turn, naturally, reduce to certain given events. In this manner 
one can and must give an account of illusions of sense, and of error, 
and it is easy to see how those cases are to be included in which we 
should say the observer was merely dreaming, that the pointer in- 
dicated a definite line, or that he did not carefully observe, etc. The 
assertions of Blondlot about N-Rays which he believed himself to 
have discovered were certainly more than statements that under 
certain conditions he had experienced certain visual sensations; and 
because of this, of course, they could be refuted.- Strictly speaking, 
the meaning of a proposition about physical objects would be ex- 
hausted only by an indefinitely large number of possible verifications, 
and we gather from this that such a proposition can in the last 
analysis never be shown to be absolutely true. It is indeed generally 
recognized that even the most certain propositions of science are 
always to be taken as hypotheses, which remain open to further 
refinement and improvement. This has certain consequences for the 
logical nature of such propositions, but these do not interest us here. 

Once again: the meaning of a physical statement is never de- 


2. Cf. Planck, op. cit., p. 11. 


[ 92 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

termined by a single isolated verification, but it must be thought of 
in the fom: If conditions x are given, the data y occur, where we 
can substitute an indefinitely large number of conditions for x, the 
proposition remaining true for each case. (This holds even when the 
statement refers to a single happening — a historical event, for such 
an event has innumerable consequences whose occurrences are veri- 
fiable). Thus the meaning of every physical statement is lodged finally 
in an endless concatenation of data; the isolated datum therefore is 
here uninteresting. Hence if any positivist ever said that the only 
objects of science are the given experiences themselves he was 
certainly quite mistaken; what alone the scientists seek are the rules 
which govern the connections among experiences, and by means of 
which they can be predicted. No one will deny that the sole verifica- 
tion of natural laws lies in the fact that they yield such true predic- 
tions. The common objection that the immediately given, which at 
most can be but the object of psycholog}% is thus falsely made into 
the object of physics is in this way refuted. 

3) Most important however: if anyone is of the opinion that 
the meaning of a proposition is nevertheless not exhausted by what 
can be verified in the given, but extends far beyond it, he must at 
least admit that this additional meaning cannot in any way be 
described, stated, or expressed in language. For let him tiy^ to com- 
municate this additional meaning! To the extent toAvhich he -succeeds 
in communicating something about this additional meaning he will 
find that the communication consists in the fact that he has indicated 
certain conditions which can serve for verification in the given, and 
thus he finds our position confirmed. Or else he believes himself to 
have given a meaning, but closer examination shows that his words 
express only that something more is there, concerning whose nature 
simply nothing is said. And then in fact he has communicated nothing, 
and his assertion is meaningless. For one cannot assert the existence 
of something without saying what one asserts to exist. This is ob- 
vious in the case of our example of the “nucleus of the electron" which 
in principle lies beyond experience; yet for clarity's sake we shall con- 
sider another example which brings out an important point of prin- 
ciple. 

I observe two pieces of green paper and determine that they 
have the same color. The proposition which asserts the sameness 
of color is verified, among other ways, by the fact that at the same 
time I have two experiences of the same color. The proposition: 
■“there are two spots of the same color before me now” cannot be 
reduced to any others; it is verified by the fact that it describes the 




tipasltivism and Realism [ ] 

: riven. It has a dear meaning: by virtue of the meanings of the 
words involved in the proposition, it signifies just the existence of color 
sameness; and by virtue of linguistic usage the proposition expresses 
just that experience. Now I show one of these two pieces of paper 
to a second observer, and ask the question: does he see the green 
as I do? Is his color experience like my color experience? This case 
differs in principle from that just considered. While there the state- 
ment was verifiable by the experience of color sameness, here, brief 
reflection shows, such a verification is simply impossible. Of course 
the second observer, if he is not color blind, calls the paper green, 
and if I describe this green to him more closely by saying: it is 
yellower than this carpet, but bluer than the billiard cloth, darker 
than this plant, etc., he will find the same to hold in his experience, 
i.e. he will agree with my statements. But even if all his judgments 
about color agree entirely with mine I cannot infer from this that he 
experiences this same quality. It could be the case that on looking 
at the green paper he would have a color experience which I would 
call '‘red,” that on the other hand, when I see red he would see green, 
calling it “red” of course, and so on. Indeed it might even be that 
my color sensations correspond to his tone experiences, or to any 
other data. It would nevertheless forever be impossible to discover 
these differences, between his and my experience. We should always 
understand one another perfectly, and could never be of different 
opinions regarding our environment if (and this is the only assumption 
that need be made) the inner order of his experiences agreed with 
that of mine. There is no question here of their “quality,” all that is 
required is that they can be arranged into systems in the same manner. 

All this is indeed admitted, and philosophers have often pointed 
it out. But, for the most part, while they have allowed that such sub- 
jective differences are theoretically possible, and that this possibility 
raises a very interesting question of principle, they have held it to be 
“highly probable” that the other observer and I do in fact have the 
same experience. But, we must point out, the statement that different 
individuals have the same experience has its sole verifiable meaning in 
the fact that all their assertions (and of course all the rest of their 
behavior) exhibit certain agreements. Hence it follows that the state- 
ment means nothing but this. It is only to express the same thing in a 
different manner if we say that we here are concerned with the simi- 
larity of two system-orders. The proposition that two experiences of 
different subjects not only occupy the same place in the order of a sys- 
tem but are, in addition, qualitatively similar has no meaning for us. 
Note well, it is not false, but meaningless: we have no idea what it 



[ 94 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

Experience shows, however, that most people find it ver>^ difficult 
to agree to this. We must make it clear that here we have to do with a 
logical impossibility of verification. It makes good sense to speak of 
the similarity of data in the same consciousness, for it can be verified 
through an immediate experience. But if we want to speak of the 
similarity of data in different consciousnesses we are dealing with a 
new concept, which has to be newly defined. For the statements in 
which it occurs are no longer verifiable in tlie old manner. The new 
definition is simply the similarity of all relevant reactions of the two 
individuals; we can find no other. Most people, of course, believe 
that no definition is required here; one knows the meaning of 
“similar” without it, and the meaning in both cases is the same. But, 
to recognize this as a mistake we need only remember the concept 
of simultaneity, in which the situation is exactly the same. To the 
concept of “simultaneity at a place” there corresponds the concept 
of “similarity of the experiences of the same individual,” and to 
“simultaneity at different places” there corresponds the notion of 
“similarity of the experiences of different persons.” The second 
notion is, with respect to the first, a new concept in each case, and 
must be specially defined. We can no more indicate a directly ex- 
periencable quality which would verify the similarity of two greens 
in different consciousnesses than we can for simultaneity at different 
points: both must be determined by a system of relations. 

Many philosophers have sought to overcome the difficulty which 
seemed to confront them here by all sorts of speculations and ideal 
experiments, speaking, say, of a universal consciousness comprehend- 
ing all individuals (God) or thinking perhaps that by means of some 
artificial connection of the nervous systems of two individuals the 
sensations of one would be made accessible to the other, and thus 
be rendered comparable. But of course all this is in vain. For even 
in this fantastic way in the end only the contents of one and the same 
consciousness would be directly compared. The question, however, 
concerns the possibility of the comparison of qualities in so far as 
they belong to different, and not the same, consciousnesses. 

Hence it must be granted that a statement concerning the simi- 
larity of the experiences of two persons has no other communicable 
meaning than a certain agreement of their reactions. Of course 
everyone is free to believe that such a proposition also possesses 
another more direct meaning; but so much is sure: no such meaning 
is verifiable, and one cannot in any way state or show what this 
meaning is. Hence it follows that such a meaning simply cannot 
in any way become the object of discussion. We can say absolutely 





, : [95] 

^ Positivism and Realism 

about it, and it can in no way enter into any J 

means°of which we communicate with one another. And ^ ^ ’ 

fS become clear here holds generally. We can understand n a 
oroposition only what it communicates, and a meaning . , 

SSy if it is verifiable. Since propositions are 

for conuBunication we can include in their meanings ^ny ^ Y 

S.“ «icate. For fitis reason I shonld maintain that “nreamng 

ran mean only “verifiable meaning.” 

But even if someone should insist that there is a non-veri 
meaning this would not help in the least. For such a meamng can 
S no way enter into anything he says or asks, or into what we aA 
him or answer him. In other words; if there were any such thi p, 

S our utterances, arguments, and modes of f 

Quite unaffected bv it, whether we were dealing with daily life, ethical 
TaBthSc attitudes, with science or philosophy. Ever^hmg wouU 
remain as if there were no unverifiable meamng. For if there were 
a difference this very difference would make it verifiable. 

This is a serious situation, and we must insist that it be taken 
seriouslv. Above all one must guard against confusing this lo^^ 
impossibility with an empirical incapacity, as if some technical 
culty and human imperfection were responsible for the fact that oriy 
what is verifiable can be expressed, and as if there were still some rcc 
entrance throuah which an unverifiable meaning might sip m ami 
make itself evident in our discourse and behavior. No. The tn^OTi- 
municability is absolute; he who believes (or 

he believes) in a non-verifiable meaning must nevertheless admit u c 
with respect to it only one course is open to him: utter silence. 
Neither he nor we gain anything, no matter how often he a^rts y 
there is a non-verifiable meaning!” For this statement itself is devoid 
of meaning, it tells us nothing. 

3. WH.'tT IS THE Meaning of “Reality,” 

OF “External World”? 

We are now prepared to apply what has been said to the so-called 
problem of the reality of the external world. ^ 

We ask: What is the meaning of the realist’s assertion, there 
is an external world?” or what is the meaning of the statement 
(attributed to the positivist by the realist) “there is no external 
world”? 

In order to answer the question it is of course necessary to make 
clear the meanings of the words, “there is,” and pxtemal world. 
We begin with the first. “There is an x” means the same as x is 


[ 96 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

real” or “x is actual.” Hence what do we mean when we attribute 
reality to an object? It is an old, very important logical or philosophi- 
cal insight, that the proposition “x is real” is of quite a different sort 
from a proposition which ascribes some property to x (e.g. '‘x is 
hard.”) In other words: reality or existence is not a predicate. The 
statement “the dollar in my pocket is round” has a completely 
different logical form from that of the statement “the dollar in my 
pocket is real.” In modern logic this distinction is expressed by 
means of two very different symbolisms, but it was already clearly 
drawn by Kant, who, as we know, in his critique of the so-caUed 
ontological proof of God’s existence, correctly found the source of 
error of this proof in the fact that existence is treated as a predicate. 

In daily life we constantly speak of reality or existence, and for 
this reason it cannot be very difficult to discover its meaning. In a 
law-suit it is often necessary to determine whether a certain docu- 
ment actually exists, or whether it is merely wrongly asserted to 
exist; and it is not altogether unimportant to me whether the dollar 
in my pocket is only imagined or is real. Now everyone knows how 
such an assertion of the reality of something is verified, and there 
cannot be the slightest doubt that the reality of the dollar is verified 
and verified only by the fact that, as a result of certain suitable 
manipulations, I obtain certain sensations of touch and sight upon 
w'hose presence I am accustomed to say “this is a dollar.” The same 
holds of the document, except that in this case we would content 
ourselves with certain statements of others who claim to have seen 
the document, i.e. to have had perceptions of a veiy^ definite sort. 
And the “statements of others” consist again of certain acoustic, or, 
if they were WTitien statements, of certain visual perceptions. No 
special analysis is required of the fact that the occurrence of certain 
sense-perceptions among the data always constitutes the sole criterion 
of statements concerning the reality of a “physical” object or event in 
everyday life, as well as in the most subtle propositions of science. 
That there are okapis in Africa can be determined only by the 
fact that such animals are observed there. However it is not necessary 
that the object or event “itself” be perceived. We can, for example, 
imagine the existence of a transneptunian planet to be inferred with 
as much certainty from the observation of perturbations as from the 
direct perception of a spot of light in the telescope. The reality of 
atoms furnishes us with another example. And the same is true of the 
other side of the moon. 

It is of great importance to realize that the occurrence of a 
definite single experience in the verification of a proposition about 


. Positivism and Realism [ I 

'nature is: often not accepted as verifying the proposition, but that 
throughout we are concerned with uniformities, with^ connectioiis 
obeying natural laws: in this manner genuine verifications are dis- 
tinguished from illusions and hallucinations. When we say of any 
object or event — ^which must be designated by a description — ^that 
it is real this means that there exists a very definite connection 
between perceptions or other experiences, that under certain condi- 
tions certain data appear. Such a statement is verified in this manner 
.alone, and therefore it has only this communicable meaning. 

This was in principle already formulated by Kant, whom no 
one would charge with ‘"positivism.” Reality for him is a category, 
and if w^e apply it in any way, and say of an object that it is real this 
means, according to Kant, that it belongs to a collection of percep- 
tions connected according to some natural law. 

We see that for us (as for Kant; and the same applies to every 
philosopher who understands his business) it is simply a matter of 
saying what it means in eveiyday life or in science to ascribe real 
existence to a thing. Our task is in no sense that of correcting the 
statements of everyday life or of science. 1 must confess that I should 
repudiate and consider absurd any philosophical system that in- 
volved the assertion that clouds and stars, mountains and sea were 
unreal, that the chair by the wall ceased to exist whenever I turned my 
back. Nor do I credit any serious thinker with any such statement. 
It w^ould for example surely be quite a perverse interpretation of 
Berkeley's philosophy to see in it such a system. He too didn’t deny 
the reality of the world of bodies, but merely tried to explain what 
we mean when we ascribe reality to it. He who says that unperceived 
ideas exist in God’s mind does not thereby deny their existence but 
seeks to understand it. John Stuart Mill himself did not wish to deny 
the reality of physical bodies, but to clarify it, when he declared 
them to be "'permanent possibilities of sensation,” though in my 
opinion his manner of expression was veiy ill chosen. 

Therefore if one understands by "'positivism” a view which denies 
the reality of bodies I must declare positivism to be simply absurd. 
But I do not believe that such an interpretation of positivistic views 
would be historically just, at least so far as their ablest representatives 
are concerned. Be this as it may, w'e are not concerned v/ith it, but 
with the view' itself. And in this connection we have seen that our 
principle, that the meaning of a proposition is identical with its veri- 
fication, leads to the insight that the assertion of the reality of a 
thing is a statement regarding a regular connection of experiences. 
It does not lead to the conclusion that the assertion is false. (There- 




[ 98 ] 

fore reality is not denied to physical things in favor of sensations.) 
with expounded are not at all satisfied 

Sp? following answer; “You do 

indeed, admit the realty of the physical world, but, as it seems to us’ 
only verbally. You simply call that real which we would describe as a 
mere conceptual construction. When we use the word rSfity we 
mean by it something quite different from what you mean Your 
definition of reality refers back to experiences; but we mea^ome- 
thmg altogether independent of experience. We mean somethint^ 

to^the dTf?'?' "T® independence evidently attributed by you 

to the data alone, m the sense that you reduce everythin^ to £ 
as to something not further reducible.” ^ ° ^ 

to ^ to invite our opponents 

vcrSSf Ld propositions are verified. S? htw 

coyider the psycholoS afiLrSthL'ti 

“con'ttnt“S "’’"‘“r on our view a reaiity is attributed to a 
content of consciousness” which is denied to a physical obiect 

to hv -1‘w a datum is possible only if it"is referred 

S course rC^’rJ"'’ <Jhec. indicaSof Sds 

loat T * ^ ‘ ^ consciousness.” Qn the language of symbolic 

s ctLs rL‘S,””sSr“- 

ra;Thavt"Z“io”rfy“ "Ur 

and dteSS fhe LT'asThl - hVe?" 

be written in Russell’s; cumhrvr meaningless, and cannot 

Descartes” stat« “-I ‘“'Sht that 

Uon, -4 ?«er of conse^Se : SL» 'l! ““‘f 
it expresses nothing and SS no 

loTr ‘ T? i -- 

be tested. A proposition only has meS^is vlrmabSw'ff 


Positivism and Realism [ ] 

state the conditions under which it would be true and under which 
it would be false. But how shall I describe the conditions under which 
the proposition “my contents of consciousness exist” would be false? 
Every attempt would lead to absurdity, for example to such state- 
ments as “it is the case that nothing is the case,” or something of the 
sort. Therefore it is self-evident that I cannot describe the conditions 
which make the proposition true (try to do so!). There is indeed 
also no doubt that Descartes failed to gain any knowledge through his 
statement, and was no wiser at the end than he was at the beginning 
of his inquiry. 

No, a question concerning the reality of an experience makes 
sense only if its reality can significantly be doubted. I can for ex- 
ample ask: Is it really true that I felt happy upon hearing that news? 
This can be verified or falsified in exactly the same way as, say, the 
question: is it true that Sirius has a satellite (that this satellite 
is real)? That on a given occasion I exp>erienced pleasure can for 
example be verified by examining the statements of others concern- 
ing my behavior at the time, by finding a letter written by me at 
the time, or even simply by a veridical memoiy' of the emotion ex- 
perienced. Hence there is here absolutely no difference in principle: 
to be real always means to stand in a definite relationship to the 
given. And this ^so holds, say. for an experience at this very moment. 
For example, I can significantly ask (say in the course of a physio- 
logical experiment): do I, or do I not. experience a pain, at this 
moment? Observe that here “pain" does not function as a proper 
name for a this-here, but represents a concep>t which stands for a 
describable class of experiences. Here, too, the question is answered 
by determining that an experience having certain describable prop- 
erties occurs in conjunction with certain conditions (experimental 
conditions, concentration of attention etc.). Such describable prop- 
erties would be, for instance, similarity to an experience occurring 
under certain other conditions; the tendency to produce certain reac- 
tions, etc. 

No matter how we twist and turn: it is impossible to interpret 
an existential proposition except as a statement regarding a con- 
nection of perceptions. It is reality of the same sort that one must 
attribute to data of consciousness and, say. to physical events. Hardly 
anything in the history of philosophy has produced greater con- 
fusion than the attempt to distinguish one of the two as true “being.” 
Wherever the word “real” is significantly used it means one and the 
same thing. 

The opponent of this view will perhaps not feel that what has 


MORITZ SCHLICK 


[ 100 ] 

been said upsets Ms own view in any way, but will be of the impress 
sioE that the preceding arguments presuppose a point of departure 
he is from the outset unwilling to adopt. He must indeed grant 
that a decision regarding the reality or unreality of a fact in ex- 
perience is always made in the way described, but he claims that 
in this way one arrives only at what Kant called empirical reality. 
This method defines the realm of the observations of everyday life 
and of science, but beyond this limit lies something more, the 
transcendent reality, which cannot be deduced by strict logic, and 
therefore is not a postulate of the understanding, but is perhaps a 
postulate of reason. This is the only real external world, and it alone 
is relevant to the philosophical problem of the existence of the ex- 
ternal world. Thus our discussion leaves the question of the meaning 
of the word “reality,” and turns to that of the phrase “external world.” 

The phrase “external world” is evidently used in two different 
W’'ays: first in the language of everyday life, and secondly as a tech- 
nical term in philosophy. 

Wherever it occurs in daily life it has, as do most of the expres- 
sions used in practical affairs, a sensible meaning which can be 
stated. In opposition to the “inner world,” which includes memories, 
thoughts, dreams, desires, feelings, the external world is simply the 
world of mountains and trees, of animals and men,. Every child 
knows what is meant when we assert the existence of definite ob- 
jects of tMs world; and we must insist that it really means absolutely 
nothing more than what the child knows. We all know how to 
verify the statement, say, that “there is a castle in the park outside 
the city.” We act in certain ways and then if certain clearly describ- 
able facts are experienced we say: “Yes, there really is a castle 
there,” otherwise v/e say the statement was wrong, or a lie. And if 
someone asks us: “Was the castle also there at night, when no one 
saw it?” We answer: “Undoubtedly! For it would have been im- 
possible to build it since this morning; furthermore the condition 
of the building shows that not only was it there yesterday, but 
for hundreds of years, hence before we were born.” Thus we pos- 
sess quite definite empirical criteria with wMch to determine 
whether houses and trees existed when we did not see them, and 
whether they already existed before our birth, and whether they 
will exist after our death. This means that the statement that those 
things “exist independently of us” has a clear verifiable meaning, 
and is obviously to be affirmed. We can very well distinguish em- 
pirically tMngs of this sort from those that are only “subjective” and 



I IVl ] 

Positivism and Realism , 

^^dependent upon ns.’’ If, f 5 lay that the 

I see a dark spot when I look f the waU is there 

spot is there only when I look of this distinction is 

even when I do not look at it. The venhcation or i 

indeed quite easy, and both these statements say ] 

tained in the verifications, and t/taken with the signification 

Hence if the phrase external world is taken w«n me ^ 

si^Vly “®“°'biyt'w?have 

In tte negative. There are, S aiv thinker 

wten we1^fc°“f miuntSs and plants he would convince us that 

n„rs:ieS. ^SSef fin ‘oppo.siho„ to — 

r«1 If “ »?t' ts the 

Seir theory and therefore the one must be real in the same sense 
as the oth?r. The objectivity of fn no 

same as that of 

Srt3dor formm in Lct-'we aJe at last convinced that the 
existence of even the most subtle “invisible things, assumed b> the 
SSist S: S principle, verified exactly as is the reality of a tree 

""in order to settle the dispute concerning realism it is of^ vej 
.Treat importance to draw the physicist’s attention to the 
his'.'xternal world is simplv nature, which also surrounds us in c y 
iiie aS not the “transcendent world” of the metaphysic, aiu The 

TrSf.:nrS’ ,rwf Sv? aSy’aaidT— h£ 

Tn instil that it must be by us. Atoms in Kant's system ha» no 
transcendent reality, they are not “things in themselves. Hence the 
vSSToM appeal to the Kantian philosophy; its arguments 
£i only to the empirical external world which we all acknowledge. 


[102] 

morttz schlick 

« .0 a tra««ad=a, wodd; his elactroas „„aphysi=a, 

SlSHstSslrS 

»hic^»p„a.=s .heTJ^^fhS '.he L'SsISr “ 

held b; sf S' oSr,„‘ L'o”: ::vrs^? 

=“£=t:P«P''5S 

elsewhere „a„v .™e?bSSUordra"„d”te 

S “CS lFIt -r- 

t ^”fbf ~Zfi; 

siHSS-^ - - “ 

theticaliy something unknowable. For fte^^ m^sralwavrb? 


Positivism and Realism [ 103 ] 

have the property of fulfilling this function, and must be so con- 
stituted that it is justified by those reasons. But in just this 'way cer- 
tain statements are made regarding the assumed entity and these 
express our knowledge of it. And of course they contain complete 
knowledge of it. For only that can be assumed hypothetically for 
which there are grounds in experience. 

Or does the ‘'realistic” scientist want to designate the theory of 
objects which are not directly experienced as a metaphysical hypoth- 
esis for some other reason than that of their unknowableness, which is 
not under consideration at all? To this he will perhaps answer affirma- 
tively. In fact we learn from numerous statements in the literature that 
the physicist does not add any statement of its unknowable char- 
acter to his affirmation of a transcendent world; quite the contrary, 
he is rightly of the opinion that the nature of the extra-mental things 
is correctly represented by his equations. Thus the external world 
of the physical realist is not that of traditional metaphysics. He uses 
the technical term of the philosopher, but what he means by it has ap- 
peared to us to be nothing but the external world of everyday life, 
whose existence no one, not ex^en the “positivist,” doubts. 

What, then, is that other reason which leads the “realist” to 
conceive his external world as a metaphysical hypothesis? Why does 
he want to distinguish it from the empirical external world which 
we have described? The answer to this question leads us back again 
to an earlier point in our discussion. The physical “realist” is quite 
satisfied with our description of the external world except in one 
point: he does not believe that we have granted it enough reality. It 
is not because it is unknowable, or for any such reason that he 
thinks his “external world” differs from the empirical, but only be- 
cause a different, higher reality pertains to it. This often shows itself 
in his language; the word “real” is frequently reserved for that ex- 
ternal world in contrast with the merely “ideal,” “subjective” con- 
tents of consciousness, and in opposition to mere “logical” construc- 
tions, “positivism” being reproached with the attempt to reduce 
reality to such logical constructs. 

But the physical realist, too, feels obscurely that, as we know, 
reality is not a “predicate,” hence he cannot well pass from our 
empirical to his transcendent external world by ascribing to it, in 
addition to the characteristics which we also attribute to physical ob- 
jects, the characteristic of “reality.” Nevertheless he expresses him- 
self in this way; and this illegitimate leap, which carries him beyond 
the realm of significance, would indeed be “metaphysical,” and will 
be felt by him to be such. 





liii 

f >i«' |i ■' 

Is' I 
f ^ M ,' 




r-; fl 04 ] 

';,H mokitz schlick 

3 S 

:ii “W- 

only in the “given ” and that ■ f ^ obpct, can be tested 

tions can be formulated and meaimg of all proposi- 

- given— this principle is mislak^y*^ “nceiwd nsV^t Ss'’l°fl*''' 

that the meanin<' of an existential^ ^ the contrary: 

by mere proportions of the fn sense exhausted 

that definite experience will occu™’ fthSe conditions 

an infinite set according to our viei constituting 

beyond ail this in somethino- <^ic u* I Hieaning lies 

•■independeoTeristSS '^s 4™ ■ c »y. 

■0 vAich out principle 'fails to do j^tke 

do these phras« •°ndepenS'e 3 kttnt"''aL'^“tjr‘‘“ d 
’»ea„? In other words: what verMlt Sff “ "“'“ndent bemg” 

heves himself to “de^r *K' ^^iferentl^ from one who be- 

sei^'e the stirrv^ sensations.” The former will ob- 

own puny nature an^^^ conscious of his 

of the world with very different^eer^*^”^' grandeur 

S o/ ht° wn'-fe"'*' ““““ - Sef; W 

self'r; Ss tasb devote him- 

knowiedge of Ihe external" "" '""dsfaction in the 

cause he believes S To h T ? be- 

structions. ^ith his own con- 

that^soSSrTtoThTtehTvio^o??^ comment. Let us assume 

difference such as has been deco ^‘ddirits Acre does exist a 

of course be M otevable difff^ T 
gts on expressmg this diffenence brsV„“/S'ore*„fT'“>' 

even, Ae nreuAug 5 S ItaTemen, wo '>■“ 

observe in fte behavior of Ae two men ’"lAaf “* 

reahty. or •■rianscendent be“,ror“h“,?™f:x;",: 



' positivism and Realism [ ] 

miglit choose to employ, mean here simply certain states of feeling, 
which occur in the men when they observe the world, or make state- 
ments about it, or philosophize. It is, indeed, the case that the use of 
the words “independent existence,” “transcendent reality,” etc., is 
simply and only the expression of a feeling, of a psychological attitude 
of the speaker (this, moreover, may, in the final analysis, be true of all 
metaphysical propositions). If someone assures us that there is a 
real external world in the trans-empirical sense of the word, he of 
course believes himself to have communicated some truth about the 
world. But in actual fact, his words express something very different; 
they merely express certain feelings which give rise to various lin- 
guistic and other reactions on his part. 

If this self-evident point requires any further emphasis I should 
like to call attention to the fact — and with the greatest stress on the 
seriousness of what is said — that the non-metaphysician is not dis- 
tinguished from the metaphysician by, say. the absence in him of 
those feelings which the other expresses in terms of the statements 
of a realistic philosophy, but only by the fact that he recognizes that 
these statements simply do not have the meaning they seem to have, 
and are therefore to be avoided. The non-metaphysician will express 
these same feelings in a dlffereni way. In other words: the contrast 
drawn in the first answer of the "realisr" between the two types of 
thinkers was misleading and unjust. If one is unfortunate enough 
not to feel the sublimity of the starry heavens sometiiing other than 
a logical analysis of the concepts of reality and external world is 
to be blamed. To assume that the opponents of metaphysics are 
unable justly to comprehend, say, the greatness of Copernicus, be- 
cause in a certain sense the Ptolemaic view represents the empirical 
facts as w'eH as the Copernican. seems to me to be as strange as to 
believe that the “positivist” cannot be a good parent because accord- 
ing to his theory his children are merely complexes of his own sense- 
impressions, and it is therefore senseless to take measures for their 
welfare after his death. No: the world of the non-metaphysician is 
the same world as that of all other men; it lacks nothing which is 
needed to bestow meaning on all the propositions of science and 
the whole conduct of life. He merely avoids adding meaningless state- 
ments to his description of the world. 

We come now to the second answer which can be given to the 
question concerning the meaning of the assertion of a transcendent 
reality. It consists in granting that it makes no difference at all for 
experience whether or not one assumes something further to exist 
behind the empirical world, that metaphysical realism therefore 


[ 106 ] 


unverifiable. Hence one cannot in- 
dicate any further what is meant by this assertion; but nevertheless 

Uout veScatS?^"’ ^ 

nothing but the view, criticized in the previous section 
Uon ^^“Srmerf “ P“P»sitioii has aothmg to do with its verifica- 

special case, perefore we must say: you designate here by ex- 
rttpce or reality something which simply cannot in any wJy be 

make sense. We shall noi quarrel with you over this point. But this 

can in no admission just made this sense 

can in no way become evident, it cannot be expressed in any written 
or spoken communication, nor by any gesture or conduct For if 

S Ind ,r IH™ ""m? "“Pirical 

fact, and the world would be d/fferent if the proposition “there is 

an extpnal world” were true, from what it would £ if it were false 

This difference would then constitute the meaning of th^p^ase 

be an empirical meaning- that 

4ich iTk^ empirical world, 

wnich, like all human beings, we also acknowledge.^ Even to speak 

of any other world is logically impossible. There can be no dLcus 

s.on conccmms ic, to, , noo-veriliable existence c^o. ento meat 

liera 'him'self™/ ptoposiiion. Whoever still believes^, be- 

heves himself to believe— m it must do so only silently Ar<mments 
can relate only to what can be said. ^ r^uments 

discussion may be summarized as follows- 

seems to m^tn h “positivistic” tendency 

^ems to me to be the pnnciple that the meaning of every proposi- 

tion is completely eptained within its verification in the ^ 

IS principle has seldom been clearly apparent within that 
general tendency, and has so frequently been mkef 4th so many un 
tenable propsitions that a logical purification is necessary l/one 
result of the purification positivism, which wuld per- 
^ justifiable, at least a differentiating adjective must 

?ied?-S^4“44i^™ “logistic poSm” 

to m^ to 

XXVtf/®(193lf^^e ^ Joumal of Philosophy, Vol. 

VoL XIII, Ser. B (Tu^ 19301 Universilalis Aboensis, 

VmversUii, GoJorg ’ ^ Schrifien der 


Positivism and Realism [ ] 

2) This principle does not mean and does not imply that only 
the given is real. Such an assertion does not make sense. 

3) Hence also, consistent empiricism does not deny the existence 
of an external world; it merely points out the empirical meaning of 
this existential proposition. 

4) It is not a “Theory of As If.” It does not assert that every- 
thing behaves as if there were physical independent bodies; but for 
it, too, everything is real which the non-philosophizing scientist calls 
real. The subject-matter of physics is not sensations, but laws. The 
formulation, used by some positivists, that bodies are only “com- 
plexes of sensations” is therefore to be rejected. What is correct is 
only that propositions concerning bodies are transformable into 
equivalent propositions concerning the occurrence of sensations in 
accordance with laws. 

5) Hence logical positivism and realism are not in opposition; 
whoever acknowledges our fundamental principle must be an em- 
pirical realist.^ 

6) An opposition exists only between the consistent empiricist 
and the metaphysician, and indeed no more against the realist than 
against the idealist metaphysician (the former has been referred to 
in our discussion as “realist” in quotation marks). 

7) The denial of the existence of a transcendent externai world 
would be just as much a metaphysical statement as its affirmation. 
Hence the consistent empiricist does not deny the transcendent 
world, but shows that both its denial and afSnnation are meaningless. 

This last distinction is of the greatest importance. I am con- 
vinced that the chief opposition to our view derives from the fact 
that the distinction between the falsity and the meaninglessness of 
a proposition is not observed. The proposition “Discourse concern- 
ing a metaphysical external world is meaningless” does not say; 
“There is no external world,” but something altogether different. 
The empiricist does not say to the metaphysician “what you say is 
false,” but, “what you say asserts nothing at all!” He does not con- 
tradict him, but says “I don’t understand you.” 

4. On this point and on the entire subject of the present essay the reader is also 
referred to Hans Cornelius’ “Zur Kritik der Wissenschafllichen Grundbegriife/’ 
Erkenntnis, Vol. 11. The formulations there are, however, open to objections. See 
also the splendid remarks in Chapter X of PhilHp Frank’s fine work. Das Kausal- 
gesetz und seine Grenzen, and Rudolf Carnap’s Scheinprobleme der Philosophic, 


5 



The Empiricist Criterion 

of Meaning 

BY CARL G. HEMPEL 


1. Introduction 

The fundamental tenet of modem empiricism is the view that 
all non-analytic knowledge is based on experience. Let us call this 
thesis the principle of empiricism.^ Contemporar>' logical empiricism 
has added- to it the maxim that a sentence makes a cognitively mean- 
ingful assertion, and thus can be said to be either tme or false, only 
if it is either (1) analytic or seli-contradictorv' or (2) capable, at 
least in principle, of experiential test. According to this so-called 
empiricist criterion of cognitive meaning, or of cognitive significance, 
many of the formulations of traditional metaphysics and large parts 
of epistemology are devoid of cognitive significance — however rich 
some of them may be in non-cognitive import by virtue of their 
emotive appeal or the moral inspiration they offer. Similarly certain 
doctrines which have been, at one time or another, formulated within 
empirical science or its border disciplines are so contrived as to be 
incapable of test by any conceivable evidence; they are therefore 
qualified as pseudo-hypotheses, which assert nothing, and which 

This article first appeared in Vol. 4 of Revue Internationale de Philosophie (1950). 
It is republished here with the kind permission of Professor Hempel and the editor 
of that journal. 

t- This term is used by Benjamin (2) in an examination of the foundations of 
empiricism. For a recent discussion of the basic ideas of empiricism see Russell (27), 
Part Six. 

2. In his stimulating article, “Positivism,” W, T. Siace argues, in effect, that the 
testability criterion of meaning is not logically entailed by the principle of empiricism. 
(See (29), especially section 11.) This is correct: according to the latter, a sentence 
expresses knowledge only if it is either analytic or corroborated by empirical evi- 
dence; the former goes further and identifies the domain of cognitively significant 
discourse with that of potential knowledge; i. e., it grants cognitive import only to 
sentences for which — unless they are either analytic or contradictorv' — a test by 
empirical evidence is conceivable. 


S 


[ 108 ] 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ ] 

therefore have no explanatory or predictive force whatever. This 
verdict applies, for example, to the neo-vitalist speculations about 
entelechies or vital forces, and to the “teiefinalist hypothesis*' pro- 
pounded by Lecomte du Nouy,^ 

The preceding formulations of the principle of empiricism and 
of the empiricist meaning criterion provide no more, however, than 
a general and rather vague characterization of a basic point of view, 
and they need therefore to be elucidated and amplified. And while 
in the earlier phases of its development, logical empiricism was to 
a large extent preoccupied with a critique of philosophic and scien- 
tific formulations by means of those fundamental principles, there 
has been in recent years an increasing concern with the positive tasks 
of analyzing in detail the logic and methodology of empirical science 
and of clarifying and restating the basic ideas of empiricism in the 
light of the insights thus obtained. In the present article, I propose 
to discuss some of the problems this search has raised and some of 
the results it seems to have established. 

2. Changes in the Testability Criterion 

OF Empirical Meaning 

As our formulation shows, the empiricist meaning criterion lays 
down the requirement of experiential testability for those among 
the cognitively meaningful sentences which are neither analytic nor 
contradictory; let us call them sentences with empirical meaning, 
or empirical significance. The concept of testability, which is to 
render precise the vague notion of being based — or rather baseable 
— on experience, has undergone several modifications which refiect 
an increasingly refined analysis of the structure of empirical knowl- 
edge. In the present section, let us examine the major stages of this 
development. 

For convenience of exposition, we first introduce three auxiliar}^ 
concepts, namely those of observable characteristic, of observation 
predicate, and of observation sentence. A property or a relation of 
physical objects will be called an observable characteristic if, under 
suitable circumstances, its presence or absence in a given instance 
can be ascertained through direct observation. Thus, the terms 
“green,’’ “soft,” “liquid,” “longer than,” designate observable char- 
acteristics, while “bivalent,” “radioactive,” “better electric con- 
ductor,” and “introvert” do not. Terms which designate observable 
characteristics will be called observation predicates. Finally, by an 


3. CL (19), Ch. XVL 


f no 1 

^ CARL G. HEMPEL 

observation sentence we shaU understand any sentence which— cor- 
rectly or incorrectly — asserts of one or more specifically named ob- 
jects that they have, or that they lack, some specified observable 
1 following sentences, for example, meet this con- 
toon. The Eiffel Tower is taUer than the buildings in its vicinity ” 
Die pointer of this mstrument does not cover the point marked 
3 on the scale, and even, “The largest dinosaur on exhibit in New 
York s Museum of Natural History had a blue tongue”; for this last 
sentence assies to a specified object a characteristic— having a blue 
of such a kind that under suitable circumstances 
’ Chow dog) its presence or absence can 

by direct observation. Our concept of obser^’ation 
sentence is mtended to provide a precise interpretation of the va^e 
n asserting something that is “in principle” ascer- 

tainable by direct observation, even though it mav happen to be 
actually incapable of bemg observed bv mvself. perhaps also bv 
my contemporaries, and possibly even bv anv human bein- who 
ever lived or wdl live. Any evidence that might be adduced In the 
test of an empirical hypothesis may now be thouaht of as beincf ex- 
pressed in observation sentences of this kind.^ “ “ 

Changes in the conception 6f testabilitv, 
and thus of empmcal meaning. In the earlv davs of the Vienna 
Urcie a sentence was said to have empirical raeaninc if it was 
capable, at least m pnnciple, of complete verification bv observa- 
tional evidence; i.e., if observational evidence could be' described 
which, if actually obtained, would condusivelv establish the truth 
of the sent ence.^' With the help of the concept of obser^■ation 

sgsMItlsilSPi 

Ongmaliy, the permissible evidence was meant to be resiricrp^ m ic 

obMrvable by the speaker and perhaps his fellow-beings during ibeir Ufetiii”^ 

tongue of the largest dinosaur m New York’s Museum of Natural History Wue 


..The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ ] 

fence, we can restate this requirement as follows: A sentence S has 
empirical meaning if and only if it is possible to indicate a finite 
set of observation sentences, Oi, O 2 , . . * , On, such that if these 
are true, then S' is necessarily true, too. As stated, however, this 
condition is satisfied also if S is an analytic sentence or if the given 
observation sentences are logically incompatible with each other. By 
the following formulation, we rule these cases out and at the same 
time express the intended criterion more precisely: 

(2.1) Requirement of complete verifiability in principle: A sen- 
tence has empirical meaning if and only if it is not analytic and 
follows logically from some finite and logically consistent class of 
observation sentences.® 

or black” is completely verifiable in our sense; for it is a logical consequence of the 
Sentence S^, “The tongue of the largest dinosaur in New York’s Museum of Natural 
History was blue”; and this is an observation sentence, as has been shown above. 

And if the concept of verifiability in principle and the more general concept of 
confirmability in principle, which will be considered later, are construed as referring 
to logically possible evidence as expressed by observation sentences, then it follows 
similarly that the class of statements which are verifiable, or at least confirmable, in 
principle includes such assertions as that the planet Neptune and the Antarctic 
Continent existed before they were discovered, and that atomic warfare, if not 
checked, may lead to the extermination of this planet. The objections which Russell 
(cf. (27), pp. 445 and 447) raises against the verifiability criterion by reference to 
those examples do not apply therefore if the criterion is understood in the manner 
here suggested. Incidentally, statements of the kind mentioned by Russell, which are 
not actually verifiable by any human being, were explicitly recognized as cognitively 
significant already by Schlick (in (28), Part V). who argued that the impossibility 
of verifying them was “merely empirical.” The characterization of verifiability with 
the help of the concept of observation sentence as suggested here might serve as a 
more explicit and rigorous statement of that conception. 

6. As has frequently been emphasized in empiricist literature, the term “veri- 
fiability” is to indicate, of course, the conceivability, or better, the logical possibility 
of evidence of an observational kind which, if actually encountered, would consti- 
tute conclusive evidence for the given sentence; it is not intended to mean the 
technical possibility of performing the tests needed to obtain such evidence, and 
even less does it mean the possibility of actually finding directly observable phe- 
nomena which constitute conclusive evidence for that sentence — which would be 
tantamount to the actual existence of such evidence and would thus imply the truth 
of the given sentence. Analogous remarks apply to the terms “falsifiabiiiiy” and 
“confirmability.” This point has been disregarded in some recent critical discussions 
of the verifiability criterion. Thus, e.g., Russell (cf. (27), p. 448) construes verifia- 
bility as the actual existence of a set of conclusively verifying occurrences. This 
conception, which has never been advocated by any logical empiricist, must naturally 
turn out to be inadequate since acording to it the empirical meaningfulness of a 
sentence could not be established without gathering empirical evidence, an J more- 
over enough of it to permit a conclusive proof of the sentences in question! It is 
not surprising, therefore, that his extraordinary interpretation of verifiability leads 
Russell to the conclusion: “In fact, that a proposition is verifiable is itself not 
verifiable” (/. c.) Actually, under the empiricist interpretation of complete veri- 
fiability, any statement asserting the verifiability of some sentence S whose text is 
quoted, is either analytic or contradictory; for the decision whether there exists a 
class of observation sentences which entail S, i. e., whether such observation sen- 
tences can be formulated, no matter whether they are true or false — that decision 


[ 112 ] 

™ . . . CARL G. HEMPEL 

cntenon, however, has several serious defects. The first of 
those here to be mentioned has been pointed out by various writers: 

versal fom, out aU sentences of uni- 

l^s; for these cannot be conclusively verified by any^ finite“set of 
observational data. And since sentences of this ipfcSitute f 
integral part of scientific theories, the verifiability requirement must 
Ij regarded as overly restrictive in this respect SiSy “he cn 
tenon disqualifies all sentences such as “For any subst^ce there 

^“versal andTStentiS 

quantifiers (i.e., occurrences of the terms “all” -fu * 

equivalents); for no sentences of toS ct. 

from any fimte set of observation sentences ^ 

nIs" ienteSTuS rs^'^he'ltLlls "pXT' 

irnattn'tvr«r.r'’“'“ “ « 

clearly, the empiricist criterion of meLn. is not intended conn 

SmS p^s: “/e'ShSj ro-s. 

{c) Let P be an observation predicate. Then the purelv ev 

Sfs r'““ ("There exists at leas' one thLi 

Inv h P^pecly P") IS completely verifiable, for it follows fsor^ 
any ofcervatton sentence asserting „t some particular oWe" tSm 
« has the property P, But its denial , being equivalent to the Liversal 

" information whate^ 

proposition is said to be ‘true’ when it is ‘terifirw*^ positivists: “A 

know the conditions which when reali-^d win «■. when we 

Ay^r) ” (cf. ( 31 ), p. 145). The quoted thesis which “at ' 

logical positivist, including Aver is in ’ir. * n’ anv 

describe conditions which^ if ^realized would 

the Chrysler Building is painted a b^iphf v n '^ sentence “The outside of 
verifying conditions for its^ denial* hencf ^ similarly, we can describe 

sentence and its denial would have to he^ ^ quoted principle, both the 

under discussion does not accord with ered true. Incidentally, the passage 

i-c., p. 40 , that verifiabiSty IS i^Lde^ observation, 

which shows that verifiabiUty is meant to h.- a the meaning of a sentence — 

than of truth. ^ ^ criterion of cognitive significance rather 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ ] 

sentence “(x) ^ P(x)” (“Nothing has the property P”) is clearly 
not completely verifiable, as follows from comment {a) above. 
Hence, under the criterion (2.1), the denials of certain empirically 
— and thus cognitively — significant sentences are empirically mean- 
ingless; and as they are neither analytic nor contradictory, they are 
cognitively meaningless. But however we may delimit the domain 
of significant discourse, we shall have to insist that if a sentence falls 
within that domain, then so must its denial. To put the matter more 
explicitly: The sentences to be qualified as cognitively meaningful 
are precisely those which can be significantly said to be either true 
or false. But then, adherence to (2.1) would engender a serious 
dilemma, as is shown by the consequence just mentioned. We would 
either have to give up the fundamental logical principle that if a 
sentence is true or false, then its denial is false or tnie, respectively 
(and thus cognitively significant); or else, we must deny, in a manner 
reminiscent of the intuitionistic conception of logic tind mathematics, 
that “(x) P(x)’' is logically equivalent to the negation of 

‘‘(Ex) P (x).” Clearly, the criterion (2.1), which has disqualified 
itself on several other counts, does not warrant such drastic measures 
for its preservation; hence, it has to be abandoned.’^ 

Strictly analogous considerations apply to an alternative criterion, 
which makes complete falsifiability in principle the defining char- 
acteristic of empirical significance. Let us formulate this criterion 
as follows: A sentence has empirical meaning if and only if it is 
capable, in principle, of complete refutation by a finite number of 
observational data; or, more precisely: 

(2,2) Requirement of complete falsifiabiUty in principle: A sen- 
tence has empirical meaning if and only if its denial is not anal}l:ic 
and follows logically from some finite logically consistent class of 
observation sentences.^ 

7. The arguments here adduced against the verifiability criterion also prove the 
inadequacy of a view closely related to it, namely that two sentences have the same 
cognitive significance if any set of observation sentences which would verify one 
of them would also verify the other, and conversely. Thus, e. g., under this criterion, 
any two general laws would have to be assigned the same cognitive significance, for 
no general law is verified by any set of observation sentences. The view just referred 
to must be clearly distinguished from a position which Russell examines in his 
critical discussion of the positivistic meaning criterion. It is “the theory that two 
propositions whose verified consequences are identical have the same significance” 
((27), p. 448). This view is untenable indeed, for what consequences of a statement 
have actually been verified at a given time is obviously a matter of historical acci- 
dent which cannot possibly serve to establish identity of cognitive significance. But 
I am not aware that any logical positivist ever subscribed to that “theory.” 

8. The idea of using theoretical falsifiability by observational evidence as the 
“criterion of demarcation” separating empirical science from mathematics and logic 
on the one hand and from metaphysics on the other is due to K. Popper (cf. (22), 


[ 114 ] CARL G. HEMPEL 

This criterion qualifies a sentence as empirically meaningful if 
its denial satisfies the requirement of complete verifiability; as is to 
be expected, it is therefore inadequate on similar grounds as the 
latter: 

(a) It rules out purely existential hypotheses, such as “There 
exists at least one unicorn,” and ail sentences whose formulation 
calls for mixed — i.e., universal and existential — quantification; for 
none of these can possibly be conclusively falsified by a finite number 
of observation sentences. 

(b) If a sentence S is completely falsifiable whereas N is a 
sentence which is not, then their conjunction, S.N. (i.e., the ex- 
pression obtained by connecting the two sentences by the word 
“and”) is completely falsifiable; for if the denial of S is entailed 
by some class of observation sentences, then the denial of S.N. is, 
a fortiori, entailed by the same class. Thus, the criterion allows 
empirical significance to many sentences which an adequate empiri- 
cist criterion should mle out, such as, say “All swans are white and 
the absolute is perfect.” 

(c) If “P” is an observation predicate, then the assertion that 
all things have the property P is qualified as significant, but its 
denial, being equivalent to a purely existential hypothesis, is dis- 
qualified (cf. (a)). Hence, criterion (2.2) gives rise" to the same 
dilemma as (2.1). 

In sum, then, interpretations of the testability cnterion in terms 
of complete verifiability or of complete faisifiability are inadequate 
because they are overly restrictive in one direction and overly in- 
clusive in another, and because both of them require incisive changes 
in the fundamental principles of logic. 

Several attempts have been made to avoid these difficulties by 
constming the testability criterion as demanding merely a partii 
and possibly indirect confirmability of empirical hypotheses by ob- 
servational evidence. 

(2.3) A formulation suggested by Ayer® is characteristic of 
these attempts to set up a clear and sufficiently comprehensive 
criterion of confirmability. It states, in effect, that a sentence S has 
empirical import if from S in conjunction with suitable subsidiary 

section 1-7 and 19-24; also see (23), voL II, pp. 282-285). Whether Popper would 
subscribe to the proposed restatement of the faisifiability criterion, I do not know. 

9. ( 1 ) , Ch. I. — ^The case against the requirements of verifiability and of faisifia- 
bility, and favor of a requirement of partial confirmability and disconfirmability is 
very clearly presented also by Pap in (21), Chapter 13. 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ ] 

hypotheses it is possible to derive observation sentences which are 
not derivable from the subsidiary hypotheses alone. 

This condition is suggested by a closer consideration of the 
logical structure of scientific testing; but it is much too liberal as 
it stands. Indeed, as Ayer himself has pointed out in the second edi- 
tion of his book. Language, Truth, and Logic , his criterion allows 
empirical import to any sentence whatever. Thus, e.g., if S is the 
sentence “The absolute is perfect,” it suffices to choose as a sub- 
sidiary hypothesis the sentence “If the absolute is perfect then this 
apple is red” in order to make possible the deduction of the ob- 
servation sentence “This apple is red,” which clearly does not fol- 
low from the subsidiary hypothesis aloneT^ 

(2.4) To meet this objection, Ayer has recently proposed a 
modified version of his testability criterion. The modification re- 
stricts, in effect, the subsidiary' hypotheses mentioned in (2.3) to 
sentences which are either analytic or can independently be shown 
to be testable in the sense of the modified criterion.^- 

But it can readily be shown that this new criterion, like the re- 
quirement of complete falsifiability, allows empirical significance 
to any conjunction S.N, w^here S satisfies Ayers criterion while N 
is a sentence such as “The absolute is perfect,” which is to be dis- 
qualified by that criterion. Indeed: whatever consequences can be 

10. (l), 2d ed., pp. 11-12. 

11. According lo Siace (cf. (29), p. 218), the criterion of partial and indirect 
testability, which he calls the positivist principle, presupposes (and thus logically 
entails) another principle, which he terms the Principle oj Observable Kinds: “A 
sentence, in order to be signiheant, must assert or deny facts which are of a kind 
or class such that it is logically possible directly to observe some facts which are 
instances of that class or kind. And if a sentence purports to assert or deny facts 
which are of a class or kind such that it would be logically impossible directly lo 
observe any instance of that class or kind, then the sentence is non-significant.” T 
think the argument Siace offers to prove that this principle is entailed by the re- 
quirement of testability is inconclusive (mainly because of the incorrect tacit assump- 
tion that "on the transformation view of deduction,” the premises of a valid deductive 
argument m.usi be necessary conditions for the conclusion (/. c., p. 225). Without 
pressing this point any further, I should like to add here a remark on the principle 
of observable kinds itself. Professor Stace does not say how we are to determine 
what “facts” a given sentence asserts or denies, or indeed whether it asserts or 
denies any “facts” at all. Hence, the exact import of the principle remains unclear. 
No matter, however, how one might choose the criteria for the factual reference of 
sentences, this much seems certain: If a sentence expresses any fact at all, say /, 
then it satisfies the requirement laid down in the first sentence of the principle; for 
we can always form a class containing / together with the fact expressed by some 
observ'ation sentence of our choice, which makes / a member of a class of facts 
at least one of which is capable, in principle, of direct observation. The first part 
of the principle of obsert’abie kinds is therefore all-inclusive, somewhat like Ayer’s 
original formulation of the empiricist meaning criterion. 

12. This restriction is expressed in recursive form and involves no vicious circle. 
For the full statement of Ayer’s criterion, see (1), second edition, p. 13. 


CARL G. HEMPEL 


[ 116 ] 

deduced from S with the help of permissible subsidiary hypotheses 
can also be deduced from S.N. by means of the same subsidiary 
hypotheses, and as Ayer’s new criterion is formulated essentially in 
terms of the deducibility of a certain type of consequence from 
the given sentence, it countenances S.N together with S. Another 
difficulty has been pointed out by Professor A. Church, who has 
shown^^ that if there are any three observation sentences none of 
which alone entails any of the others, then it follows for any sentence 
S whatsoever that either it or its denial has empirical import ac- 
cording to Ayer’s revised criterion. 

3. Translatability into an Empiricist Language 

AS A New Criterion of Cognitive Meaning 

I think it is useless to continue the search for an adequate cri- 
terion of testability in terms of deductive relationships to observa- 
tion sentences. The past development of this search — of which we 
have considered the major stages — seems to warrant the expectation 
that as long as we try to set up a criterion of testability for indi- 
vidual sentences in a natural language, in terms of logical relation- 
sliip to observation sentences, the result will be either too restrictive 
or too inclusive, or both. In particular it appears likely that such 
criteria would allow empirical import, in the manner of {2A)(b) 
or of (2.2) (h), either to any alternation or to any conjunction of 
two sentences of which at least one is qualified as empirically mean- 
ingful; and this peculiarity has undesirable consequences because the 
liberal grammatical rules of English as of any other natural lan- 
guage countenance as sentences certain expressions (‘The absolute 
is perfect” was our illustration) wmich even by the most liberal em- 
piricist standards make no assertion whatever; and these would 
then have to be permitted as components of empirically significant 
statements. 

The predicament would not arise, of course, in an artificial 
language whose vocabulary and grammar were so chosen as to pre- 
clude altogether the possibility of forming sentences of any kind 
which the empiricist meaning criterion is intended to rule out. Let 
us call any such language an empiricist language. This reflection 
suggests an entirely different approach to our problem: Give a gen- 
eral characterization of the kind of language that would qualify as 
empiricist, and then lay down the following 

(3.1) Translatability criterion of cognitive meaning: A sentence 


13, Church (11). 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ 117 ] 

has cognitive meaning if and only if it is translatable into an em- 
piricist language. 

This conception of cognitive import, while perhaps not explicitly 
stated, seems to underlie much of the more recent work done by 
empiricist writers; as far as I can see it has its origin in Carnap’s 
essay, Testability and. Meaning (especially part IV). 

As any language, so also any empiricist language can be char- 
acterized by indicating its vocabulary and the rules determining its 
logic; the latter include the syntactical rules according to which sen- 
tences may be formed by means of the given vocabulary. In effect, 
therefore, the translatability^ criterion proposes to characterize the 
cognitively meaningful sentences by the vocabulary out of v/hich they 
may be constructed, and by the syntactical principles governing their 
construction. What sentences are singled out as cognitively significant 
will depend, accordingly, on the choice of the vocabulary and of 
the construction rules. Let us consider a specific possibility: 

(3.2) We might qualify a language L as empiricist if it satisfies 
the following conditions: 

(a) The vocabulary of L contains: 

(1) The customary^ locutions of logic which are used in the 
formulation of sentences; including in particular the expressions '‘not,” 
“and,” “or,” “if . . . then . . . “all.” “some.” “the class of all 
things such that . . . “. . . is an element of class . . .”; 

(2) Certain observation predicates. These will be said to con- 
stitute the basic empirical vocabulary’ of L; 

(3) Any expression definable by means of those referred to 
under (1) and (2). 

(b) The rules of sentence formation for L are those laid down 
in some contemporary’ logical system such as Principia Mathematica, 

Since all defined terms can be eliminated in favor of primitives, 
these rules stipulate in effect that a language L is empiricist if all 
its sentences are expressible, with the help of the usual logical locu- 
tions, in terms of observable characteristics of physical objects. Let 
us call any language of this sort a thing-language in the narrower 
sense. Alternatively, the basic empirical vocabulary of an empiricist 
language might be construed as consisting of phenomenalistic terms, 
each of them referring to some aspect of the phenomena of per- 
ception or sensation. The construction of adequate phenomenalistic 
languages, however, presents considerable difiiculties,^^ and in recent 
empiricism, attention has been focussed primarily on the potential- 

14. Important contributions to the problem have been made by Carnap (5) and 
by Goodman (15). 


I 

f I CARL G. HEMPEL 

the descriS 5 aatv^ i? ; iMd lhemsd,es more direoly ,o 
voked in are ,cs. of scieSc hypSEer'’' 

the trankTaWUty SSS' 

00. ^ O^r r£“S '^feorSt- 3 ^ 

of the terms “aU” and “Sl- h" i.e., for the use 

is generally excluded from the r^l)' of quantified statement 

course; cognitively significant dis- 

do.o«'d 

nificant; ^ mi^ht be qualified as cognitively sig- 

M<irfeLS,“o!“?‘dentarot 7°eMe“' ™‘=' ““tom^S to Pmtciph 
of L. Honco, the mStli, "8“'" » '=”K”oe 
tequenco which is eotaiied by 4,™^ °f 'S'*,;” ‘I’VT 

attribute cognitive me^nin^*^toT//^"^^^’ criterion does not 

“The absolute s Set’’ fnd 

translated into an emS cisrl.^l cannot be 

not definable by means of nurefo1nc®“ i are 

terms. ^ ^°g'^al expressions and observation 

^oblem of Disposition Terms 
AND OF Theoretical Constructs 

aiso'iS’pmtesS"t” "«ri«ivo-as toe, incidentally 

cohsiderataTempaSsUailT,;”' ''^'=1“ ””” ‘=1'' fo^ 

(3.2). then, as liTe^S"' “ ““ordanee with 

allows cognitive import to a sentence onM O-D 

terms are explicitly definable bv ^ constitutive empirical 

as we shall a"rgu. p.2«2y miy e™s1 B« 

are not so definable^ hence dte'diterio. Snfdtbig'^fjtj'S: 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ 119 ] 

as devoid of cognitive import, all scientific hypotheses containing 
such terms — an altogether intolerable consequence. 

The concept of temperature is a case in point. At first glance, it 
seems as though the phrase “Object x has a temperature of c degrees 
centigrade,” or briefly “T(x) =c” could be defined by the follow- 
ing sentence, (D): T(x) — c if and only if the following condition 
is satisfied: If a thermometer is in contact with x, then it registers c 
degrees on its scale. 

Disregarding niceties, it may be granted that the denniens given 
here is formulated entirely in reference to obser\'abIes. However, it 
has one highly questionable aspect. In Principia Mathemntica and 
similar systems, the phrase “if p then is construed as being synon- 
ymous with “not p or and under this so-called material inter- 

pretation of the conditional a statement of the form “if p then 
is obviously true if (though not only if) the sentence standing in 
the place of is false. If, therefore, the meaning of “if . . . 
then . . in the definiens of (D) is understood in the material 
sense, then that definiens is true if (though not only if) x is an object 
not in contact with a thermometer — no matter what numerical value 
we may give to c. And since the definiendum would be true under 
the same circumstances, the definition (D) would qualify as true 
tlie assignment of any temperature value whatsoever to any object 
not in contact with a thermometer! Analogous considerations apply 
to such terms as “electrically charged,” “magnetic,” “intelligent,” 
“electric resistance,” etc., in short to aU disposition terms, i.e., terms 
which express the disposition of one or more objects to react in a 
determinate way under specified circumstances. A definition of such 
terms by means of observation predicates cannot be effected in the 
manner of (D), however natural and obvious a mode of definition 
this may at first seem to be.^^ 

There are two main directions in which a resolution of the diffi- 
culty might be sought. On the one hand, it could be argued that 
the definition of disposition terms in the manner of (D) is perfectly 
adequate provided that the phrase “if . . . then . . .” in the definiens 
is construed in the sense it is obviously intended to have, namely 
as implying, in the case of (D), that even if x is not actually in 
contact with a thermometer, still if it were in such contact, then the 
thermometer would register c degrees. In sentences such as this, 
the phrase “if . . . then ...” is said to be used counterfactually; 

15. This difficulty in the definition of disposition terms was first pointed out 
and analyzed by Camap (in (6); see esp. section 7). 


[ 120 ] 

.... . CARL G. HEMPEL 

ditionar sense, which implies a counterfactual con- 
araonal, that the defimens of (D) would have to be constnied Thic 
suggestion would provide an answer to the problem of definin<» dis 

account of the exact meamng of counterfactual conditionals seems 

he^tatua S a diSl y I.” 

the status of a program rather than that of a solution. The lack of 

nfn counterfactual conditionals is aU the more de- 

plorable as such a theory is needed also for the analysis of the con 

A H in empirical science and of certain related ideas 

^ ?n ffr “ the logic and methodology of science 

is --“S 

Tf o fh ^ pieans or the following reduction sentence fRV 

If a thermometer is in contact with an Sbject x, tLn fS - c if 
and only If the thermometer registers c degmes. ^ 

his rule, in which the conditional mav be constru<>d in th- 

n^triThTfoS^^if “temperaturrS:^^^^^^^^^ 

gradually extended to cases not covered in K^r ^ 

rurther redumion sentences, which reflect the meLuram»nrof 10^ 
perature by devices other than thermometers. 

ivcduction sentences tlms provid'^. a m^anc fr\r 
mulation^f what is commonly referred to as operational d^finhb.ns°is 

no avan'^oVr C. L Lewis would be of 

unWi^:^srde^a°d:/wTin^ 

based on empirical laws. For recent discuSfons ofThe m relationship, i. e., one 
see Langford (18); Lewis (20) no % 1 n oin ^ rh - ^ counterfactuals 
(14); Reichenbach (26), Chapter VIII- Goodman 

Popper (24). '-napter Vill, Hempel and Oppenheim (16), Part III; 

found in Camap^(7L^’Part'^'in The^na^al^Tfi^^'r" centra! idea may be 

the expression “T(x) = c” illustrates onlv^th^ formulated above for 

the so-called bilateral reducliofseSencI ^ 

see.1or°e” -- ‘^-eloped by Bridgman. 


i The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [111 ] 

j- At the same time, they show that the latter are not deiiiiitions in 
I the strict sense of the word, but rather partial specifications of 
I meaning, 

i The preceding considerations suggest that in our characteriza- 
I tion (3.2) of empiricist languages we broaden the provision ^ (3) 
j by permitting in the vocabulary of L all those terms whose mean- 
ing can be specified in terms of the basic empirical vocabular}' by 
I means of definitions or reduction sentences. Languages satisfying 
I this more inclusive criterion will be referred to as thing-languages 
I in the wider sense. 

I If the concept of empiricist language is broadened in this man- 
ner, then the translatability criterion (3.1) covers — as it should — 
also all those statements whose constituent empirical terms include 
‘‘empirical constructs,” i.e., terms which do not designate observ^ables, 
but which can be introduced by reduction sentences on the basis of 
observation predicates. 

Even in this generalized version, however, our criterion of cog- 
nitive meaning may not do justice to advanced scientific theories, 
wfiich are formulated in terms of “theoretical constructs,” such as 
the terms “absolute temperature,” “gravitational potential,” “electric 
field,” function,” etc. There are reasons to tiiink that neither 
definitions nor reduction sentences are adequate to introduce these 
terms on the basis of observ^ation predicates. Thus, e.g., if a system 
of reduction sentences for the concept of electric field were avail- 
able, then — to oversimplify the point a little — it would be possible 
to describe, in terms of observable characteristics, some necessary^ 
and some sufficient conditions for the presence, in a given region, 
of an electric field of any mathematical description, how^ever com- 
plex. Actually, however, such criteria can at best be given only for 
some sufficiently simple kinds of fields. 

Now' theories of the advanced type here referred to may be 
considered as hypothetico-deductive systems in which ail statements 
are logical consequences of a set of fundamental assumptions. Fun- 
damental as well as derived statements in such a system are formu- 
lated either in terms of certain theoretical constructs which are not 
defined within the system and thus play the role of primitives, or 
in terms of expressions defined by means of the latter. Thus, in 
their logical structure such systems equal the axiomatized uninter- 
preted systems studied in mathematics and logic. They acquire 
applicability to empirical subject matter, and thus the status of 
theories of empirical science, by virtue of an empirical interpretation. 
The latter is effected by a translation of some of the sentences of 


[ 122 ] CAKL G. HEMPEL 

the theory — often derived rather than fimdamental ones — into an 
empiricist language, which may contain both observation predicates 
and empirical constructs. And since the sentences which are thus 
given empirical meaning are logical consequences of the fundamental 
hypotheses of the theory, that translation effects, indirectly, a partial 
interpretation of the latter and of the constructs in terms of which 
they are formulated.^^ 

In order to make translatability into an empiricist language an 
adequate criterion of cognitive import, we broaden therefore the 
concept of empiricist language so as to include thing-languages in 
the narrower and in the wider sense as well as all interpreted theo- 
retical systems of the kind just referred to.^^ With this understanding, 
(3.1) may finally serve as a general criterion of cognitive meaning. 

5. On “the Meaning” of an Empirical Statement 

In effect, the criterion thus arrived at qualifies a sentence as 
cognitively meaningful if its nondogical constituents refer, directly 
or in certain specified indirect ways, to observables. But it does not 
make any pronouncement on what “the meaning” of a cognitively 
significant sentence is, and in particular it neither says nor implies 
that that meaning can be exhaustively characterized by what the 
totality of possible tests would reveal in terms of observable phe- 
nomena. Indeed, the content of a statement with empirical import 
cannot, in general, be exhaustively expressed by means of any class 
of observation sentences. 

For consider fiivSt, among the statements permitted by our cri- 
terion, any purely existential hypothesis or any statement involving 

19, The distinction between a formal deductive system and the empirical theory 
resulting from it by an interpretation has been elaborated in detail by Reicbenbach 
in his penetrating studies of the relations between pure and physical geometry'; cf., 
e. g., Reichenbach (25). The metliod by means of which a formal system is given 
empirical content is characterized by Reichenbach as “coordinating definition” of 
the primitives in the theory by means of specific empirical concepts. As is suggested 
by our discussion of reduction and the interpretation of theoretical construcis, how- 
ever, the process in question may have to be construed as a partial interpretation 
of the non-logical terms of the system rather than as a complete definition of the 
latter in terms of the concepts of a thing-language. 

20. These systems have not been characterized here as fully and as precisely as 
would be desirable. Indeed, the exact character of the empirical interpretation of 
theoretical constructs and of the theories in which they function is in need of further 
investigation. Some problems which arise in this connection — such as whether, or 
in what sense, theoretical constructs may be said to denote — are obviously also of 
considerable epistemological interest Some suggestions as to the interpretation of 
theoretical constructs may be found in Carnap (8), section 24, and in Kaplan (17); 
for an excellent discussion of the epistemological aspects of the problem, see 
Feigl (13). 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ 123 ] 

mixed quantiication. As was pointed out earlier, under {2,2) {a) y 
statements of these kinds entaU no observation sentences whatever; 
hence their content cannot be expressed by means of a class of ob- 
servation sentences. 

And secondly, even most statements of purely universal form 
(such as “All flamingoes are pink”) entail observation sentences 
(such as “That thing is pink”) only when combined with suitable 
other observation sentences (such as “That thing is a flamingo”). 

This last remark can be generalized. The use of empirical hypoth- 
eses for the prediction of observable phenomena requires, in practi- 
cally all cases, the use of subsidiary empirical hypotheses.^^ Thus, 
e.g., the hypothesis that the agent of tuberculosis is rod-shaped 
does not by itself entail the consequence that upon looking at a 
tubercular sputum specimen through a microscope, rod-like shapes 
will be observed: a large number of subsidiary hypotheses, including 
the theory of the microscope, have to be used as additional premises 
in deducing that prediction. 

Hence, what is sweepingly referred to as “the (cognitive) mean- 
ing” of a given scientific hypothesis cannot be adequately character- 
ized in terms of potential observational evidence alone, nor can it 
be specified for the hypothesis taken in isolation. In order to under- 
stand “the meaning” of a hypothesis within an empiricist language, 
we have to know not merely what observation sentences it entails 
alone or in conjunction with subsidiary hypotheses, but also what 
other, non-observational, empirical sentences are entailed by it, what 
sentences in the given language would confirm or disconfirm it, and 
for what other hypotheses the given one would be confirmatory^ or 
disconfirmatory. In other words, the cognitive meaning of a statement 
in an empiricist language is reflected in the totality of its logical rela- 
tionships to all other statements in that language and not to the ob- 
servation sentences alone. In this sense, the statements of empirical 
science have a surplus meaning over and above what can be ex- 
pressed in terms of relevant observation sentences.^^ 

6. The Logical Status of the 
Empiricist Criterion of Meaning 

What kind of a sentence, it has often been asked, is the empiri- 
cist meaning criterion itself? Plainly it is not an empirical hypothesis; 

21. This point is cleady taken into consideration in Ayer’s criteria of cognitive 
significance, which were discussed in section 2. 

22. For a fuller discussion of the issues here involved cf. Feigl (13) and the 
comments on Feigl’s position which will be published together with that article. 


[ 1Z4J 

1---* *4. • ■» , CARL G. HEMPEL 

by its ow^sSidSd.^ iSdeSoTcISS? 

what claim of soundness or vaUdity coul? p“if be^ mS 

indicates 

s'or-ri 

Sf fa rsu^rTotti^Snt 

gendered and even less with r controversies it has en- 

present article, that the changes inT^’ illustrated in the 

been determined by the obiective r>f content have always 

adequate index of cotmitive imnnrf criterion a more 

nates the character of thl em^- objective illumi- 

.ended ,o proSTa -"““"S. K ie in- 

sentence which makes an intPii' -w^ ^^P^ication of the idea of a 
nnnedly vague, a"?? TJ" ” ™a idea is ad- 

place it by a more orerkt- ^ . Philosophic explication to re- 
precision we cannot demand of^rn difference of 

plicandum.-’^ hU then !re 
exphcation, as expresld in , 0 ^ 

meaning? specific criterion of cognitive 

rather generally recS^nlze? as S’ m '^hich are 

another large class 0 /” which this is^ ^ intelligible assertions, and 
We shall have to demanTS af i "r 
account these spheres of common ^ai 

ist us say, denies cognitiv^moort tS’ “ ^^P^'cation which, 
to generalizations expressed iif terms ^^‘^"Pttons of past events or 
jected as inadequate As te ufj^ observables has to be re- 

~-d.s5S.s~ '^5;ssro"5l 

g"l”pLf HH'SSH'" Ts 

or i“the “woild oot 

in<^ m outline the explication of ih^ ®^P^Jcation in his article (9) which eram 
f? The’ Frege RiSSl' 

(30)_are outstkoding exaSnfe’s of defirdtion 

«n of various aspects of logical ana^:rTefkp^l^?"crp.^^^^^^ ^ 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ 125 | 

But an adequate explication of the concept of cognitively sig- 
nificant statement must satisfy yet another, even more important, 
requirement: together with the explication of certain other concepts, 
such as those of confirmation and of probability, it has to provide 
the framework for a general theoretical account of the structure and 
the foundations of scientific knowledge. Explication, as here under- 
stood, is not a mere description of the accepted usages of the terms 
under consideration: it has to go beyond the limitations, ambiguities, 
and inconsistencies of common usage and has to show how we had 
better construe the meanings of those terms if we wish to arrive at 
a consistent and comprehensive theory of knowledge. This type of 
consideration, which has been largely influenced by a study of the 
structure of scientific theories, has prompted the more recent exten- 
sions of the empiricist meaning criterion. These extensions are de- 
signed to include in the realm of cognitive significance various types 
of sentences which might occur in advanced scientific theories, or 
which have to be admitted simply for the sake of systematic simplicity 
and uniformity,-^ but on whose cognitive significance or non-signifi- 
cance a study of what the term “intelligible assertion” means in 
everyday discourse could hardly shed any light at all. 

As a consequence, the empiricist criterion of meaning, like the 
result of any other explication, represents a linguistic proposal which 
itself is neither true nor false, but for which adequacy is claimed in 
two respects: first in the sense that the explication provides a reason- 
ably close analysis of the commonly accepted meaning of the ex- 
piicandum — and this claim implies an empirical assertion; and sec- 
ondly in the sense that the explication achieves a "'rational recon- 
struction” of the explicandum, i.e., that it provides, together perhaps 
with other explications, a general conceptual framework which per- 
mits a consistent and precise restatement and theoretical systematiza- 
tion of the contexts in which the explicandum is used — and this claim 
implies at least an assertion of a logical character. 

Though a proposal in form, the empiricist criterion of meaning 
is therefore far from being an arbitrary definition; it is subject to 
revision if a violation of the requirements of adequacy, or even a 
way of satisfying those requirements more fully, should be discov- 

25. Thus, e. g., our criterion qualifies as significant certain statements contain- 
ing, say, thousands of existential or universal quantifiers — even though such sen- 
tences may never occur in everyday nor perhaps even in scientific discourse. For 
ind^d, from a systematic point of view it would be arbitrary and unjustifiabie to 
limit the class of significant statements to those containing no more than some fixed 
number of quantifiers. For further discussion of this point, cf. Carnap (6), sections 
17, 24, 25. 


[ 126 ] 

^ j T j j • . CARL G, BDEMPEL 

nrnhi ^ that before long some of the ooen 


bibliographic references 

Logic, Gollancz, London, 1936; 

journal of Philos.. 

CofS’YoriT'iS" Macmillan 

(4) “Operational Analysis” (Philos, of Science. 

(6) cSSao R ’ ”T^ ®®"hn, 1928. 

• a^nd 

(7) Carnap, R., Logical Foundations of the Unitv of t 

> "" wv.'rai"' 

(9) Caman R ’ “Th^ science, I, 3, Umv. of Chicago Press, 1939. 

LA i"r ?T9?5) °' 

“““"'isfs,”- C„„di.i0.al- 

vlTfiXTlT 52-^: “'■ 

Sof's? ■' l’g°“r‘;°Af ^ "“ 5“''“= M'ftol- (i>.9yc/,o/. 

j PMd ;„ alaaw “A rsr' 

?CX LAolA'S,? 

(15) G»<ln.«.^N, rfe 5 ,„„„„ App„.. H.mri U.ive„ity 

(16) Hempel, C. G., and Oppenheim P “Studip<! in tfiA • f t: 

<.l‘l•ihs. of ScUnce, Vol’isf ms) ®’‘' 

o/pmAvoAA™)”"" “f normal 

(18) Wfort. C^H,^Re,i» i„ rfe , 00 . 00 , p, Spmi. Lop,.. Vol. 6 


The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ ] 

(19) Lecomte du Noiiy, Human Destiny, New York, London, Toronto, 

1947. 

(20) Lewis, C. L, An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, Open 
Court Pub!., La Salle, 111., 1946. 

(21) Pap, A., Elements of Analytic Philosophy, The Macmillan Co., 
New York, 1949. 

(22) Popper, K., Logik der Forschung, Springer, Vienna, 1935. 

(23) Popper, K., The Open Society and Its Enemies, 2 vols., Routledge, 
London, 1945. 

(24) Popper, K., “A Note on Natural Laws and So-called ‘Contrary-to- 
Fact Conditionals’ ” {Mind, VoL 58, 1949). 

(25) Reichenbach, H., Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre, Berlin, 1928. 

(26) Reichenbach, H., Elements of Symbolic Logic, The Macmillan Co., 
New York, 1947. 

(27) Russell, B., Human Knowledge, Simon and Schuster, New York, 

1948. 

(28) Schiick, M., “Meaning and Verification” (Philos. Review, Vol. 45, 
1936). (Also reprinted in Feigl and SeUars, Readings in Philo- 
sophical Analysis, New York, 1949). 

(29) Stace, W. T. “Positivism” (Mind, Vol. 53, 1944). 

(30) Tarski, A., “The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Founda- 
tions of Semantics” (Philos, and Phcnorn. Research, Vol. 4, 
1944). (Also reprinted in Feigl and Sellars, Readings in Philo- 
sophical Analysis, New York, 1949.) 

(31) Werkmeister, W. H., The Basis and Structure of Knowledge, 
Harper, New York and London, 1948. 

(32) Whitehead, A. N., and Russell, B., Principia Mathemaiica, 3 vols., 
2nd ed., Cambridge, 1925-1927. 


REMARKS BY THE AUTHOR (1958) 

If I were to write a revised version of this article, I would qualify the 
objections (2.1) (b) and (2.2) (b) against complete verihability or falsi- 
fiabHity as criteria of empirical meaningfulness, or empirical significance. 
The first of these objections argues that if a sentence S is empirically sig- 
nificant under the verifiability criterion, then so is 5 v N, even when N 
is cognitively meaningless in the sense of being (i) neither analytic nor 
self-contradictory and (ii) devoid of empirical meaning in the sense of 
the verifiability criterion; for whatever class of observation sentences com- 
pletely verifies S also completely verifies SvN, since SyN is & logical 
consequence of S, — But the rule underlying this latter assertion, i.e., the 
rule that an alternation is logically implied by either of its components, 
applies only if N, no less than S, is a statement, i.e. a sentence which is 
either true or false; and if the verifiability criterion is taken to characterize 
all sentences, other than the analytic and the self-contradictory ones, 


CARL G. HElvfPEL 


[128] 

wMcli can significantly be said to be either true or false, then clearly N 
cannot be significantly said to be either true or false and thus is no state- 
ment at all; hence the inference from S to SvN falls. — ^The case against 
objection (2.2) (b) is analogous.^ However, the latter objection still ap- 
plies against the view of those who propound faisifiability as a criterion 
which will separate off the statements of empirical science from those of 
logic and mathematics and from those of metaphysics, without denying 
truth or falsity to the latter. For then S.N qualifies as a significant scien- 
tific statement if S does, even though be a purely metaphysical utter- 
ance. The remaining arguments mentioned in section 2 of my article 
seems to me fully sufficient, however, to disqualif}’ both complete veri- 
fiability and complete faisifiability as criteria of cognitive significance. 

I have more serious doubts concerning the idea of a transl at ability 
criterion of the kind proposed in sections 3 and 4 of the article. For the 
notion of translatability needed in this context is by no means fully clear, 
and an attempt to explicate it faces considerable difficulties.- It seems 
desirable, therefore, to do without that idea. In a sequeF to the anicle 
here under consideration, I did just that and considered instead the pos- 
sibility of characterizing cognitively significant sentences as being built 
up, according to specified syntactical rules, from a given logical vocabu- 
lary and from cognitively (better: empirically) significant terms; each 
of the latter would have to be either an observational predicate or an 
expression connected with a set of observational terms by sentences of 
specified types, such as definitions or reduction sentences, wnich could 
then be said to introduce the non-observational term in question.-^ There 
remains the problem of specifying the types of sentences which are to 
be permissible for this purpose. This issue, which is briefly examined in 
section 4 of the present article, has been dealt with in much greater 
detail in two more recent essays of mine.^ 

1. A criticism to this effect was put forth some years ago by students in a 
graduate seminar of mine; recently, the same point was made explicitly and 
forcefully by D. Rynin in his presideniiai address, “Vindication of 

Proceedings and Addresses of The American Philosophical Asso- 
ciation, Vol. 30 (1957), p. 45-67; cf. especially pp. 57-58. 

2. Tnis has recently been pointed out veiy^ lucidly by I. SchefBer in “Prospects 
of a Modest Empiricism,” The Review of Metaphysics, Vol 10, pp, 383-400, 602- 
625 (1957); cf. especially sections 7-11. 

3. C. G. Hempel, “The Concept of Cognitive Significance: A Reconsideration,” 
Proc. Amer. Acad, of Arts and Sciences, Vol. 80, No. 1, pp. 61-77 (1951). 

4. This procedure seems closely related in spirit to one recently suggested by 
Scheffler (loc. cit., section 9), namely replacement of the irajosiatabiiity' condition 
by the following criterion: S is cognitively significant if and only if it w a sentence 
of some empiricist language. 

5. “A Logical Appraisal of Operationism,” The Scientific Monthly, Vol. 79, 
pp. 215-220 (1954), reprinted in Philipp Frank, ed., The Validation of Scientific 
Theories, the Beacon Press, Boston, 1957. — “The Theoretician’s Dilemma,” in H. 
Feigl, M. Scriven, and G. Maxwell, eds., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of 
Science, Vol. IL University of Minnesota Press, 1958. For a critical discussion of 
the issues raised in these articles, see especially R. Carnap, “The Methodoiogicai 
Character of Theoretical Concepts,” in H. Feigl and M. Scriven, eds., Minnesota 



The Empiricist Criterion of Meaning [ 129 ] 

But BO matter how one might reasonably delimit the class of sen- 
tences qualified to introduce empirically significant terms, this new ap- 
proach seems to me to lead to the realization that cognitive significance 
cannot well be construed as a characteristic of individual sentences, 
but only of more or less comprehensive systems of sentences (corre- 
sponding roughly to scientific theories). A closer study of this point 
suggests strongly that, much like the analytic-synthetic distinction, the 
idea of cognitive significance, with its suggestion of a sharp distinction 
between significant and non-significant sentences or systems of such, has 
lost its promise and fertility as an explicandum, and that it had better be 
replaced by certain concepts which admit of differences in degree, such 
as the formal simplicity of a system; its explanatory and predictive power; 
and its degree of confirmation relative to available evidence.® The analy- 
sis and theoretical reconstruction of these concepts seems to offer the 
most promising way of advancing further the clarification of the issues 
implicit in the idea of cognitive significance. 


Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. I. University of Minnesota Press, 1956; 
and sections 12-19 of SchefSer’s article cited in note 28. 

6. This point is developed in detail in my anicle cited in note 3. 







6 


The Old and the New Logic 

BY RUDOLF CARNAP 
(translated by ISAAC LEVi) 


1. Logic as a Method of Philosophizing 

The new series of this journal, which begins with this volume, 
will be devoted to the development of a new, scientific method of 
philosophizing. Perhaps this method can be briefly characterized as 
consisting in the logical analysis of the statements and concepts of 
empirical science. This description indicates the two most important 
features that distinguish this method from the methods of traditional 
philosophy. First, this type of philosophizing goes strictly hand in 
hand vith empirical science. Thus, philosophy is no longer viewed 
as a domain of knowledge in its own right, on a par with, or superior 
to, the empirical sciences. Secondly, this description indicates the 
part that philosophy plays in empirical science: it consists in the 
clarification of the statements of empirical science; more specifically, 
in the decomposition of statements into their parts (concepts), the 
step by step reduction of concepts to more fundamental concepts 
and of statements to more fundamental statements. This way of 
setting the problem brings out the value of logic for philosophical 
enquiries. Logic is no longer merely one philosophical discipline 
among others, but we are able to say outright: Logic is the method 
of philosophizing. Logic is understood here in the broadest sense. 
It comprehends pure, formal logic and applied logic or the theory 
of knowledge. 

The desire to replace metaphysical concept-poetry by a rigorous, 
scientific method of philosophizing would have remained a pious 
hope if the system of traditional logic had been the only logic^ in- 

This article, originally entitled “Die alte und die neue Logik,” appeared in the first 
issue of Erkenntnis. Vol. I of Erkenntnis (1930-31) was at the same time Vol. IX of 
Annalen der Philosophie (see Editor’s Introduction, p. 6 above).. It is published here 
with the kind permission of Professor Camap. 



[ 133 ] 



[ 134 ] 

, . RUDOLF CARNAP 

' av^able. Traditional logic was totally incapable of satisfy 

grists ns “iS 

tadt,duSr.t'SS' there Meed a peat many 

—g iantiSr/ =i.“BTStpn' SMS 

raSSMeTtageMSM “M".*'!' «”™ed at a 

SS Tdl " M'preSfSceMM'thS 

SdtaSSf tierenntoed by the inadequacy o7its fomtal 

the S?aSdSLS meSSSS h'™" “t' 

Tf ’’““f 

SeVSpSSSnTora"SS“ f" 

at first envisnapH Th significant nature were not 

S tie SoSaS „I thenw"? P“^f Phere have even now taken 
vantaae f “S for “‘""cted even less ad- 

easy .i™.d.°y S Sch theraoMch 

vent the new lo"ic is strii'ino^ Tn ht^ generally, circum- 

by mathematics'"fricrhtf>r,c ^ ^ formal garb demanded 

SSSifHSSSSS 

the old philosophy is to he " advMates — hes the point at which 
inexorable Idment of the t’"^ ““S't- Before the 

sense, wuMM^oIuMM °f MtCM *” ""t 

Kr°a ?T,‘- MSyM 

materially ^ Proyes itself to be not merely 

and therefore meM£s."''‘“ ™»nnhle 

2. The New Logic 

last^enm^ FoUowIm ^on° decades of the 

earlier contributions (De MorganM^iTooklstSMl, 


The Old and the New Logic [ 135 ] 

and Schroder made the first attempts at a new and comprehensive 
reconstruction of logic. On the basis of this previous work, White- 
head and Russell created the great basic work of the new logic, Frm- 
cipia Mathematica (1910-1913). All further contributions to the 
new logic depend upon this work. They attempt either to supplement 
or revise it. (A few names may be mentioned here; the Gottingen 
School: Hilbert, Ackermann, Bemays, Behmann, et al; the Warsaw 
School: Lukasiewicz, Lesniewski, Chwistek, Tarski, et al; Wittgen- 
stein and his associate Ramsey.) 

The most important stimulus for the development of the new 
logic lay in the need for a critical re-examination of the foundations 
of mathematics. Mathematics, especially since the time of Leibniz 
and Newton, had made enormous advances and acquired an abun- 
dance of new knowledge. But the securing of the foundations had 
not kept in step with the rapid growth of the edifice. Therefore, about 
a centur}^ ago, a more vigorous effort began to be made to clarify 
the fundamental concepts. This effort was successful in many in- 
stances. Mathematicians succeeded in defining in a rigorous form 
such important concepts as, for example, limit, derivative and com- 
plex number. For a long time, these concepts had been fruitfully 
applied in practice without having adequate definitions. We have 
only the sure instincts of great mathematicians and not the clarity 
of concepts to thank for the fact that the inadequacy of the concept 
formation caused no mischief in mathematics. 

Efforts at a clarification of fundamental concepts went forward 
step by step. People were not satisfied with reducing the various 
concepts of mathematical analysis to the fundamental concept of 
number; they required that the concept of number should itself be 
logically clarified. This inquirv^ into the logical foundations of arith- 
meric with a logical analysis of number as its goal, called peremptorily 
for a logical system which had the comprehensiveness and precision 
to do the work demanded of it. Thus, these inquiries gave an es- 
pecially strong impetus to the development of the new logic. Peano, 
Frege, Whitehead, Russell and Hilbert were led to do their work 
on logic primarily for this reason. 

The necessity for a new reconstruction of logic became even 
more pressing wfien certain contradictions (“antinomies”) were no- 
ticed in the realm of mathematics which soon proved themselves to 
be of a general, logical nature. These contradictions could be over- 
come only by a fundamental reconstruction of logic. 

In the following pages, some of the important characteristics of 
the new logic will be stated. Above all, mention will be made of 


[ I RUDOLF CARNAP 

those traits which distinguish the new logic from the old and by 
means of which the new logic has gained a special significance for 
Ae whole of science. First we shall take a look at the symbolic garb 
in which the new logic customarily appears. Then a few remarks 
will be made about the enrichment in content which consists pri- 
marily in taking account of relations instead of restricting oneself 
to predicates. In addition, it will be briefly shown how the contra- 
dictions to which we have just referred are overcome by the so-called 
theory of types. After dealing with these points, which are significant 
chiefly for logic itself, we shall examine the several points of general 
scientific importance: the possibility of deriving mathematics from 
logic; the explanation of the essentially tautological character of logi- 
cal sentences, a point which is ver^^ important for philosophy; the 
analysis of concepts by means of which science is rendered a unified 
whole; and finally the elimination of metaphysics by logical analysis. 

3. The Symbolic Method 

When a reader looks at a treatise in modern logic, the first out- 
ward feature that strikes him is the use of symbolic forms which 
appear similar to those of mathematics. This symbolism was orisi- 
naJy' constructed in imitation of mathematics. However, forms more 
suitable for the special purposes oi logic were subsequently developed. 

in^ mathematics, the advantage of the symbolic method of repre- 
sentation over verbal language is obvious. Consider the sentence: “if 
one number is multiplied by another, the result is the same as that 
obtained by multiplying the second by the first.” It is evidently much 
clearer and more convenient to say, “For any numbers x and y, 
iT IS the case that x.y = y.x” or more briefly, using the logical sif’n 
for universality, “(a, y).x.y=:y..x.” - - - - 

_ By _ employing symbolism "in logic, inferences acquire a rigor 
which IS otherwise unobtainable. Inferences are made by means^of 
arithmetical operations on formulae analogous to calculations (hence 
the designation “calculus,” “propositional calculus,” “functional cal- 
culus”). To be sure, material considerations guide the course of 
deduction, but they do not enter into the deduction itself. This 
method guarantees that no unnoticed assumptions will slip into the 
deduction, a thing which it is very difficult to avoid in a word- 
language. Such deductive rigor is especiallv important in the axio- 
matoation of any domain, e.g. geometry. The history of geometry 
furmshes numerous examples of impure deductions, such as the vari- 
ous attempts to derive the axiom of parallels from the other axioms 


The Old and the New Logic [ ] 

of Euclidean geometry. A sentence equivalent to the axiom of paral- 
lels was always tacitly assumed and employed in these derivations. 
Rigor and neatness is required in the constitution of concepts just as 
much as in the derivation of sentences. With the methods of the new 
logic, analysis has shown that many philosophical concepts do not 
satisfy the higher standards of rigor; some have to be interpreted 
differently and others have to be eliminated as meaningless. (See 
Section 9 below\) 

As will become clearer presently, the theory of knowledge, which 
is after all nothing but applied logic, can no more dispense with 
symbolic logic than physics can dispense with mathematics. 

4. The Logic of Relations 

The new logic is distinguished from the old not only by the 
form in which it is presented but chieSy also by the increase of its 
range. The most important new domains are the theor}^ of relational 
sentences and the theory of sentential functions. Only the theory- of 
relations will be (briefly) considered here. 

The only form of statements (sentences) in the old logic was the 
predicative form: "‘Socrates is a man/' "All (or some) Greeks are 
men.” A predicate-concept or property is attributed to a subject- 
concept. Leibniz had already put fonvard the demand that logic 
should consider sentences of relational form. In a relational sentence 
such as, for example, "a is greater than b,” a relation is attributed 
to two or more objects, (or. as it might be put, to several subject- 
concepts). Liebniz's idea of a theory of relations has been worked 
out by the new logic. The old logic conceived relational sentences 
as sentences of predicative form. However, many inferences involv- 
ing relational sentences thereby become impossible. To be sure, one 
can interpret the sentence “a is greater than b” in such a way that 
the predicate "greater than b" is attributed to the subject a. But 
the predicate then becomes a unity; one cannot extract b by any 
rule of inference. Consequently, the sentence "b is smaller than a” 
cannot be inferred from this sentence. In the new logic, this infer- 
ence takes place in the following way: The relation “smaller than” 
is defined as the “converse” of the relation “greater than.” The in- 
ference in question then rests on the universal proposition: If a 
relation holds between x and y, its converse holds between y and x. 
A further example of a statement that cannot be proved in the old 
logic: “Wherever there is a victor someone is vanquished.” In the 


1 138 1 

^ ■* RUDOLF CARNAP 

new logic, this follows from the logical proposition: If a relation 
has a referent, it also has a relatum. 

Relational statements are especially indispensable for the mathe- 
matical sciences. Let us consider as an example the geometrical 
rancep^f the three-place relation “between” (on an open straight 
ime) Tht geometrical axioms “If a lies between b and c, b does 
not he between c and a” can be expressed only in the new logic. 
According to the predicative view, in the first case we would have 
?” between b and c” and “lying between c and 

. If these are left unanalyzed, there is no way of showing how the 
first is tramformed into the second. If one takes the objects b and 
c out of the predicate, the statement “a lies between b and c” no 
lonpr serves to characterize only one object, but three. It is therefore 
a three-place relational statement. 

“between” are of such a kind 
that the order of their terms cannot be altered at wHI. The deter- 

™ domain rests essentially on relations 
of this kind. If among a class of persons it is known which of any 

persons is thereby serially ordered. It 

asc$DtiMs^^ n predicative 

^nptions— namely, by attributing a definite measure as .a property 

ih f ™ ^bat case it would again have to be assumed 

that with respect to any two of these quantities, it was known which 

instructed This shows the indispensability of the theory of fela- 

"“nd orderings: 

(number senes), geometry (point series), physics (all 

sta« mainSsr“°‘' 

Restnction to predicate-sentences has had disastrous effects on 
objects outside logic. Perhaps Russell is right when he made t£s 
logical failing responsible for certain metaphysical errors If everv 
sentence attributes a predicate to a subject; there can after aS b^ 

Sn ^nd every state of affairs must con- 

^t m the possession of a certam attribute by the Absolute. In the 

^^taphysical theories about mysterious “sub- 
stances could be traced to this mistake. 

a ^ certain that this restriction has for 

a long time been a senous drag upon physics-^.g., the idea that 

rr philosoVcal sfnse. Above S! 

coticpnf 7 ^k logical error is responsible for the 

concept of absolute space. Because the fundamental form of a prop- 


The Old and the New Logic [ ] 

osition had to be predicative, it could only consist in the specification 
of the position of a body. Since Leibniz had recognized the possi- 
bility of relational sentences, he was able to arrive at a correct 
conception of space: the elementaiy^ fact is not the position of a 
body but its positional relations to other bodies. He upheld the view 
on epistemological grounds: there is no way of determining the abso- 
lute position of a body, but only its positional relations. His campaign 
in favor of the relativistic view of space, as against the absolutistic 
views of the followers of Newton, had as little success as his pro- 
gram for logic. 

Only after two hundred years were his ideas on both subjects 
taken up and carried through: in logic with the theoiy’ of relations 
(De Morgan 1858; Peirce 1870), in physics with the theor>^ of rela- 
tivity (anticipator}^ ideas in Mach 1SS3; Einstein 1905). 

5. The Logical Antinomies 

Around the turn of the centur}', certain strange contradictions 
(‘‘paradoxes”) appeared in the new mathematical discipline of set 
theor}^ Closer investigation soon showed that these contradictions 
were not specifically mathematical but were of a general logical 
character, the so-called “logical antinomies." The new logic had not 
yet developed to the point where it was able to overcome these 
contradictions. This was a defect which it shared with the old logic, 
and it provided a further motive for rebuilding the system of logic 
from its foundations. Russell succeeded in eliminating the contra- 
dictions by means of the “theoiy of upes.” The gulf betw'een the 
new and the old logic thereby became sail wider. The old logic is 
not only significantly poorer in content than the new. but, because 
the contradictions are not removed from it, it no longer counts at all. 
(Most logical textbooks are still unaware of this.) 

Let us consider the simplest example of an antinomy (foD owing 
Russell). A concept is to be called “predicable” if it is applicable to 
itself. For example: The concept “abstract” is abstract. A concept 
is to be called “impredicable” if it does not apply to itself. For 
example: The concept “virtuous” is not virtuous. According to the 
law of excluded middle, the concept “impredicable” is either predi- 
cable or impredicable. Assume that it is predicable; then, according 
to the definition of “predicable,” it can 1^ ascribed to itself and is, 
therefore, impredicable. Assume that the concept “impredicable” is 
impredicable; then the concept is ascribed to itself; consequently, 
according to the definition of “predicabie,” it is predicabie. There- 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


[ 140 ] 

fore, both assumptions are self-contradictory. There are many similar 
antinomies. 

The theory of types consists in the fact that all concepts, both 
properties and relations, are classified according to “types.” For 
simplicity’s sake, let us restrict ourselves to properties. A distinction 
is made between “individuals,” i.e. objects which are not properties 
(zero level); properties of individuals (first level); properties of 
properties of individuals (second level) and so on. Let us take for 
example bodies to be individuals; then “square” and “red” are prop- 
erties of the first level; “spatial property” and “color” are properties 
of the second level. The theory of types says: a property of the first 
level can be attributed or denied only to individuals but cannot 
apply to properties of the first or higher levels at all; a property of 
the second level can be attributed or denied only to properties of 
the first level but cannot apply to individuals or to properties of the 
second or higher levels, and so on. For example: If a and b are 
bodies, the sentences “a is square” and “b is red” are either true 
or false but in either case meaningful. Further, the sentences “Square- 
ness is a spatial property” and “Red is a color” are true. On the 
other hand, the series of words “a is a spatial property,” “Square- 
ness is red” and “Color is a spatial property” are neither true nor 
false but meaningless. They are mere pseudo-sentences. Such pseudo- 
sentences are avoided if a property of the nth level is" applied only 
to concepts of the level n-1. A particularly important special case 
follows from this: The assumption that a certain property belongs 
or does not belong to itself can be neither true nor false, .but is 
meaningless. 

As one can easily see, if the rules of the theory of types are 
obeyed, the above-mentioned antinomy of “impredicable” does not 
arise. For the stated definitions of “predicable” and impredicable” 
cannot be formulated. They are therefore meaningless. The remaining 
antinomies which have not been referred to here can be eliminated 
in a similar manner. 

6. Mathematics as a Branch of Logic 

As has been mentioned, the logical analysis of arithmetic is one of 
the goals of the new logic. Frege had already come to the conclusion 
that mathematics is to be considered a branch of logic. This view was 
confirmed by Whitehead and Russell who carried through the con- 
struction of the system of mathematics on the basis of logic. It was 
shown that every mathematical concept can be derived from the 
fundamental concepts of logic and that every mathematical sentence 


The Old and the New Logic [ 

(insofar as it is valid in every conceivable domain of any size) can 
be derived from the fundamental statements of logic. 

The most important concepts of the new logic (they are in part 
reducible to one another) are the following: 1. Negation: “not”; 

2. the logical connectives for two sentences: “and,” “or,” “if — ^then”; 

3. “every” (or “all”), “there is”; 4. “identical.” The possibHity of 
deriving arithmetical concepts may be illustrated by a simple ex- 
ample: the number two as a cardinal, i.e., as the number of a concept. 
Definition: “The cardinal number of a concept f is nvo” is to mean 
“There is an x and there is a y such that x is not identical with y, x 
falls under f, y fails under f, and for every z it is the case that if z 
falls under f, z is identical with x or with y.” We see that only the 
logical concepts which have just been listed are employed in this 
definition of “two”; this can be shown rigorously only in a symbolic 
representation. All the natural numbers can be defined in a similar 
manner. Furthermore, the positive and negative numbers, fractions, 
real numbers, complex numbers, and finally even the concepts of 
analysis — ^limit, convergence, derivative, integral, continuity, etc. — 
can also be defined in this way. 

Since every mathematical concept is derived from the funda- 
mental concepts of logic, every mathematical sentence can be trans- 
lated into a sentence about purely logical concepts; and this transla- 
tion is then deducibie (under certain conditions, as has been 
indicated) from the fundamental logical sentences. Let us take as 
an example the arithmetical sentence Its translation into 

a sentence of pure logic reads: “If a property f has the cardinal 
number 1 and a property g has the cardinal number 1, and f and g 
are mutually exclusive, and if the concept h is the union of f and g, 
then h has the cardinal number 2.” This translation represents a 
sentence from the logic of properties (theoiy of sentential functions) 
which is derivable from the fundamental sentences of logic. In a 
similar way, all the remaining sentences of arithmetic and analysis 
(to the extent that they are universally valid in the widest sense) 
are provable as sentences of logic. 

7. The Tautological Character of Logic 

On the basis of the new logic, the essential character of logical 
sentences can be clearly recognized. This has become of the greatest 
importance for the theory of mathematical knowledge as w'eli as for 
the clarification of controversial philosophical questions. 

The usual distinction in logic between fundamental and derived 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


[ ^<2 ] 

sentences is arbitrary. It is immaterial whether a logical sentence is 
derived from other sentences. Its validity can be recognized from its 
form. This may be illustrated by a simple example. 

With the aid of the logical connectives, one can construct other 
sentences from two sentences “A” and '‘B”, e.g., “not-A,” “A or B,” 
“A and B.” The truth of these compound sentences obviously does 
not depend upon the meanings of the sentences “A” and “B” but 
only upon their truth-values, i.e., upon whether they are true or 
fal^. Now there are four combinations of truth-values for “A” and 
“B,” namely, 1. “A” is true and “B” is true: TT, 2. TF, 3. FT, 4. 
FF. The meaning of a logical connective is determined by the fact 
that the sentences constructed with the help of this connective are 
true in certain of the four possible cases and false in the others. For 
example, the meaning of “or” (in the non-exclusive sense) is de- 
termined by the stipulation that the sentence ‘'A or B’’ is true in 
the first three cases and false in the fourth. Compound sentences 
can be combined further to make new compound sentences. Let us 
take as an example: “(tiot-A and not-B) or (A or B).” We can 
now establish the truth-values in the four cases first for the con- 
stituent sentences and then for the sentence as a whole. We thereby 
in this example arrive at a remarkable result. ‘‘Not-A” is true only 
in the third and fourth cases. “Not-B is tnie only in the second and 
fourth cases. Consequently, “not-A and not-B’' is true only in the 
fourth case. 


A B 


T 

T 

F 

F 


not-A 

F 

F 

T 

T 


not-B 

F 

T 

F 

T 


not-A 

and 

not-B 

F 

F 

F 

T 


A or B 


T 

T 

T 

F 


( not-A and 
not-B) or 
(A orB) 

T 

T 

T 

T 


“A or B” is true in the first three cases. Therefore, the entire sentence 
“(not-A and not-B) or (A or B)” is true in every case. Such a 
formula, which depends neither on the meanings nor the truth- 
values of the sentences occurring in it but is necessarily true, whether 
its constituent sentences are true or false, is called a tautology. A 
tautology is true in virtue of its mere form. It can be shown that aU 
the sentences of logic and, hence, according to the view advocated 
here, all the sentences of mathematics are tautologies. 

If a compound sentence is communicated to us, e.g., “It is rain- 


The Old and the New Logic [ 143 ] 

ing here and now or it is snowing/’ we learn something about reality. 
This is so because the sentence excludes certain of the relevant 
states-of-affairs and leaves the remaining ones open. In our example, 
there are four possibilities: 1. It is raining and snowing, 2. It is 
raining and not snowing, 3. It is not raining but it is snowing, 4. It 
is not raining and not snowing. The sentence excludes the fourth 
possibility and leaves the first three open. If, on the other hand, we 
are told a tautology, no possibility is excluded but they all remain 
open. Consequently, we learn nothing about reality from the 
tautology, e.g., “It is raining (here and now) or it is not raining.’’ 
Tautologies, therefore, are empt}*'. They say nothing; they have, 
so-to-speak, zero-content. However, they need not be trivial on this 
account. The above-mentioned tautology is trivial. On the other 
hand, there are other sentences whose tautological character cannot 
be recognized at first glance. 

Since ail the sentences of logic are tautological and devoid of 
content, we cannot draw inferences from them about what was 
necessary or impossible in reality. Thus the attempt to base meta- 
physics on pure logic which is chiefly characteristic of such a system 
as Hegel’s, is shown to be unwarranted. 

Mathematics, as a branch of logic, is also tautological. In the 
Kantian terminology^: The sentences of mathematics are analytic. 
They are not synthetic a priori. Apriorism is thereby deprived of its 
strongest argument. Empiricism, the view that there is no synthetic 
a priori knowledge, has always found the greatest difficulty in inter- 
preting mathematics, a difficulty which Mill did not succeed in 
overcoming. This difficulty is removed by the fact that mathematical 
sentences are neither empirical nor synthetic a priori but analytic. 

8. Unified Science 

We distinguish applied logic ^ the logical analysis of the concepts 
and sentences of the different branches of science, from pure logic 
with its formal problems. Though up to now most of the work in the 
new logic has dealt with formal subjects, it has also attained successful 
results in this domain. 

The analysis of the concepts of science has shown that all these 
concepts, no matter whether they belong, according to the usual 
classification, to the natural sciences, or to psychology or the social 
sciences, go back to a common basis. They can be reduced to root 
concepts which apply to the “given,” to the content of immediate 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


[ 144 ] 

experience. To begin with, all concepts relating to one’s own ex- 
perience, i.e. those which apply to the psychological events of the 
knowing subject, can be traced back to the given. Ail physical con- 
cepts can be reduced to concepts relating to one’s own experience, 
for every physical event is in principle confirmable by means of 
perceptions. All concepts relating to other minds, that is, those that 
apply to the psychological processes of subjects other than oneself, 
are constituted out of physical concepts. Finally the concepts of the 
social sciences go back to concepts of the kinds just mentioned. 
Thus, a genealogical tree of concepts results in which every concept 
must in principle find its place according to the way it is derived 
from other concepts and ultimately from the given. The constitution 
theory, i.e. the theoiy^ of the construction of a system of all scientific 
concepts on a common basis, shows further that in a corresponding 
manner every statement of science can be retranslated into a state- 
ment about the given (“methodological positivism”). 

A second constitution system, which likewise includes all con- 
cepts, has physical concepts for its basis, i.e., concepts which apply to 
events in space and time. The concepts of psychology and the social 
sciences are reduced to physical concepts according to the principle 
of behaviorism (“methodological materialism”). 

We speak of “methodological” positivism or materialism because 
we are concerned here only with methods of deriving concepts, 
while completely eliminating both the metaphysical thesis of positiv- 
ism about the reality of the given and the metaphysical thesis of 
materialism about the reality of the physical world. Consequently, 
the positivist and materialist constitution systems do not contradict 
one another. Both are correct and indispensable. The positivist 
system corresponds to the epistemological viewpoint because it proves 
the validity of knowledge by reduction to the given. The materialist 
system corresponds to the view-point of the empirical sciences, for 
in this system all concepts are reduced to the physical, to the only 
domain which exhibits the complete rule of law and makes inter- 
subjective knowledge possible. 

Thus, with the aid of the new logic, logical analysis leads to a 
unified science. There are not different sciences with fundamentally 
different methods or different sources of knowledge, but only one 
science. All knowledge finds its place in this science and, indeed, is 
knowledge of basically the same kind; the appearance of fundamental 
differences between the sciences are the deceptive result of our using 
different sub-languages to express them. 


The Old and the New Logic 


[145] 


9. The Elimination of Metaphysics 

The tautological character of lo^c shows that all inference is 
tautological. The conclusion always says the same as the premises 
(or less), but in a different linguistic form. One fact can never be 
inferred from another. (According to the usual view this does occur 
in inductive inference, but this subject cannot be discussed here.) 
From this follows the impossibility of any metaphysics which tries 
to draw inferences from experience to something transcendent which 
lies beyond experience and is not itself experiencable; e.g. the “thing 
in itself” lying behind the things of experience, the “Absolute” 
behind the totality of the relative, the “essence” and “meaning” of 
events behind the events themselves. Since rigorous inference can 
never lead from experience to the transcendent, metaphysical infer- 
ences must leave out essential steps. The appearance of transcendence 
stems from this. Concepts are introduced which are irreducible either 
to the given or to the physical. They are therefore mere illusory 
concepts which are to be rejected from the epistemological viewpoint 
as well as from the scientific viewpoint. No matter how much they 
are sanctified fay tradition and charged with feeling, they are mean- 
ingless words. 

With the aid of the rigorous methods of the new logic, we can 
treat science to a thoroughgoing process of decontamination. Ever}’ 
sentence of science must be proved to be meaningful by logical 
analysis. If it is discovered that the sentence in question is either a 
tautology or a contradiction (negation of a tautology), the statement 
belongs to the domain of logic including mathematics. Alternatively 
the sentence has factual content, i.e., it is neither tautological nor 
contradictor}^; it is then an empirical sentence. It is reducible to the 
given and can, therefore, be discovered, in principle, to be either 
true or false. The (true or false) sentences of the empirical sciences 
are of this character. There are no questions which are in principle 
unanswerable. There is no such thing as speculative philosophy, a 
system of sentences with a special subject matter on a par with those 
of the sciences. To pursue philosophy can only be to clarify the 
concepts and sentences of science by logicai analysis. The instrument 
for this is the new logic. 


[146] 


RUBOLF CARNAP 


REMARKS BY THE AUTHOR (1957) 

The position explained in sections 8 and 9 of the foregoing paper 
was modified in the years following its publication in the following respect. 
The reduction of scientific concepts to the concepts of either of the two 
bases indicated (viz., to the given, i.e., sense-data, or to observable prop- 
erti^ of physical thmgs) cannot generally be carried out in the form of 
explicit definitions. Therefore scientific sentences are in general not 
translatable into sentences of either of the two bases; the relation between 
them is more complicated. Consequently a scientific sentence is not 
simply decidable as true or as false; it can only be more or less confirmed 
on the basis of given observations. Thus the earlier principle of verifia- 
bility, jfirst pronounced by Wittgenstein, was replaced by the weaker 
requirement of confirmability. The thesis of the unity of science re- 
mained, however, intact in virtue of the common basis of confirmation 
for all branches of empirical science. The modification here indicated was 
explained in the article “Testability and Meaning” (1936-37). For the 
later development of the conception of the nature of scientific concepts, 
see the article “The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts” 
(1956), in H. Feigl and M. Scriven eds., Minnesota Studies in the Phi- 
losophy of Science, VoL I. 


7 



i 


I 


Logic, Mathematics and 

Knowledge of Nature 
BY HANS HAHN 
(translated by ARTHUR PAP) 


I 

Even a cursory glance at the statements of physics shows that they 
are obviously of a very diverse character. There are statements like 
“if a stretched string is plucked, a tone is heard” or “if a ray of 
sunlight is passed through a glass prism, then a colored band, inter- 
spersed with dark lines, is visible on a screen placed behind the 
prism,” which can be tested at any time by observation. We also find 
statements like “the sun contains hydrogen.” “the satellite of Sirius 
has a density of about 60 , 000 ,” “a hydrogen atom consists of a 
positively charged nucleus around which a negatively charged electron 
revolves,” which cannot by any means be tested by immediate 
observation but which are made only on the basis of theoretical 
considerations and likewise are testable only with the help of theoreti- 
cal considerations. And thus we are confronted by the urgent ques- 
tion; what is the relationship between observation and theory in 
physics — and not just in physics, but in science generally. For there 
is but one science, and wherever there is scientific investigation it 
proceeds ultimately according to the same methods; only we see 
everything with the greatest clarity in the case of physics, because it 
is the most advanced, neatest, most scientific of all the sciences. And 
in physics, indeed, the interaction of observation and theory is 

This contribution comprises the first four sections of tlie pamphlet “Logik, Mathe- 
matik und Naturerkennen,” published in Vienna in 1933 as the second volume of the 
series entitled “Einheitswissenschaft.” It is reproduced here with the kind permission 
of Mrs. Lilly Hahn, Gerold & Co., Vienna, and Professor Rudolf Carnap, the co- 
editor of Einheitswissenschaft. The last two sections of Hahn’s pamphlet which 
are omitted do not deal with the nature of logical or mathematical propositions. 



[ 147 3 


f 3 HANS HAHN 

especially pronounced, even officially recognized by the institution 
of special professorships for experimental physics and for theoretical 
physics. 

Now, presumably the usual conception is roughly speaking the 
following: we have two sources of knowledge, by means of which 
we comprehend “the world,” “the reality” in which we are “placed”- 
experience, or observation on the one hand, and thinking on the 
other. For example, one is engaged in experimental physics or in 
theoretical physics according to one’s using the one or the other of 
tiiese sources of knowledge in physics. 

Now, in philosophy we find a time-honored controversy about 
these two sources of knowledge: which parts of our knowledge 
denye from observation, are “a posteriori,” and which derive from 
nking, are a priori”? Is one of these sources of knowledge 
superior to the others, and if so, which? 

beginning philosophy has raised doubts about the 
reliability of observation (indeed, these doubts are perhaps the 
source of all philosophy). It is quite understandable that such doubts 
arose, t ey spring from the belief that sense -perception is frequently 
deceptive. At sunrise or at sunset the snow on distant mountains 
appears red, but “in reality” it is surelv white! A stick which is 
immersed m water appears crooked, but “in reality”^t is surely 
straight If a man recedes from me, he appears smaller and smaUer 
to me, but surely he does not change size “in reality”! 

Now, although all the phenomena to which we have been refer- 
ring have long since been accounted for by physical theories, so that 
nobody any longer regards them as deceptions caused by sense- 
perception, t e consequences which flow from this primitive, lon^- 
discarded conception stiU exert a powerful influence. One says: if 
o seryation is sometimes deceptive, perhaps it is always so! Perhaps 
everything disclosed by the senses is mere illusion! Everybody knows 
the phenomenon of dreams, and everybody knows how difficult it is at 
whether a given experience was “real life” or “a mere 
whatever we observe is merely a dream 

can hi' hallucinations occur, and that they 

an be so vivid that the subject cannot be dissuaded from taking his 

' then, whatever we observe is only 

evei^Srln^' through appropriately polished lenses, 

verythmg appears distorted; who knows whether perhaps we do not 

JrssS’ tlte world as it were through distorting 

h reSNi^ rilf see everything distorted, different from what 
It really is! This is one of the basic themes of the philosophy of Kant 


Logic, Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ 149 ] 

But let us return to antiquity. As we said, the ancients believed 
that they were frequently deceived by observation. But nothing of 
this kind ever happened in the case of thought: there were plenty of 
delusions of sense, but no delusions of thought! And thus, as confi- 
dence in observation got shaken, the belief may have arisen that 
thinking is a method of knowledge which is absolutely superior to 
observation, indeed the only reliable method of knowledge: observa- 
tion discloses mere appearance, thought alone grasps true being. 

This, “rationalistic,” doctrine that thinking is a source of knowl- 
edge which surpasses observation, that it is indeed the only reliable 
source of knowledge, has remained dominant from the climax of 
Greek philosophy until modem times. I cannot even intimate what 
peculiar fmits matured on the tree of such knowledge. At any rate, 
they proved to have extraordinarily little nourishing value; and thus 
the “empiricist” reaction, originating in England, slowly gained the 
upper hand, supported by the tremendous success of modern natural 
science — the philosophy which teaches that observation is superior 
to thought, indeed is the only source of knowledge: nihil est in 
intellectu, quod non prius fuerit in sejtsu; in English: “nothing is in 
the intellect which was not previously in the senses.” 

But at once this empiricism faces an apparently insuperable 
dijSiculty: how is it to account for the real validity of logical and 
mathematical statements? Observation discloses to me only the 
transient, it does not reach beyond the observed; there is no bond 
that would lead from one observed fact to another, that would compel 
future observations to have the same result as those already made. 
The laws of logic and mathematics, however, claim absolutely uni- 
versal validity: that the door of my room is now closed, I know by 
observation; next time I observe it it may be open. That heated 
bodies expand, I know by observ'ation: yet the very next observation 
may show that some heated body does not expand; but that two and 
two make four, holds not only for the case in which I verify it by 
counting I know with certainty that it holds always and everywhere. 
Whatever I know by observation could be otherwise: the door of 
my room might have been open now, I can easily imagine it; and 
I can easily imagine that a body does not expand on being heated; 
but two and two could not occasionally make five, I cannot imagine 
in any way what it would be like for twice two to equal five. 

The conclusion seems inevitable: since the propositions of logic 
and mathematics have absolutely universal validity, are apodeictically 
certain, since it must be as they say and cannot be otherwise, these 
propositions cannot be derived from experience. In view of the tre- 


^ j ^ . HANS HAHN 

mendous importance of logic and mathematics in the system of our 
toowledge, empincism therefore, seems to be irrevocably refuted 
To be sure, m spite of all this the older empiricists have Lemoted 
we^no^ h and mathematics upon experience. According to them 
we believe Aat something must be this way and caLt £ 
otherwise simply because the relevant experience is so old 3 

iSiS -S— ^ 

a sign of good luck, an occurrence which is not so very rare^ hnw 

!hf Ts'“’ 3 

uiis iramework. As re^aras the imitc t 

knowledge, opinions diverge 

Thus it is, for instance, disputed whether geometry is a priori 
periencTAn^^^^ 

nl^ssitZs o tho„ I? K ^ as 

thf>v h H tiy various philosophers — but always after 

^ ^ probably a prevalent tendency among nhvsi- 

St aTsi'tidr'r" ”‘1'“ “pSs S. 

o bemg as wide and general as possible, and to acknowledge 


Logic, Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ 151 ] 

experience as the source of our knowledge of ever^hing that is 
somehow concrete. 

The usual conception, then, may be described roughly as fol- 
lows: from experience we leam certain facts, which we formulate 
as ‘laws of nature”; but since we grasp by means of thought the 
most general lawful connections (of a logical and mathematical 
character) that pervade reality, we can control nature on the basis 
of facts disclosed by observation to a much larger extent than it 
has actually been observed. For we know in addition that anything 
which can be deduced from observed facts by application of logic 
and mathematics must be found to exist. According to this view, 
the experimental physicist provides knowledge of laws of nature by 
direct observation. The theoretical physicist thereafter enlarges this 
knowledge tremendously by thinking, in such a way that we are in 
a position also to assert propositions about processes that occur far 
from us in space and time and about processes which, on account 
of their magnitude or minuteness, are not directly observable but 
which are connected with what is directly observed by the most 
general laws of being, grasped by thought, the laws of logic and 
mathematics. This view seems to be strongly supported by numerous 
discoveries that have been made with the help of theor}', like — ^to men- 
tion just some of the best known — the calculation of the position 
of the planet Neptune by Leverrier, the calculation of electric waves 
by Maxwell, the calculation of the bending of light rays in the gravi- 
tational field of the sun by Einstein and the calculation of the red- 
shift in the solar spectrum, also by Einstein. 

Nevertheless we are of the opinion that this view is entirel3»- un- 
tenable. For on closer analysis it appears that the function of thought 
is immeasurably more modest than the one ascribed to it by this 
theory. The idea that thinking is an instrument for learning more 
about the world than has been observed, for acquiring knowledge of 
something that has absolute validity always and everywhere in the 
world, an instrument for grasping general laws of ail being, seems 
to us wholly mystical. Just how should it come to pass that we could 
predict the necessary outcome of an observation before having made 
it? Whence should our thinking derive an executive power, by which 
it could compel an observation to have this rather than that result? 
Why should that which compels our thoughts also compel the course 
of nature? One would have to believe in some miraculous pre-estab- 
lished harmony between the course of our thinking and the course 
of nature, an idea which is highly mystical and ultimately theological. 

There is no way out of this situation except a return to a purely 


[ 152 ] HANS HAHN 

empiricist standpoint, to the view that observation is the only source 
of knowledge of facts: there is no <3 priori knowledge about matters 
of fact, there is no "'materiaV" a priori. However, we shall have to 
avoid the error committed by earlier empiricists, that of interpreting 
the propositions of logic and mathematics as mere facts of experi- 
ence. We must look out for a different interpretation of logic and 
mathematics. 

n 

Let us begin with logic. The old conception of logic is approxi- 
mately as follows: logic is the account of the most universal prop- 
erties of things, the account of those properties which are common 
to all things; just as ornithology is the science of birds, zoology’ the 
science of all animals, biolog>- the science of ail living beings, so 
logic is the science of all things, the science of being as such. If 
this were the case, it would remain wholly unintelligible whence 
logic derives its certainty. For we surely do not know all things. 
We have not observed everything and hence we cannot know how 
everything behaves. 

Our thesis, on the contrary, asserts: logic does not by any means 
treat of the totality of things, it does not treat of objects^ at all but 
only of our way of speaking about objects; logic is first generated 
by language. The certainty and universal validity, 0: better, the 
irrefutability of a proposition of logic derives just from the fact that 
it says nothing about objects of any kind. 

Let us clarify the point by an example. I talk about a well-known 
plant: I describe it, as is done in botanical reference books, in terms 
of the number, color and form of its blossom leaves, its calyx leaves, 
its stamina, the shape of its leaves, its stem, its root, etc., and I 
make the stipulation: let us caU any plant of this kind “’snow rose," 
but let us also call it “helleborus niger.” Thereupon I can pro- 
nounce with absolute certainty the universally vdid proposition: 
‘"every snow rose is a helleborus niger.” It is certainly valid, always 
and everywhere; it is not refutable by any sort of obsen^ation; but 
it says nothing at all about facts. I learn nothing from it about the 
plant in question, when it is in bloom, where it may be found, 
whether it is common or rare. It tells me nothing about the plant; 
it cannot be disconfirmed by any observation. This is the basis of 
its certainty and universal validity. The statement merely expresses 
a convention concerning the way we wish to talk about the plant 
in question. 


Logic, Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ I 

Similar considerations apply to the principles of logic. Let ns 
make the point with reference to the two most famous laws of logic: 
the law of contradiction and the law of the excluded middle. Take, 
for example, colored objects. We learn, by training as I am tempted 
to say, to apply the designation ‘Ted’’ to some of these objects, and 
we stipulate that the designation “not red” be applied to ail other 
objects. On the basis of this stipulation we now can assert with ab- 
solute certainty the proposition that there is no object to which 
both the designation ‘Ted” and the designation “not red” is applied. 
It is customary to formulate this briefly by saying that nothing is 
both red and not red. This is the law of contradiction. And since 
we have stipulated that the designation “red” is to be applied to 
some objects and the designation “not red” to all other objects, 
we can likewise pronounce with absolute certainty the proposition: 
eveiy^thing is either designated as “red” or as “not red,” which it 
is customary' to formulate briefly by saying that eveiyhhing is either 
red or not red. This is the law of the excluded middle. These 
two propositions, the law of contradiction and the law of the 
excluded middle, say nothing at all about objects of any kind. 
They do not tell me of any of them whether they are red or 
not red, wdich color they have, or anything else. They merely 
stipulate a method for applying the designations “red” and “not 
red” to objects, i.e. they prescribe a method of speaking about things. 
And their universal validity and certainty, their irrefutability, just 
derives from the fact that they say nothing at all about objects. 

The same is to be said of ail the other principles of logic. We 
shall presently return to this point. But first let us insert another 
consideration. We have previously maintained that there can be no 
material a priori, i.e. no a priori knowledge about matters of fact. 
For we cannot know the outcome of an observation before the 
latter takes place. We have made clear to ourselves that no material 
a priori is contained in the laws of contradiction and of excluded 
middle, since they say nothing about facts. There are those, how- 
ever, who would perhaps admit that the nature of the laws of logic 
is as described, yet would insist that there is a material a priori 
elsewhere, e.g. in the statement “nothing is both red and blue” (of 
course what is meant is: at the same time and place) which is 
alleged to express real a priori knowledge about the nature of 
things. Even before having made any observation, they say, one 
can predict with absolute certainty that it will not disclose a thing 
which is both blue and red; and it is maintained that such a priori 
knowledge is obtained by “eidetic insight” or an intuitive grasp of 


[ 154 ] HANS HAHN 

the essence of colors. If one desires to adhere to our thesis that 
there is no kind of material a priori, one must somehow face state- 
ments like "‘nothing is both blue and red.” I want to attempt this 
in a few suggestive words, though they cannot by any means do 
full justice to this problem which is not easy. It surely is correct 
that we can say with complete certainty before having made any 
observations: the latter will not show that a thing is both blue and 
red — ^just as we can say with complete certainty that no observation 
will yield the result that a thing is both red and not red, or that a 
snow rose is not a helleborus niger. The first statement, however, is 
not a case of a material a priori any more than the second and third. 
Like the statements “every snow rose is a helleborus niger”: and 
“nothing is both red and not red,” the statement “nothing is both 
blue and red” says nothing at all about the nature of things; it 
likewise refers only to our proposed manner of speaking about ob- 
jects, of applying designations to them. Earlier we said: there are 
some objects that we call “red,” every other object we call “not 
red,” and from this we derive the laws of contradiction and excluded 
middle. Now we say: some objects we call “red,” some other objects 
we call “blue,” and other objects again we call “green,” etc. But if 
it is in this way that we ascribe color designations to objects, then 
we can say with certainty in advance: in this procedure no object 
is designated both as “red” and as “blue,” or more briefly: no ob- 
ject is both red and blue. The reason why we can say this with cer- 
tainty is that we have regulated the ascription of color designations 
to objects in just this way. 

We see, then, that there are two totally different kinds of state- 
ments: those which really say something about objects, and those 
Vr^hich do not say an 5 rthing about objects but only stipulate rules for 
speaking about objects. If I ask “what is the color of Miss Ema’s 
new^ dress?” and get the answer “Miss Ema’s new dress is not both 
red and blue (all over),” then no information about this dress has 
been given to me at all. I have been made no wiser by it. But if I 
get the answer “Miss Erna’s new dress is red,” then I have received 
some genuine information about the dress. 

Let us clarify this distinction in terms of one more example. A 
statement which reaUy says something about the objects which it 
mentions, is the following: “If you heat this piece of iron up to 
800°, it will turn red, if you heat it up to 1300°, it will turn white.” 
What makes the difference between this statement and the state- 
ments cited above, which say nothing about facts? The application 
of temperature designations to objects is independent of the appli- 


Logic, Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ 155 ] 

cation of color designations, whereas the color designations “red” 
and “not red,” or “red” and “blue” are applied to objects in mutual 
dependence. The statements “Miss Ema’s new dress is either red or 
not red” and “Miss Ema’s new dress is not both red and blue” 
merely express this dependence, hence make no assertion about that 
dress, and are for that reason absolutely certain and irrefutable. 
The above statement about the piece of iron, on the other hand, 
relates independently given designations, and therefore really says 
something about that piece of iron and is for just that reason not 
certain nor irrefutable by observation. 

The following example may make the difference between these 
two kinds of statements particularly clear. If someone were to tell 
me: “I raised the temperature of this piece of iron to 800° but 
it did not turn red,” then I would test his assertion; the result of 
the test may be that he was lying, or that he w^as the victim of an 
illusion, but perhaps it would turn out that — contrary to my previous 
beliefs — there are cases where a piece of iron heated to 800° does 
not become red-hot, and in that case I would just change my opinion 
about the reaction of iron to heating. But if someone tells me “I 
raised the temperature of this piece of iron to 800°, and this made 
it turn both red and not red” or “it became both red and white,” 
then I w’ill certainly make no test whatever. Nor will I say “he has 
told me a lie,” or “he has become the victim of an illusion” and 
it is quite certain that I would not change my beliefs about the 
reaction of iron to heating. The point is — it is best to express it in 
language which any card player is familiar with — that the man has 
revoked: he has violated the rules in accordance with which we 
w'ant to speak, and ! shall refuse to speak with him any longer. It 
is as though one attempted in a game of chess to move the bishop 
orthogonally. In this case too, I would not make any tests, I would 
not change my beliefs about the behavior of things, but I would re- 
fuse to play chess with him any longer. 

To sum up: we must distinguish two kinds of statements: those 
w^hich say something about facts and those which merely express 
the way in which the rules which govern the application of words 
to facts depend upon each other. Let us call statements of the latter 
kind tautologies: they say nothing about objects and are for this 
very reason certain, universally valid, irrefutable by observation; 
whereas the statements of the former kind are not certain and are 
refutable by observation. The logical laws of contradiction and 
of the excluded middle are tautologies, likewise, e.g., the statement 
“nothing is both red and blue.” 


HANS HAHN 


[ i56 ]. 

And now we maintain that in the same way all the other laws of 
logic are tautologies. Let ns, therefore, return to logic once more 
in order to clarify the matter by an example. As we said, the desig- 
nation “red’’ is applied to certain objects and the convention is 
adopted of applying the designation “not red” to any other object. 
It is this convention about the use of negation which is expressed 
by the laws of contradiction and of the excluded middle. Now we 
add the convention — still taking our examples from the domain of 
colors — that any object which is called “red” is also to be called 
“red or blue,” “blue or red,” “red or yellow,” “yellow or red,” etc., 
that every object which is called “blue,” is also called “blue or red,” 
“red or blue,” “blue or yellow,” “yellow or blue,” etc., and so on. 
On the basis of this convention, we can again assert with complete 
certainty the proposition: “every red object is either red or blue.” 
This is again a tautology. We do not speak about the objects, but 
only about our manner of talking about them. 

If once more we remind ourselves of the way in which the des- 
ignations “red,” “not red,” “blue,” “red or blue,” etc. are applied 
to objects, we can moreover assert with complete certainty and ir- 
refutability: eveiything to which both designations “red or blue” 
and “not red” are applied, is also designated as “blue”— which is 
usually put more briefly: if a thing is red or blue and not red, then 
it is blue. Which is again a tautology. No information about the 
nature of things is contained in it, it only expresses the sense in 
which the logical words “not” and “or” are used. 

Thus we have arrived at something fundamental: our conven- 
tions regarding the use of the words “not” and “or” is such that in 
asserting the two propositions “object A is either red or blue” and 
“object A is not red,” I have implicitly already asserted “object A 
is blue.” This is the essence of so-called logical deduction. It is not. 
then, in any way based on real connections between states of affairs, 
which we apprehend in thought. On the contrary, it has nothing at 
all to do with the nature of things, but derives from our manner of 
speaking about things. A person who refused to recognize logical 
deduction would not thereby manifest a different belief from mine 
about the behavior of things, but he would refuse to speak about 
things according to the same rules as I do. I could not convince 
him, but I would have to refuse to speak with him any longer, just 
as I should refuse to play chess with a partner who insisted on 
moving the bishop orthogonally. 

What logical deduction accomplishes, then, is this: it makes us 


Logic, Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ ^^'7 ] 

aware of all that we have implicitly asserted — on the basis of con- 
ventions regarding the use of language — in asserting a system of 
propositions, just as, in the above example, “object A is blue” 
is implicitly asserted by the assertion of the two propositions “object 
A is red or blue” and “object A is not red.” 

In saying this we have already suggested the answer to the ques- 
tion, v^hich naturally must have forced itself on the mind of every 
reader who has followed our argument: if it is really the case that 
the propositions of logic are tautologies, that they say nothing about 
objects, what purpose does logic serve? 

The logical propositions which were used as illustrations derived 
from conventions about the use of the words “not” and “or” (and 
it can be shovvm that the same holds for ail the propositions of so- 
called propositional logic). Let us, then, first ask for what purpose 
the words “not” and “or” are introduced into language. Presumably 
the reason is that we are not omniscient. If I am asked about the 
color of the dress worn by Miss Erna yesterday, I may not be able 
to remember its color. I cannot say whether it was red or blue or 
green; but perhaps I will be able to say at least “it was not yellow.” 
Were I omniscient, I should know its color. There would be no need 
to say “it was not yellow”: I could say “it was red.” Or again: my 
daughter has written to me that she received a cocker-spaniel as a 
present. As I have not seen it yet, I do not know its color; I cannot 
say “it is black” nor “it is brown”; but I am able to say “it is black 
or brown.” Were I omniscient, I could do without this “or” and 
could say immediately “it is brown.” 

Thus logical propositions, though being purely tautologous, 
and logical deductions, though being nothing but tautological trans- 
formations, have significance for us because we are not omniscient. 
Our language is so constituted that in asserting such and such prop- 
ositions we implicitly assert such and such other propositions — ^but 
we do not see immediately all that we have implicitly asserted in this 
manner. It is only logical deduction that makes us conscious of it. 
I assert, e.g., the propositions “the flower which Mr. Smith wears 
in his buttonhole, is either a rose or a carnation,” “if Mr. Smith 
wears a carnation in his buttonhole, then it is white,” “the flower 
which Mr, Smith wears in his buttonhole is not white.” Perhaps I 
am not consciously aware that I have implicitly asserted also “the 
flower which Mr. Smith wears in his buttonhole is a rose”; but logi- 
cal deduction brings it to my consciousness. To be sure, this does 
not mean that I know whether the flower which Mr. Smith wears 


HANS HAHN 


[ 158 ] 

in Ms buttonhole really is a rose; if I notice that it is not a rose, 
then I must not maintain my previous assertions — otherwise I sin 
against the rules of speaking, I revoke. 

Ill 

If I have succeeded in clarifying somewhat the role of logic, I 
may now be quite brief about the role of mathematics. The proposi- 
tions of mathematics are of exactly the same kind as the propositions 
of logic: they are tautologous, they say nothing at all about the ob- 
jects we want to talk about, but concern only the manner in which 
we want to speak of them. The reason why we can assert apodeicti- 
caliy with universal validity the proposition: 2 + 3 = 5, why we 
can say even before any observations have been made, and can say 
it v/ith complete certainty, that it will not turn out that 2 + 3 = 7, 
is that by “2 + 3” we mean the same as by “5” — ^just as we mean 
the same by "‘helleborus niger” as by “snow rose.” For this reason 
no botanical investigation, however subtle, could disclose that an 
instance of the species “snow rose” is not a helleborus niger. We 
become aware of meaning the same by “2 + 3” and by “5,” by 
going back to the meanings of “2,” “3,” “5,” “+,” and making 
tautological transformations until we just see that “2 + 3” means 
the same as “5.” It is such successive tautological transformation 
that is meant by “calculating”; the operations of addition and mul- 
tiplication which are learnt in school are directives for such tauto- 
logical transformation; every mathematical proof is a succession of 
such tautological transformations. Their utility, again, is due to the 
fact that, for example, we do not by any means see immediately that 
we mean by “24 X 31” the same as by “744”; but if we calculate 
the product “24 X 31,” then we transform it step by step, in such a 
way that in each individual transformation we recognize that on 
the basis of the conventions regarding the use of the signs involved 
(in this case numerals and the signs “+” and “X”) what we mean 
after the transformation is still the same as what we meant before it, 
until finally we become consciously aware of meaning the same by 
“744” as by “24 X 31.” 

To be sure, the proof of the tautological character of mathematics 
is not yet complete in all details. This is a difficult and arduous task; 
yet we have no doubt that the belief in the tautological character 
of mathematics is essentially correct. 

There has been prolonged opposition to the interpretation of 
mathematical statements as tautologies; Kant contested the tauto- 


Logic t Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ 159 ] 

logical character of mathematics emphatically, and the great mathe- 
matician Henri Poincare, to whom we are greatly indebted also for 
philosophical criticism, went so far as to argue that since mathematics 
cannot possibly be a huge tautology, it must somewhere contain an 
a priori principle. Indeed, at first glance it is difficult to believe 
that the whole of mathematics, with its theorems that it cost such 
labor to establish, with its results that so often surprise us, should 
admit of being resolved into tautologies. But there is just one little 
point which this argument overlooks: it overlooks the fact that we 
are not omniscient. An omniscient being, indeed, would at once 
know everything that is implicitly contained in the assertion of a few 
propositions. It would know immediately that on the basis of the 
conventions concerning the use of the numerals and the multiplica- 
tion sign, “24 X 31” is synonymous with “744.” An omniscient 
being has no need for logic and mathematics. We ourselves, how- 
ever, first have to make ourselves conscious of this by successive 
tautological transformations, and hence it may prove quite surprising 
to us that in asserting a few propositions we have implicitly also as- 
serted a proposition which seemingly is entirely difierent from them, or 
that we do mean the same by two complexes of symbols which are ex- 
ternally altogether different. 

I\' 

And now let us be clear what a world-wide difference there is 
between our conception and the traditional — perhaps one may say: 
piatonizing — conception, according to which the w'orld is made in 
accordance with the laws of logic and mathematics (“God is peren- 
nially doing mathematics”), and our thinking, a feeble reflection of 
God’s omniscience, is an instrument given to us for comprehending 
the eternal laws of the world. No! Our thinking cannot give insight 
into any sort of reality. It cannot bring us information of any fact 
in the world. It only refers to the maimer in which we speak about 
the world. All it can do is to transform tautologically what has been 
said. There is no possibility of piercing through the sensible world 
disclosed by observation to a “world of true being”; any metaphysics 
is impossible! Impossible, not because the task is too difficult for 
our human thinking, but because it is meaningless, because every 
attempt to do metaphysics is an attempt to speak in a way that con- 
travenes the agreement as to how we wish to speak, comparable 
to the attempt to capture the queen (in a game of chess) by means 
of an orthogonal move of the bishop. 


HANS HAHN 


[ 160 ] 

Let US return now to the problem which was onr point of 
departure: what is the relationship between observation and theory 
in physics? We said that the usual view was roughly this: experience 
teaches us the validity of certain laws of nature, and since our think- 
ing gives us insight into the most general laws of all being, we know 
that likewise anything which is deducible from these laws of nature 
by means of logical and mathematical reasoning must be found to 
exist. We see now that this view is untenable; for thinking does not 
grasp any sort of laws of being. Never and nowhere, then, can 
thought supply us with knowledge about facts that goes beyond the 
observed. But what, then, should we say about the discoveries made 
by means of theory on which, as we pointed out, the usual view so 
strongly relies for its support? Let us ask ourselves, e.g., what was 
involved in the computation of the position of the planet I^eptune 
by Leverrier! Newton noticed that the familiar motions, celestial as 
well as terrestrial, can be well described in a unified way by the 
assumption that between any two mass points a force of attraction is 
exerted which is proportional to their masses and inversely propor- 
tional to the square of their distance. And it is because this assump- 
tion enables us to give a satisfactory description of the familiar 
motions, that he made it, i.e. he asserted tentatively, as an hypothesis, 
the law of gravitation: between any two mass points there is a force 
of attraction which is proportional to their masses and inversely pro- 
portional to the square of their distance. He could not pronounce 
this law as a certainty, but only as an hypothesis. For nobody can 
know that such is really the behavior of ever)^ pair of mass points — 
nobody can observe all mass points. But having asserted the law of 
gravitation, one has implicitly asserted many other propositions, 
that is, all propositions which are deducible from the law of gravi- 
tation (together with data immediately derivable from observation) 
by calculation and logical inference. It is the task of theoretical 
physicists and astronomers to make us conscious of everything we 
implicitly assert along with the law of gravitation. And Leverrier's 
calculations made people aware that the assertion of the law of 
gravitation implies that at a definite time and definite place in the 
heavens a hitherto unknown planet must be visible. People looked 
and actually saw that new planet — ^the hypothesis of the law of gravi- 
tation was confirmed. But it was not Leverrier’s calculation that 
proved that this planet existed, but the looking, the observ^ation. This 
observation could just as well have had a different result. It could just 
as well have happened that nothing was visible at the computed 
place in the heavens — in which case the law of gravitation would 


Logic, Mathematics and Knowledge of Nature [ 161 ] 

not have been confirmed and one would have begun to doubt 
whether it is really a suitable hypothesis for the description of the 
observable motions. Indeed, this is what actually happened later: 
in asserting the law of gravitation, one implicitly asserts that at a 
certain time the planet Mercury must be visible at a certain place 
in the heavens. Whether it would actually be visible at that time at 
that place, only observation could disclose; but observations showed 
that it was not visible at exactly the required position in the heavens. 
And what happened? They said: since in asserting the law of gravi- 
tation we implicitly assert propositions which are not true, we can- 
not maintain the hypothesis of the law of gravitation. Newton’s theory 
of gravitation w^as replaced by Einstein’s. 

It is not the case, then, that we know through experience that 
certain laws of nature are valid, and — since by our thinking we 
grasp the most general laws of all being — therefore also know that 
v/hatever is deducible from these laws by reasoning must exist. On 
the contrary, the situation is this: there is not a single law of nature 
which we know^ to be valid; the laws of nature are hypotheses which 
we assert tentatively. But in asserting such laws of nature we im- 
plicitly assert also many other propositions, and it is the task of 
thinking to make us conscious of the implicitly asserted propositions. 
So long, now', as these implicitly asserted propositions, to the extent 
that they are about the directly obseiwable, are confirmed by ob- 
servation, these laws of nature are confirmed and we adhere to 
them; but if these implicitly asserted propositions are not confirmed 
by observation, then the laws of nature have not been confirmed and 
are replaced by others. 






8 


Psychology in Physical Language 
BY RUDOLF CARNAP 
(translated by GEORGE SCHICK) 


1. Introduction. Physical Language 
AND Protocol Language 

In wkat follows, we intend to explain and to establish the thesis 
that every sentence of psychology may be formulated in physical 
language. To express this in the material mode of speech: all sen- 
tences of psychology describe physical occurrences, namely, the 
physical behavior of humans and other animals. This is a sub-thesis 
of the general thesis of physicalism to the effect that physical lan- 
guage is a universal language, that is, a language into which every 
sentence may be translated. The general thesis has been discussed 
in an earlier article/ whose position shall here serve as our point 
of departure. Let us first briefly review some of the conclusions of 
the earlier study. 

In meta-linguistic discussion we distinguish the customary ma- 
terial mode of speech (e.g. “The sentences of this language speak of 
this and that object.’') from the more correct formal mode of speech 
(e.g. “The sentences of this language contain this and that word 
and are constructed in this and that manner.”) In using the material 
mode of speech we run the risk of introducing confusions and pseudo- 
problems. If, because of its being more easily understood, we occa- 
sionally do use it in what follows, we do so only as a paraphrase of 
the formal mode of speech. 

Of first importance for epistemological analyses are the protocol 

This article was originally published in Volume III of Erkenntnis (1932/33). It is 
reproduced here with the Idnd permission of Professor Carnap. 

1. Carnap, “Die Physikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wissenschaft/^ 
Erkenntnis 11, 1931, pp. 432-465. [The English translation of this article by Max 
Black was published as a monograph under the title “The Unity of Science” 
(London: Kegan Paul, 1934).] 


[ 165 3 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


[ 166 ] 

language, in wMch the primitive protocol sentences (in the material 
mode of speech: the sentences about the immediately given) of a 
particular person are formulated, and the system language, in which 
the sentences of the system of science are formulated. A person S 
tests (verifies) a system-sentence by deducing from it sentences of 
his own protocol language, and comparing these sentences with those 
of his actual protocol. The possibility of such a deduction of proto- 
col sentences constitutes the content of a sentence. E a sentence 
permits no such deductions, it has no content, and is meaningless. If 
the same sentences may be deduced from two sentences, the latter 
two sentences have the same content. They say the same thing, and 
may be translated into one another. 

To every sentence of the system language there corresponds some 
sentence of the physical language such that the two sentences are 
inter-translatable. It is the purpose of this article to show that this 
is the case for the sentences of psychology’'. Moreover, every sentence 
of the protocol language of some specific person is inter-translatable 
with some sentence of physical language, namely, with a sentence 
about the physical state of the person in question. The various proto- 
col languages thus become sub-languages of the physical language. 
The physical language is universal and inter-subjective. This is the 
thesis of physicalism. 

If the physical language, on the grounds of its universality, were 
adopted as the system language of science, all science would become 
physics. Metaphysics would be discarded as meaningless. The .vari- 
ous domains of science would become parts of unified science. In 
the material mode of speech: there would, basically, be only one 
kind of object — physical occurrences, in whose realm law would 
be all-encompassing. 

Physicalism ought not to be understood as requiring psychology 
to concern itself only with physically describable situations. Tlie 
thesis, rather, is that psychology may deal with whatever it pleases, 
it may formulate its sentences as it pleases — these sentences will, in 
every case, be translatable into physical language. 

We say of a sentence P that it is translatable (more precisely, 
that it is reciprocally translatable) into a sentence Q if there are 
rules, independent of space and time, in accordance with which Q 
may be deduced from P and P from Q; to use the material mode 
of speech, P and Q describe the same state of affairs; epistemologi- 
cally speaking, every protocol sentence which confirms P also con- 
firms Q and vice versa. The definition of an expression “a” by means 
of expressions “b,” “c” . . . , represents a translation-rule with 


Psychology in Physical Language [ ] 

tlie Iieip of which any sentence in which “a” occurs may be trans- 
lated into a sentence in which “a” does not occur, but “b/" ‘"c,” . . . 
do, and vice versa. The translatability of all the sentences of language 
Li into a (completely or partially) different language L2 is assured 
if, for every expression of Li, a definition is presented which directly 
or indirectly (i.e., with the help of other definitions) derives that 
expression from expressions of L2. Our thesis thus states that a 
definition may be constructed for every psychological concept (i.e. 
expression) which directly or indirectly derives that concept from 
physical concepts. We are not demanding that psychology formulate 
each of its sentences in physical terminology. For its own purposes 
psycholog}" may, as heretofore, utilize its own terminolog}". All that 
we are demanding is the production of the definitions through which 
psychological language is linked with physical language. We main- 
tain that these definitions can be produced, since, implicitly, they 
already underlie psychological practice. 

If our thesis is correct, the generalized sentences of psycholog}", 
the laws of psycholog}", are also translatable into the physical lan- 
guage. They are thus physical laws. Whether or not these physical 
laws are deducibie from those holding in inorganic physics, remains, 
however, an open question. This question of the deducibility of the 
laws is completely independent of the question of the definability of 
concepts. We have already considered this matter in our discussion 
of biology.- As soon as one realizes that the sentences of psychology 
belong to the physical language, and also overcomes the emotional 
obstacles to the acceptance of this provable thesis, one will, indeed, 
incline to the conjecture, which cannot as yet be proved, that the 
laws of psychology are special cases of physical laws holding in in- 
organic physics as well But v/e are not concerned with this conjecture 
here. 

Let us permit ourselves a brief remark — apart from our principal 
point^ — concerning the emotional resistance to the thesis of physical- 
ism. Such resistance is always exerted against any thesis when an 
Idol is being dethroned by it, when we are asked to discard an idea 
with which dignity and grandeur are associated. As a result of 
Copernicus’ work, man lost the distinction of a central position in 
the universe; as a result of Darwin’s, he was deprived of the dignity 
of a special supra-animal existence; as a result of Marx’s, the factors 
by means of which history can be causally explained were degraded 
from the realm of ideas to that of material events; as a result of 

2. “Die Piiysikalische Sprache,” op. cit., p. 449 ff., {The Unity of Science, 
p. 68 ff.). 


[ 168 ] 

XT- ♦ l, > • . RUDOLF CARNAP 

of men can te causaUy explained were located in afSrlSt tote 

StSaLT^f tSXoS: Lr ■ 

Se:;"^“= aVrri?' r 

express the request SThe^rSlTSe rstdalldoT^ S'"'”" 

to retain the objectivity and openness of minri t ^ 
the testing of a scientific thesis 

2. The FoR^^s of Psychological Sentences 

^ The distinction betv/een singular and general sentences is as 

mponant in psycholog>.- as in other sciences. A s/ZZ pJcAo 
logical sentence, e.g. “Mr A was ann,-,, a» ^‘nguiar psycno- 

anaiogue of the physical sentence, “YeSday at°noorfhe^^” 

with ? 28 de.;::fct^i^aJ^^^^^^ 

r -I'hir r cS “f ■ ~ A -Id 

* scc;„d LpoS “t Z of„„VSletSoL1"?e' 
nicats concerning sequences of events, that is. of causal laws Fo: 
lu ^unce \^ nen, unaer such and such circumstances ima<T»s of 

Stch -'„d “ M'- A oi: ,0 anyone 

always (or- frequentiv^''^(?^’ emotion of such and such a sort 

analogy Lid “wL a somTiIT^I “ ^ Pty^eal 

Resi“arrh is ' ■ heated, it usually expands ” 

t.n.? mK ^ primarily directed to the discovery of general sen 

^yp- 

P or on the basis of some smgle illustrative case. In our 


Psychology in Physical Language [ 169 ] 

view, knowledge cannot be gained by such means. We need not, 
however, enter upon a discussion of this issue here, since even on 
the view of phenomenology itself, these sentences do not belong to 
the domain of psychology. 

In physics it sometimes seems to be the case that a general law 
is established on the basis of some single event. For instance, if a 
physicist can determine a certain physical constant, say, the heat- 
conductivity of a sample of some pure metal, in a single experiment, 
he will be convinced that, on other occasions, not only the sample 
examined but any similar sample of the same substance will, very 
probably, be characterizable by the same constant. But here too in- 
duction is applied. As a result of many previous observations the 
physicist is in possession of a universal sentence of a higher order 
which enables him in this case to follow an abbreviated method. 
This higher-order sentence reads roughly: ‘‘All (or: the following) 
physical constants of metals vary only slightly in time and from 
sample to sample.” 

The situation is analogous for certain conclusions drawn in 
psychology'. If a psychologist has, as a result of some single experi- 
ment, determined that the simultaneous sounding of two specific 
notes is experienced as a dissonance by some specific person A, he 
infers (under favorable circumstances) the truth of the general sen- 
tence which states that the same experiment with A will, at other 
times, have the same result. Indeed, he will even venture — and 
rightly — to extend this result, with some probability, to pairs of 
tones with the same acoustic interv'ai if the pitch is not too different 
from that of the first experiment. liere too the inference from a 
singular sentence to a general one is only apparent. Actually, a sen- 
tence inductively obtained from many observations is brought into 
service here, a sentence which, roughly, reads: “The reaction of 
any specific person as to the consonance or dissonance of a chord 
varies only very slightly with time, and only slightly on a not too 
large transposition of the chord.” It thus remains the case that every^ 
general sentence is inductively established on the basis of a number 
of singular ones. 

Finally, we must consider sentences about psycho-physical inter- 
relations, such as for instance, the connection between physical 
stimulus and perception. These are likewise arrived at through in- 
duction, in this case through induction in part from physical and in 
part from psychological singular sentences. The most important sen- 
tences of gestalt psychology belong also to this kind. 

General sentences have the character of hypotheses in relation 


I RUDOLF CARNAP 

to concrete sentences, that is, the testing of a general sentence con- 
sists in testing the concrete sentences which are deducible from it. 
A general sentence has content insofar and only insofar as the con- 
crete sentences deducible from it have content Logical analysis must 
therefore primarily be directed towards the examination of the 
latter sort of sentences. 

If A utters a singular psychological sentence such as “Yesterday 
mormng B was happy,” the epistemological situation differs accord- 
mg as A and B are or are not the same person. Consequently, we 
distinguish between sentences about other minds and sentences about 
one^s own mind. As we shaU presently see, this distinction cannot 
be made among the sentences of inter-subjective science. For the 
epistemological analysis of subjective, singular sentences it is, how- 
ever, mdispensable, 

3. Sentences about Other Minds 

, The epistemological character of a singular sentence about other 
minds will now be clarified by means of an analogy with a sentence 
about a physical property, defined as a disposition to behave (or 
respond) in a specific manner under specific circumstances (or 
stimuli). To take an example: a substance is called “plastic” if, 
under the influence of deforming stresses of a specific sort and a 
specific magnitude, it undergoes a permanent change of shape, but 
remains intact. 

We shall tr}’’ to carr}^ out this analog}’’ by juxtaposing two ex- 
amples. We shall be concerned with the epistemological situation of 
the example taken from psycholog}”; the parallel example about the 
physical property is intended only to facilitate our understanding 
of the psychological sentence, and not to serve as a specimen of an 
argument from analogy. (For the sake of convenience, where the 
text would have been the same in both columns, it is written only 
once.) 


A Sentence about a property of a A Sentence about a condition of 
physical substance. some other mind. 

E^ple: I assert the sentence P^: Example: I assert the sentence P.: 
liais wooden support is very firm.” “Mr. A is now excited.” 

There are two different ways in which sentence Pi may be derived. 
We shall designate them as the “rational” and the “intuitive” meth- 
ods. The rational method consists of inferring Pi from some protocol 


Psychology in Physical Language [ ] 

sentence pi (or from several like it), more specifically, from a 
perception-sentence 


about the shape and color of the 
wooden support. 


about the behavior of A, e.g. about 
his facial expressions, his gestures, 
etc., or about physical effects of A’s 
behavior, e.g. about characteristics 
of his handwriting. 


In order to justify the conclusion, a major premise O is still re- 
quired, namely the general sentence which asserts that 

when I perceive a wooden support v/hen I perceive a person to have 
to be of this color and form, it this facial expression and hand- 
( usually) turns out to be firm. (A writing he (usually) turns out to 
sentence about the perceptual signs be excited. (A sentence about the 
of firmness.) expressional or graphological signs 

of excitement.) 

The content of Pi does not coincide with that of pi, but goes 
beyond it. This is evident from the fact that to infer Pi from pi 
O is required. The cited relationship between Pi and pi may also 
be seen in the fact that under certain circumstances, the inference 
from pi to Pi may go astray. It may happen that, though pi occurs 
in a protocol, I am obliged, on the grounds of further protocols, to 
retract the established system sentence Pi. I would then say some- 
thing like, ‘T made a mistake. The test has shown 

that the support was not firm, even that A was not excited, even though 
though it had such and such a form his face had such and such an ex- 
and color.” pression.” 

In practical matters the intuitive method is applied more fre- 
quently than this rational one, which presupposes theoretical knowl- 
edge and requires reflection. In accordance with the intuitive method, 
Pi is obtained without the mediation of any other sentence from 
the identically sounding protocol sentence p2. 

“The support is firm.” “A is excited.” 

Consequently, one speaks in this case of immediate perceptions 

properties of substances, e.g,, of other minds, e.g., of the excite- 
of the firmness of supports. ment of A. 

But in this case too the protocol sentence po and the system sentence 
Pi have different contents. The difference is generally not noted 
because, on the ordinary formulation, both sentences sound alike. 





[ 172 ] 


RUDOLF CARNAP 


Here too we can best clarify the difference by considering the pos- 
sibility of error. It may happen that, though p, occurs in my protocol, 
I ^ obliged, on the basis of further protocols, to retract the estab- 
lished system sentence Pj. I would then say “I made a mistake Fur- 
ther tests have shown 

that the support was not firm, al- that A was not excited, although I 
?oX; “a?" 2" “ 

[The difference between p, and P, is the same as that between the 

P 3tid Pi: “A red marble is lying 
on this table of an earher example.^ The argument of that article 
shows that the inference of P, from p„ if it il to be rigorous S 
requires a major premise of general form, and that it is“ not in the 

ordinary usage, for convenience's sake, 
assigns to both sentences the same sequence of words, the inference 
is, in practice, simplified to the point of trivialip'.] 

Our problem now is: wfjat does sentence P, mean’’ Such a 
question can only be answered by the presentation of a sentence (or 
of several sentences) which has (or which conjointly have) the 
same content as Pi. The viewpoint which will here be defended is 
that Pi has the same content as a sentence P. which asserts the 
existence of a physical structure characterized by the disposition to 
react in a specific manner to specific physical stimuli. In our ex- 
sSfcture^)' existence of that physical structure (micro- 


of the wooden support that is char- of Mr. A's bodv tesneciaHv o? his 

actenzed by the fact that, under a central nerv-ous sSemT that s 

sight load, the support undergoes characterized bv a high tiulse and 

no noticeable distortion, and, un- rate of breathing, whkh on the 

fnd Sne^ bm "PPlication of certain stimuli, may 

Seak ’ higher, by vehement 

and factually unsatisfactorv’ answers 
to cjuestions, by the occurrence of 
agitated movements on the appii- 
cation of certain stimuli, etc. 

the eJ^nZirT’ ^ thoroughgoing analogy betw-een 

the examples from physics and from psycholog\g If however we 

were to qu estion the experts concerning" the examples Tom\rr 

3. See Erkennlnis, Vol. 11, p. 460 (The Unity of Science, p. 92). 


Psychology in Physical Language [ ] 

respective jSeids, the majority of them nowadays would give us 
thoroughly non-ahalogons answers. The identity of the content of Po 

and of the content of the physical and of the content of the psycho- 
sentence Pj would be agreed to as logical sentence would be denied 
a matter of course by all physicists, by almost all psychologists (the 

exceptions being the radical be- 
haviorists) . 

The contrary view which is most frequently advocated by psychol- 
ogists is that, “A sentence of the form of Pi asserts the existence 
of a state of affairs not identical with the corresponding physical 
structure, but rather, only accompanied by it, or expressed by it. 


In our example: 

?! states that the support not only 
has the physical structure described 
by p2, but that, besides, there ex- 
ists in it a certain force, namely its 
firmness. 


This firmness is not identical with 
the physical structure, but stands 
in some parallel relation to it in 
such a manner that the firmness 
exists when and only when a physi- 
cal structure of the characterized 
sort exists. 


Because of this parallelism one may 
consider the described reaction to 
certain stimuli — ^wbich is causally 
dependent upon that structure — ^to 
be an expression of firmness. 
Firmness is thus an occult prop- 
erty, an obscure power which stands 
behind physical structure, appears 
in it, but itself remains unknow- 
able.” 


Pi states that Mr. A not only has 
a body whose physical structure 
(at the time in question) is de- 
scribed by Po, but that — since he 
is a psychophysical being — he has, 
besides, a consciousness, a certain 
power or entity, in which that ex- 
citement is to be found. 

This excitement cannot, conse- 
quently, be identical with the cited 
structure of the body, but stands 
in some parallel relation (or in 
some relation of interaction) to it 
in such a manner that the excite- 
ment exists when and only when 
(or at least, frequently when) a 
physical, bodily structure of the 
characterized sort exists. 

Because of this parallelism one may 
consider the described reaction to 
certain stimuli to be an expression 
of excitement. 

Excitement, or the consciousness 
of which it is an attribute, is thus 
an occult property, an obscure 
power which stands behind physi- 
cal structure, appears in it, but 
itself remains unknowable.” 


This view falls into the error of a hypostatization as a result of 


[174 ] RUTOLF CARNAP 

which a remarkable duplication occurs: besides or behind a state 
of affairs whose existence is empirically determinable, another, paral- 
lel entity is assumed, whose existence is not determinable. (Note 
that we are here concerned with a sentence about other minds.) 
Blit— one may now object — ^is there not really at least one possi- 
bility of testing this claim, namely, by means of the protocol sentence 
p2 about the intuitive impression of 

the firmness of the support? the excitement of A? 

The objector will point out that this sentence, after all, occurs in 
the protocol along with the perception sentence pi. May not then a 
system sentence whose content goes beyond that of P2 be founded 
on p2? This may be answered as follows. A sentence says no more 
than what is testable about it. If, now, the testing of Pi consisted in 
the deduction of the protocol sentence p2, these two sentences would 
have the same content. But we have already seen that this is im- 
possible. 

There is no other possibility of testing Pi except by means of 
protocol sentences like pi or like po. If, now% the content of Pi 
goes beyond that of P2, the component not shared by the two senr 
tences is not testable, and is therefore meaningless. If one rejects 
the interpretation of Pi in terms of P2, Pi becomes a metaphysical 
pseudo-sentence. 

The various sciences today have reached very different stages in 
the process of their decontamination from metaphysics. Chiefly be- 
cause of the efforts of Mach, Poincare, and Einstein, physics is. by 
and large, practically free of metaphysics. In psychology;, on the 
other hand, the work of arriving at a science which is to be free of 
metaphysics has hardly begun. The difference betw^een the tw'o sci- 
ences is most clearly seen in the different attitudes taken by experts 
in the two fields towards the position which we rejected as meta- 
physical and meaningless. In the case of the example from physics, 
most physicists would reject the position as anthropomorphic, or 
mythological, or metaphysical. They thereby reveal their anti-meta- 
physical orientation, which corresponds to our own. On the other 
hand, in the case of the example from psychology (though, perhaps, 
not when it is so crudely formulated), most psychologists would 
today consider the view we have been criticizing to be self-evident 
on intuitive grounds. In this one can see the metaphysical orientation 
of psychologists, to which ours is opposed. 


Psychology in Physical Language 


[175] 


4. Rejoinder to Four Typical Criticisms 

Generalizing the conclusion of the argument which, with refer- 
ence to a special case, we have been pursuing above, we arrive at 
the thesis that a singular sentence about other minds always has the 
same content as some specific physical sentence. Phrasing the same 
thesis in the material mode of speech — a sentence about other minds 
states that the body of the person in question is in a physical state 
of a certain sort. Let us now discuss several objections against this 
thesis of physicalism. 

A. Objection on the ground of the undeveloped state of physiol- 
ogy: “Our current knowledge of physiology — especially our knowl- 
edge of the physiology of the central nervous system — is not yet 
sufficiently advanced to enable us to know to what class of physical 
conditions something like excitement corresponds. Consequently, 
when today we use the sentence 'A is excited,’ we cannot mean by 
it the corresponding physical state of affairs.” 

Rebuttal Sentence Pi, “A is excited” cannot, indeed, today be 
translated into a physical sentence P3 of the form “such and such a 
physico-chemical process is now taking place in A’s body” (expressed 
by a specification of physical state-coordinates and by chemical 
formulae). Our current knowledge of physiology is not adequate for 
this purpose. Even today, however, Pi may be translated into another 
sentence about the physical condition of A’s body, namely into 
the sentence P2, to which we have already referred. This takes the 
form “A’s body is now in a state which is characterized by the fact 
that when I perceive A’s body the protocol sentence pi (stating my 
perception of A’s behavior) and (or) the protocol sentence po 
(stating my intuitive impression of A’s excitement) or other, analo- 
gous, protocol sentences of such and such a sort are produced.” Just 
as, in our example from physics, sentence Pi, “The wooden support 
is firm,” refers to the physical structure of the wooden support — and 
this even though the person using the sentence may sometimes not 
be capable of characterizing this physical structure by specifying the 
distribution of the values of the physical state-coordinates, so also 
does the psychological sentence Pi, “A is excited,” refer to the 
physical structure of A’s body — ^though this structure can only be 
characterized by potential perceptions, impressions, dispositions to 
react in a specific maimer, etc., and not by any specification of state- 
coordinates. Our ignorance of physiology can therefore affect only 
the mode of our characterization of the physical state of affairs in 







[ 176 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

qiiestioH. It in no way touches upon the principal point: that sen- 
tence Pi refers to a physical state of affairs. 

B, Objection on the ground of analogy: ‘"When I myself am 
angry, I not only act out the behavior-pattern of an angry man, I 
experience a special feeling of anger. If, consequently, I observe 
someone else acting out the same behavior-pattern I may, on grounds 
of analogy, conclude (if not with certainty, at least with probability) 
that he too, besides acting as he does, now has a feeling of anger 
(which is not meant as a physical state of affairs).” 

Rebuttal, Though arguments from analogy are not certain, as 
probability arguments they are undoubtedly admissible. By way of 
an example let us consider an every-day argument from anaiog}^ I 
see a box of a certain shape, size, and color. I discover that it con- 
tains matches. I find another box of a similar appearance, and now, 
by analogy, draw the probability inference that it too contains 
matches. Our critic believes that the argument from analogy he 
presents is of the same logical form as the argument just presented. 
If this were the case, his conclusion would certainly be sound. But 
this is not the case. In our critic’s argument, the conclusion is mean- 
ingless — a mere pseudo-sentence. For, being a sentence about other 
minds, not to be physically interpreted, it is in principle ndt testable: 
This w'as the result of our previous considerations; objection D will 
offer us an opportunity for discussing it again. In the non-testability 
of our critic’s conclusion rests also the difference between his argu- 
ments and the example just cited. That the second box also con- 
tains matches may in principle be tested and confirmed by observa- 
tion sentences of one’s protocol. The two analogous sentences, “The 
first box contains matches” and “The second box contains matches” 
are both logically and epistemologically of the same sort. This is why 
the analogy holds here. The case is different with “I am angry” and 
“That person is angry.” We consider the former of these two sen- 
tences to be meaningful and the latter (if its physical interpretation 
is rejected) to be meaningless. Our critic, who considers the latter 
as well as the former sentence to be meaningful, will believe that 
the person who asserts the sentence finds it testable, only in a manner 
altogether different from that in which the former is testable. Thus 
both of us agree that the latter sentence is epistemologically dif- 
ferent from the former. The use of the same grammatical structure 
in these two sentences is logically illegitimate. It misleads us into 
believing that the two sentences are of the same logical form, and 
that one may be used as an analogue of the other. 

If the conclusion is acknowledged to be meaningless, it remains 


Psychology in Physical Language [ ] 

to be explained how this pseudo-sentence was introduced into the 
argument. The logical analysis of concept formation and of sentences 
in science and (especially) in philosophy very frequently discloses 
pseudo-sentences. However, a pseudo-sentence rarely turns up as 
the conclusion of an argument from analogy with meaningful prem- 
ises. This may readily be accounted for. An argument from analogy 
has (in a simple case) the following form. Premises: If A has the 
property E, it always also has the property F; A^ resembles A in 
many respects; A' has the property E. We conclude (with proba- 
bility) : A' also has the property F. Now, according to semantics, if 
“A” and “B” are object-names, “E” and “F” property-names, and 
‘‘E(A)'’ means that A has the property E, then a) if “E(A)’' and 
‘‘E(B)'' are meaningful (i.e. either true or false), “A” and “B” 
belong to the same semantic ty^'pe; b) if two names, “A” and “B/’ 
belong to the same semantic type, and ‘T(A)” is meaningful, then 
“F(B)'’ is also meaningful. In the case under discussion here “E(A)” 
and “E(Aty” are meaningful, and consequently — in accordance with 
b) — “F(AO/’ the conclusion of the argument from analogy, is also 
meaningful. Thus if the premises of an argument from, analogy are 
meaningful and yet the conclusion is meaningless, the formulation 
of the premises must be in some way logically objectionable. And 
this is indeed the case with the argument from analogy presented 
by our critic. The predicative expression ‘1 am angry” does not 
adequately represent the state of affairs which is meant. It asserts 
that a certain property belongs to a certain entity. All that exists, 
however, is an experienced feeling of anger. This should have been 
formulated as, roughly, ‘'now anger.” On this correct formulation 
the possibility of an argument from analogy disappears. For now 
the premises read: when I (i.e. my body) display angry behavior, 
anger occurs; the body of another person resembles mine in many 
respects; the body of the other person is now displaying angry 
behavior. The original conclusion can now no longer be drawn, 
since the sentence “Anger occurs” contains no “I” which may be 
replaced by “the other person.” If one wanted to draw the appro- 
priate conclusion, in which no substitution is made but the form of 
the premises simply retained, one would arrive at the meaningful but 
plairily false conclusion, “Anger occurs” — ^which states what would 
be expressed in ordinary language by “I am now angry.” 

C. Objection on the ground of mental telepathy, “The telepathic 
transmission of the contents of consciousness (ideas, emotions, 
thoughts) occurs without any determinable physical mediation. Here 
we have an instance of the knowledge of other minds which involves 


.5 f 


fl 

- % 





[ 178 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

no perception of other people’s bodies. Let ns consider an example. 
I wake up suddenly one night, have a distinct sensation of fear, and 
know that my friend is now experiencing fear; later, I discover that 
at that very moment my friend was in danger of death. In this case, 
my knowledge of my friend’s fear : cannot refer to any state of his 
body, for I know nothing of that; my knowledge concerns itself im- 
mediately with my friend’s sensation of fear.” 

Rebuttal, Psychologists are not yet unanimously decided on the 
degree to which they ought properly to credit the occurrence of 
cases of telepathy. This is an empirical problem which it is not our 
business to solve here. Let us concede the point to our critic, and 
assume that the occurrence of cases of telepathic transmission has 
been confirmed. We shall show that, even so, our earlier contentions 
are not affected in the least. The question before us is: what does 
sentence Pi, “My friend now experiences fear” mean, if I take Pi 
to be a statement of telepathically derived cognition? We maintain 
that the meaning of Pi is precisely the same as it would be if we 
used it on the grounds of some normally (rationally or intuitively) 
derived cognition. The occurrence of telepathy in no way alters the 
meaning of Pi. 

Let us consider a precisely analogous situation involving the cog- 
nition of some physical event. I suddenly have the impression that 
a picture has fallen from the wall at my house, and this when neither 
I nor anyone else can in any normal way perceive that this has 
happened. Later, I discover that the picture has, indeed, fallen from 
the wall. I now express this cognition which I have obtained by 
clairvoyance in sentence Q, “The picture has now fallen from the 
wall.” What is the meaning of this sentence? The meaning of Q 
here is clearly the same as it would be if I used it on the ground of 
some normally derived cognition, that is, on the ground of some 
cognition by direct perception of the event in question. For in both 
cases Q asserts that a physical event of a certain sort, a specific dis- 
placement of a specific body, has taken place. 

The case is the same with telepathic cognition. We have already 
considered the case in which the state of some other mind is intui- 
tively grasped, though by means of a perception of the other person’s 
body. If a telepathic cognition of the state of some other mind 
occurs, it too is based on an intuitive impression, this time without 
a simultaneous perception. That which is cognized, however, is the 
same in both cases. Earlier, we remarked that Pi does not have the 
same content as the protocol sentence p2 about the (normally) intui- 
tive impression, and that cannot support a sentence about some- 



Psychology in Physical Language [ 179 ] 

tiling beside or behind the physical condition of the other person’s 
body. Our remarks hold equally for telepathically intuitive im- 
pressions. 

D. Objection on the ground of statements by others, “We are, to 
• begin with, agreed that A is in a certain physical state which is mani- 

fested fay behavior of a certain sort and produces in me, apart from 
sense-perceptions, an intuitive impression of A’s anger. Beyond this, 
however, I can find out that A really does experience anger by 
questioning him. He himself wHl testify that he experienced anger. 
Knowing him to be a truthful person and a good observer, why 
should I not consider his statement to be true — or at least probably 
I true?” 

i Rebuttal Before I can decide w^hether I should accept A’s state- 

j ment as true, or false, or probably true — before, indeed, I can con- 

sider this question at all — I must first of all understand the statement. 
It must have meaning for me. And this is the case only if I can 
test it, if, that is, sentences of my protocol are deducible from it. 
If the expression is interpreted physically it is testable by means of 
protocol sentences such as my pi and po, that is, by sentences about 
specific perceptions and intuitive expressions. Since, however, our 
critic rejects the physical interpretation of the expression, it is in 
principle impossible for me to test it. Thus it is meaningless for me, 
and the question whether I should consider it to be true, or false, 
or probable, cannot even be posed. 

Should unusual, brilliant patterns suddenly appear in the sky — 
even if they took the form of letters which seemed to compose a 
j sentence — science could not comprehend them except by first con- 

5 cehing them, describing them, and explaining them (i.e. subsuming 

j them under general causal-sentences) as physical facts. The question 

w'hether such an arrangement of symbols constitutes a meaningful 
sentence must be decided without taking into consideration whether 
or not it appears in the sky. K this symbol-arrangement is not a 
meaningful sentence at other times, it cannot become one no matter 
: how effulgent an appearance it makes in the sky. Whether a sen- 

I tence is true or false is determined by empirical contingencies; but 

whether a sentence is or is not meaningful is determined solely by 
the syntax of language. 

It is no different in the case of those acoustic phenomena that 
issue from the mouths of certain vertebrates. They are first of all 
facts, physical occurrences, and specifically, sound waves of a cer- 
tain sort. We can, further, also interpret them as symbols. But 
whether or not such an arrangement of symbols is meaningful can- 




[ 180 I EUDOLF CARNAP 

not depend on its occurrence as an acoustic phenomenon. If the 
sentence “A was angry yesterday at noon” has no meaning for me 
— as would be the case if (insofar as our critic rejects its physical 
meaning) I could not test it — it will not be rendered meaningful by 
the fact that a sound having the structure of this sentence came from 
A’s own mouth. 

But — it will be asked — do we not need the statements of our 
fellow-men for the elaboration of inter-subjective science? Would not 
physics, geography, and history become very meager studies if I 
had to restrict myself in them to occurrences which I myself had 
directly observed? There is no denying that they would. But there 
is a basic difference between a statement by A about the geography 
of China or about some historical event in the past on the one 
hand, and, on the other, a statement by A about the anger he felt 
yesterday. I can, in principle, test the statements of the first sort 
by means of perception sentences of my own protocol, sentences 
about my own perceptions of China, or of some map, or of historical 
documents. It is, however, in principle impossible for me to test 
the statement about anger if our critic asks me to reject the physical 
meaning of the sentence. If I have often had occasion to note 
that the geographical or historical reports that A makes can be con-” 
firmed by me, then, on the basis of an inductive probability inference, 
I consider myself justified in using his other statements — insofar as 
they are meaningful to me — in the elaboration of my scientific knowl- 
edge. It is in this way that inter-subjective science is developed. A 
sentence, however, which is not testable and hence not meaningful 
prior to its statement by A is not any the more meaningful after such 
a statement. If, in accordance with our position, I construe A’s state- 
ment about yesterday’s anger as a statement about the physical con- 
dition of A’s body yesterday, this statement may be used for the 
development of inter-subjective science. For we use A’s sentence as 
evidence (just to the extent to which we have found A to be trust- 
worthy) in support of the attribution of a corresponding physical 
structure to the corresponding spatio-temporal region of our physical 
world. Neither do the consequences which we draw from this attribu- 
tion generically differ from those that are obtained from any other 
physical statement. We build our expectations of future perceptions 
on it — in this case with respect to A’s behavior, as in other cases 
with respect to the behavior of other physical systems. 

The assertions of our fellow men contribute a great deal to ex- 
tending the range of our knowledge. But they cannot bring us any- 
thing basically new, that is, anything which cannot also be learned 




Psychology in Physical Language [ ] 

in some other way. For the assertions of our fellow men are, at 
bottom, no different from other physical events. Physical events are 
different from one another as regards the extent to which they may 
be used as signs of other physical events. Those physical events which 
we call “assertions of our fellow man” rank particularly high on this 
scale. It is for this reason that science, quite rightly, treats these 
events with special consideration. However, between the contribution 
of these assertions to our scientific knowledge and the contributions 
of a barometer there is, basically, at most a difference of degree. 

5. Behaviorism and “iNTUixrvT” Psychology 

The position w^e are advocating here coincides in its broad out- 
lines with the psychological movement knovn as “behaviorism” — 
when, that is, its epistemological principles rather than its special 
methods are considered. We have not linked our exposition with a 
statement of behaviorism since our only concern is with epistemo- 
logical foundations while behaviorism is above aU else interested 
in a specific method of research and in specific concept formations. 

The advocates of behaviorism were led to their position through 
their concern with animal psychoiog>'. In this domain, w^hen the 
material given to observation does not include statements but only 
inarticulate behavior, it is most easy to arrive at the correct method 
of approach. This approach leads one to the correct interpretation 
of the statements of human experimental subjects, for it suggests 
that these statements are to be conceived as acts of verba lizin g be- 
havior, basically no different from other behavior. 

Behaviorism is confronted with views, more influential in Ger- 
many than in the United States, which uphold the thesis that psy- 
chology’s concern is not with behavior in its physical aspect, but 
rather, with meaningful behavior. For the comprehension of mean- 
ingful behavior the special method known as “intuitive understand- 
ing” (“Verstehen”) is said to be required. Physics aUegedly knows 
nothing of this method. Neither meaningful behavior considered 
collectively nor the individual instances of such behavior which 
psychology investigates can possibly — so it is maintained — ^be char- 
acterized in terms of physical concepts. 

In intuitive psychology this view^ is generally linked with the view 
that beside physical behavior there is yet another, psychical event, 
which constitutes the true subject-matter of psychology, and to which 
intuitive understanding leads. We do not want to consider this idea 
any further here, since we have already thoroughly examined it. 




RUDOLF CARNAP 


[ 182 ] 

But even after one puts this idea aside, intuitive psychology 
poses the following objection to physicalism. 

Objection based on the occurrence of ** meaningful behavior” 
"‘When psychology considers the behavior of living creatures (we 
disregard here the question whether it deals only with such behavior), 
it is interested in it as meaningful behavior. This aspect of behavior 
cannot, however, be grasped in terms of physical concepts, but only 
by means of the method of intuitive understanding. And this is why 
psychological sentences cannot be translated into physical sentences.” 

Rebuttal. Let us recall a previous example of the physicalization 
of an intuitive impression, i.e. of a qualitative designation in the 
protocol language.^ We there showed that it is possible by investi- 
gating optical state-coordinates, to determine the entirety of those 
physical conditions which correspond to “green of this specific sort” 
and to subsume them under laws. The same is the case here. It simply 
depends on the physical nature of an act — say, of an arm-movement 
— whether I can intuitively understand it — as, say, a beckoning- 
motion — or not. Consequently, physicalization is possible here too. 
The class of arm-movements to which the protocol-designation “beck- 
oning motion” corresponds can be determined, and then described 
in terms of physical concepts. But perhaps doubts may be raised 
as to whether the classification of arm-movements as intelligible or' 
unintelligible, and, further, the classification of intelligible arm- 
movements as beckoning motions or others really dej>ends, as our 
thesis claims, solely on the physical constitution of the arms, the 
rest of the body, and the environment. Such doubts are readily re- 
moved if, for instance, one thinks of films. We understand the mean- 
ing of the action on the movie screen. And our understanding would 
doubtless be the same if, instead of the film presented, another 
which resembled it in every physical particular were shown. Thus 
one can see that both our understanding of meaning and the par- 
ticular forms it takes are, in effect, completely determined by the 
physical processes impinging on our sense-organs (in the film- 
example, those impinging on our optic and auditory sense-organs). 

The problem of physicalization in this area, that is, the problem 
of the characterization of understandable behavior as such and of 
the various kinds of such behavior by means of concepts of sys- 
tematized physics, is not as yet solved. But does not then our basic 
thesis rest on air? It states that all psychological sentences can be 
translated into physical sentences. One may well ask to what extent 


4. Erkenntnis, Vol. 11, op. cit., pp. 444 ff. {The Unity of Science, p. 58 ff.). 




Psychology in Physical Language [ ] 

such a translation is possible, given the present state of our knowl- 
edge. Even today every sentence of psychology can be translated 
into a sentence which refers to the physical behavior of living crea- 
tures. In such a physical characterization terms do indeed occur 
which have not yet been physicalized, i.e. reduced to the concepts of 
physical science. Nevertheless, the concepts used are physical con- 
cepts, though of a primitive sort — ^just as ‘‘warm” and ‘"green’" 
(applied to bodies) were physical concepts before one could express 
them in terms of physical state-coordinates (temperature and electro- 
magnetic field, respectively). 

We should like, again, to make the matter clear by using a 
physical example. Let us suppose that 'we have found a substance 
whose electrical conducti\ity is noticeably raised when it is irradi- 
ated by various types of electro-magnetic radiation. We do not yet, 
however, know the mtemal structure of this substance and so can- 
not yet explain its behavior. We want to call such a substance a 
“detector” for radiation of the sort involved. Let tis suppose, further, 
that we have not yet systematically determined to what sorts of 
radiation the detector reacts. We now discover that the sorts of 
radiation to which it responds share still another characteristic, say, 
that they accelerate specific chemical reactions. Now suppose that 
we are interested in the photo-chemical effects of various sorts of 
radiation, but that the determination of these effects, in the case of 
a specific sort of radiation, is difficult and time-consuming, while 
the determination of the detector’s reaction to it is easy and quickly 
accomplished; then we shall find it useful to adopt the detector as a 
test-instrument. With its aid we can determine for any particular 
sort of radiation whether or not it is likely to have the derired photo- 
chemical effect. This practical application will not be impeded by 
our ignorance of the detector’s micro-structure and our inability 
to explain its reaction in physical terms. In spite of our ignorance, 
we can certainly say that the detector isolates a certain physically 
specified class of rays. The objection that this is not a physical class 
since we cannot characterize it by a specification of optical state- 
coordinates but only by the behavior of the detector will not stand. 
For to begin with, we know that if we carried out a careful empirical 
investigation of the electro-magnetic spectrum, we could identify the 
class of rays to which the detector responds. On the basis of this 
identffication we could then physicalize the characterization of the 
rays in terms of detector-reactions, by substituting for it a charac- 
terization in terms of systematic physical concepts. But even our 
present way of characterizing the radiation in terms of the detector- 


j- lg4 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

test is a physical characterization, though an indirect one. It is dis- 
tinguished from the direct characterization wliich is our goal only 
through being more circumstantial. There is no diSerence of kind 
between the two characterizations, only one of degree, though the 
difference of degree is indeed sufficiently great to give us a motive 
for pursuing the empirical investigations which might bring the 
direct physical characterization within our grasp. 

Whether the detector is organic or inorganic is irrelevant to the 
epistemological issue involved. The function of the detector is basi- 
cally the same whether we are dealing with a physical detector of 
specific sorts of radiation or with a tree-frog as a detector of certain 
meteorological states of affairs or (if one may believe the news- 
papers) with a sniffing dog as a detector of certain human diseases. 
People take a practical interest in meteorological forecasts. Where 
barometers are not available they may, consequently, use a tree- 
frog for the same purpose. But let us be clear about the fact that 
this method does not determine the state of the tree-frogs soul, but 
a physically specified weather condition, even if one cannot describe 
this condition in terms of the concepts of systematized physics. 
People, likewise, have a. practical interest in medical diagnoses. 
When the directly determinable symptoms do not suffice, they may, 
consequently, enlist a dog’s delicate sense of smell for^the purpose. 
It is clear to the doctor that, in doing so, he is not determining the 
state of the dog’s soul, but a physically specified condition of his 
patient’s body. The doctor may not be able, given the present state 
of physiological knowledge, to characterize the diseased condition 
in question in terms of the concepts of systematic physics. Nonethe- 
less, he know's that his diagnosis — whether it is based on the symp- 
toms he liirnself has directly observed or on the reactions of the 
diagnostic dog — determines nothing and can determine nothing but 
the physical condition of his patient. Even apart from this, the 
physiologist acknowledges the need for physicaiization. This would 
here consist in describing the bodily condition in question, i.e. defin- 
ing the disease involved in purely physiological terms (thus elimi- 
nating any mention of the dog’s reaction). A further task would 
be to trace these back to chemical terms, and these, in turn, to 
physical ones. 

The case with intuitive psychology is precisely analogous. The 
situation here happens to be complicated for epistemological analysis 
(though for psychological practice it is simplified) by the fact that 
in the examination of an experimental subject the intuitive psycholo- 
gist is both the observer and detector. The doctor here is his own 


Psychology in Physical Language [ I 

diagnostic dog; which, indeed, is also often the case in medical 
diagnoses — in their intuitive phases. The psychologist calls the be- 
havior of the experimental subject “understandable” or, in a special 
case, for instance, “a nod of affirmation,” when his detector re- 
sponds to it, or — in our special case — ^when it results in his proto- 
cols registering “A nods ^rmatively.” Science is not a system of 
experiences, but of sentences; it does not include the psychologist’s 
experience of understanding, but rather, his protocol sentence. The 
utterance of the psychologist’s protocol sentence is a reaction whose 
epistemological function is analogous to the tree-frog’s climbing and 
to the barking of the diagnostic dog. To be sure, the psychologist 
far surpasses these animals in the variety of his reactions. As a 
result, he is certainly very valuable to the pursuit of science. But 
this constitutes only a difference of degree, not a difference of kind. 

In the light of these considerations, two demands are to be made of 
the psychologist. First, we shall expect him (as we expect the doctor) 
to be clear about the fact that, in spite of his complicated diagnostic 
reaction, he establishes nothing but the existence of some specific 
physical condition of the experimental subject, though a condition 
which can be characterized only indirectly — ^by his ovn diagnostic 
reaction. Secondly, he must acknowledge (as the physiologist does) 
that it is a task of scientific research to find a way of physicalizing 
the indirect characterization. Psychology’ must determine w^hat are 
the physical conditions to which people’s detector-reactions corre- 
spond. When this is carried out for even^' reaction of this sort, i.e. 
for every result of intuitive understanding, psychological concept for- 
mation can be physicalized. The indirect definitions based on detector- 
reactions w'il! be replaced by direct definitions in terms of the concepts 
of systematized physics. Psychologya like the other scierxes. must and 
will reach the level of development at which it can replace the tree- 
frog by the barometer. But even in the tree-frog stage psychology 
already uses physical language, though of a primitive sort. 

6. Physicalization in Graphology 

The purpose of this section is not to justify^ physicalism, but only 
to show how psychological concepts can in fact be physicalized. To 
this end we shall examine a branch of psychology’ in which physical- 
ization has already been undertaken with some success. In doing 
so we may perhaps also meet the criticism which is occasionally 
voiced, that the achievement of physicalization, assuming it were 
possible, would in any case be fruitless and uninteresting. It is held 


[ 186 ] RUDOLF CARNAF 

that, given sufficient information concerning the social group and the 
circumstances of the people involved, one might perhaps be able 
to specify arm-movements which are interpreted as beckoning- 
motions in such a way that they would be characterizable in terms of 
kinematic (i.e. spatio-temporal) concepts. But it is alleged that this 
procedure would not provide us with any further insist into any- 
thing of interest, least of all into the connections of these with other 
events. 

Remarkably enough, physicalization can show significant success 
in a branch of psychology which until comparatively recent times 
was pursued in a purely intuitive (or at most a pseudo-rational) 
manner and with wholly inadequate empirical data, so that it then 
had no claim to scientific status. This is graphology. Theoretical 
graphology — we shall concern ourselves here with no other sort — 
investigates the law-like relationships which hold between the formal 
properties of a person’s handwriting and those of his psychological 
properties that are commonly called his ‘‘character.” 

We must first of all explain what is meant by character in physical 
psychology. Every psychological property is marked out as a dis- 
position to behave in a certain way. By “actual property” we shall 
understand a property which is defined by characteristics that can be 
directly observed: by “disposition” (or “dispositional ;:oncept”> we 
shall understand a property which is defined by means of an implica- 
tion (a conditional relationship, an if-then sentence). Examples of 
familiar dispositional concepts of physics may serve to illustrate this 
distinction, and will, at the same time, illustrate the distinction between 
occurrent and continuant properties, a distinction which is important 
in psychology. An example of a physical occurrent property is a 
specific degree of temperature. We define “Body K has temperature 
T” to mean “When a sufficiently small quantity of mercury is brought 
into contact with K, then ...” When defined in this way, the concept 
of temperature is a dispositional concept. Now that physics has 
disclosed the micro-structure of matter and determined the laws of 
molecular motion, a different definition of temperature is used: 
temperature is the mean kinetic energy of molecules. Here, then, 
temperature is no longer a dispositional concept, but an actual 
property. The occurrent properties of psychology are logically analo- 
gous to the familiar dispositional concepts of physics. Indeed, on 
our view, they are themselves nothing else than physical concepts. 
Example: “Person X is excited” means “If, now, stimuli of such and 
such a sort were applied, X would react in such and such a manner” 
(both stimuli and reactions being physical events). Here too the 


Psychology in Physical Language [ 187 ] 

aim of science is to change the form of the definition; more accurate 
insight into the micro-structure of the human body should enable 
us to replace dispositional concepts by actual properties. That this 
is not a utopian aim is shown by the fact that even at the present time, 
a more accurate knowledge of physiological macro-events has yielded 
us a set of actual characteristics of occurrent states (e.g. for feelings 
of various sorts: frequency and intensity of pulse and respiration, 
glandular secretion, innervation of visceral muscles, etc.). Such a 
change of definitions is markedly more difficult when the states which 
have to be delimited are not emotional, for it then presupposes a 
knowledge of the micro-structure of the central nervous system which 
far surpasses the knowledge currently available. 

Physical constants, e.g. heat-conductivity, coefficient of refraction, 
etc. might be taken as examples of physical continuant properties. 
These too were originally defined as dispositional concepts, e.g. “A 
substance has a coefficient of refraction n” means “If a ray of light 
enters the substance, then . . . Here again the aim of transforming 
the definition has already been achieved for some concepts, and is 
being pursued in the case of the remainder. The reference to dispo- 
sitions gives way to an actual designation of the composition (in 
terms of atoms and electrons ) of the substance in question. The 
psychological continuant properties or “character properties” (the 
word “character” is here being used in a broad, neutral sense — to 
mean more than volitional or attitudinal properties) can, at present, 
be defined only in the form of dispositional concepts. Example: 
“X is more impressionable than Y” means “If both X and Y have 
the same experience under the same circumstances, more intense 
feelings are experienced by X than by Y.” In these definitions, both 
in the characterization of the stimuli (the statement of the circum- 
stances) and in that of the reaction, there are names which still 
designate psychological occurrent properties, for which the problem 
of physicaiization has not yet been solved. To physicalize the desig- 
nations of continuant properties will be possible only when the 
designations of occurrent properties have been dealt with. So long 
as these are not completely physicalized, the physicaiization of con- 
tinuant properties and, as a result, that of characterolog}^ as a whole, 
must remain in a scientifically incomplete state, and this no matter 
how rich our stock of intuitive knowledge may be. 

There is no sharp division between occurrent and continuant 
designations. Nonetheless, the difference of degree is large enough 
to justify their being differently labelled and differently treated, and, 
consequently, large enough to justify the separation of characterology 


[ 188 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

from psychology as a whole (considered as the theory of behavior). 
Graphology sets itself the task of finding in the features of a person’s 
handwriting indications of his character and, to some extent, of his 
occurrent properties. The practising graphologist does not intend the 
rational method to replace intuition, but only to support or to correct 
it. It has, however, become clear that the pursuit of the task of 
physicalization will serve even this purpose. Along these lines 
graphology has already, of late, made some significant discoveries. 

Since the problem of graphology is to discover the correspond- 
ences holding between the properties of a person’s handwriting and 
those of his character, we may here divide the problem of physical- 
ization into three parts. The physicalization of the properties of 
handwriting constitutes the first part of the problem. A certain script 
gives me, for instance, an intuitive impression of something full and 
juicy. In saying so, I do not primarily refer to characteristics of the 
writer, but to characteristics of his script. The problem now is to 
replace intuitively identified script-properties of this sort by prop- 
erties of the script’s shape, i.e. by properties which may be defined 
with the aid of geometrical concepts. That this problem can be 
solved is clear. We need only thoroughly investigate the system of 
forms which letters, words, and lines of script might possibly take 
in order to determine which of these forms make the inthitive im- 
pression in question on us. So, for instance, we might find that a 
script appears full or two-dimensional (as opposed to thin or linear) 
if rounded connections are more frequent than angles, the loops 
broader than normal, the strokes thicker, etc. This task of the 
physicalization of the properties of handwriting has in many cases 
been accomplished to a large extent.*'' We are not objecting to the 
retention of the intuitively derived descriptions (in terms, for in- 
stance, of “full,” “delicate,” “dynamic,” etc.). Our requirement will 
be adequately met as soon as a definition in exclusively geometric 
terms is provided for each such description. This problem is pre- 
cisely analogous to the problem, to which we have frequently re- 
ferred, of identifying in quantitative terms those physical conditions 
which correspond to a qualitative designation — such as “green of 
such and such a sort” — in the protocol language. 

The second part of the problem consists of the physicalization 
of the character properties referred to in graphological analyses. 
The traditional concepts of characterology — ^whose meaning is as a 

5. Cj. Klages, L., Handschrift und Character, Leipzig, 1920. Several of our 
Examples are taken from this book or suggested by it. 


Psychology in Physical Language [ 189 } 

rule not clearly defined, but left to be expressed in our everyday 
vocabulary or by means of metaphorical language — ^have to be 
systematized and given physicalistic (behavioristic) definitions. We 
have already seen that such a definition refers to a disposition to 
behave in a certain way, and further, that the task of the construc- 
tion of such definitions is difficult and presupposes the physicalization 
of psychological occurrent properties. 

We can see that in both parts of the problem the task is one of 
replacing primitive, intuitive concept formations by systematic ones, 
of replacing the observer with a tree-frog by the observer with a 
barometer (in graphology, as in intuitive medical diagnoses, the ob- 
server and the tree-frog coincide). 

In addition to these questions there is a third aspect of the 
problem to be considered: the basic empirical task of graphology. 
This consists of the search for the correlations which hold between 
the properties of handwriting and those of character. Here too, a 
systematization, though of a different sort, takes place. The cor- 
respondence of a specific property of handwriting to a specific prop- 
erty of character may, at first, be recognized intuitively — ^for instance, 
as a result of an empathetic reflection on the arm-movements which 
produced the script in question. The problem of systematization 
here is to determine the degree of correlation of the two properties 
by a statistical investigation of many instances of script of the type 
in question and the characters of the corresponding writers. 

Our position now is that the further development and clarifica- 
tion of the concepts of psychology as a whole must take the direction 
we have illustrated in our examination of graphoIog^^ the direction, 
that is, of physicalization. But as we have already emphasized sev- 
eral times, psychology is a physical science even prior to such a 
clarification of its concepts — a physical science whose assignment it 
is to describe systematically the (physical) behavior of living crea- 
tures, especially that of human beings, and to develop laws under 
which this behavior may be subsumed. These laws are of quite di- 
verse sorts. A hand movement, for instance, may be examined from 
various aspects: first, semioticaliy, as a more or less conventional 
sign for some designated state of affairs; secondly, mimically, as an 
expression of the contemporaneous psychological state — the occur- 
rent properties of the person in question; thirdly, physiognomically, 
as an expression of the continuant properties — ^the character of the 
person in question. In order to investigate, say, the hand movements 
of people (of certain groups) in their mimical and physiognomic 


[ 190 ] RUIX>LF CARNAP 

aspects one might perhaps take motion pictures of them, and, from 
these, derive kmematic diagrams of the sort which engineers coH” 
struct for machine parts. In this manner the shared kmematic (i.e., 
spatio-temporal) characteristics of the hand movements with whose 
perception certain intuitive protocol designations tend to be asso- 
ciated (e.g. “This hand movement looks rushed,” . . grandiose,” 
etc.) would have to be determined. It will now be clear why pre- 
cisely graphology — the characterological investigation of writing 
movements, a very special sort of hand movements, identifiable in 
terms of their specific purpose — should be the only study of this 
sort which can as yet show any results. The reason is that writing 
movements themselves produce something resembling kinematic 
diagrams, namely, the letters on the paper. To be sure, only the 
track of the movements is drawn. The passage of time is not recorded 
— the graphologist can subsequently only infer this, imperfectly, 
from indirect signs. More accurate results would be demonstrable 
if the complete three-dimensional spatio-temporal diagram, not only 
its projection on the writing plane, were available. But even the 
conclusions to which graphology currently subscribes allay what- 
ever misgivings there might have been that investigations directed 
at the physicalization of psychological concepts would prove to be 
uninteresting. It may not even be too rash a conjecture ^hat inter- 
esting parallels may be found to hold between the conclusions of 
characterological investigations of both the involuntary and the 
voluntaiy^ motions of the various parts of the human body on the one 
hand, and on the other hand the conclusions of graphology which 
are already available to us. If specific properties of a person’s char- 
acter express themselves both in a specific form of handwriting and 
in a specific form of arm motion, a specific form of leg motion, 
specific facial features, etc., might not these various forms resemble 
one another? Perhaps, after having first given fruitful suggestions 
for the investigation of other sorts of bodily movements, graphology 
may, in turn, be stimulated by the results to examine script prop- 
erties it had previously overlooked. These, of course, are mere con- 
jectures; whether or not they are justifiable cannot affect the ten- 
ability of our thesis, which maintains the possibility of translating 
all psychological sentences into physical language. This translata- 
bility holds regardless of whether or not the concepts of psychology 
are physicalized. Physicalization is simply a higher-level, more rigor- 
ously systematized scientific form of concept formation. Its accom- 
plishment is a practical problem which concerns the psychologist 
rather than the epistemologist. 


Psychology in Physical Language 


[191] 


7. Sentences about One’s Own Mind; 

“Introspective Psychology” 

Our argument has shown that a sentence about other minds 
refers to physical processes in the body of the person in question. 
On any other interpretation the sentence becomes untestable in 
principle, and thus meaningless. The situation is the same with sen- 
tences about one’s own mind, though here the emotional obstacles 
to a physical interpretation are considerably greater. The relation- 
ship of a sentence about one’s own mind to one about someone 
else’s may most readily be seen with respect to a sentence about 
some past state of one’s own mind, e.g. Pi: “I was excited yester- 
day.” The testing of this sentence involves either a rational inference 
from protocol sentences of the form of pi — which refer to presently 
perceived script, photographs, hlms, etc. originating with me yester- 
day; or it involves an intuitive method, e.g. utilizing the protocol 
sentence p2, “I recall having been excited yesterday.” The content 
of Pi exceeds both that of the protocol sentence pi and that of the 
protocol sentence po, as is most clearly indicated by the possibility 
of error and disavowal where Pi is concerned. Pi can only be pro- 
gressively better confirmed by sets of protocol sentences of the form 
of pi and p2. The veiy same protocol sentences, however, also con- 
firm the physical sentence P^: “My body was yesterday in that 
physical condition which one tends to call ‘excitement.’ ” Pi has, 
consequently, the same content as the physical sentence P2. 

In the case of a sentence about the present state of one’s own 
mind, e.g. Pi: “I now am excited” one must clearly distinguish 
between the system sentence Pi and the protocol sentence p2, which, 
likewise, may read “I now am excited.” The difference rests in the 
fact that the system sentence Pi may, under certain circumstances, 
be disavowed, w^hereas a protocol sentence, being an epistemological 
point of departure, cannot be rejected. The protocol sentences pi 
which rationally support Pi have here some such form as “I feel 
my hands trembling,” “I see my hands trembling,” “I hear my 
voice quavering,” etc. Here too, the content of Pi exceeds that of 
both Pi and p2, in that it subsumes aU the possible sentences of 
this sort. Pi has the same content as the physical sentence P2, “My 
body is now in that condition which, both under my own observa- 
tion and that of others, exhibits such and such characteristics of 
excitement,” the characteristics in question being those which are 
mentioned both in my own protocol sentences of the sort of pi 


[ 192 ] RUTOLF CJffiNAP 

and p2 other people’s protocol sentences of corresponding 

sorts (discussed above in our example of sentences about other 
minds). 

The table opposite shows the analogous application of the 
physicalist thesis to the three cases we have discussed by exhibiting 
the parallelism of sentences about other minds, sentences about 
some past condition of one’s own mind, and sentences about the 
present condition of one’s own mind, with the physical sentence 
about the wooden support. 

Objection from introspective psychology: "‘When the psycholo- 
gist is not investigating other experimental subjects, but pursues self- 
observation, or “introspection,” instead, he grasps, in a direct man- 
ner, something non-physical — and this is the proper subject-matter 
of psychology.” 

Rebuttal. We must distinguish between a question of the justifi- 
cation of the use of some prevalent practical method of inquir}* and 
a question of the justification of some prevalent interpretation of 
the results of that method. Every method of inquir}' is justified; dis- 
putes can arise only over the question of the purpose and fruitfulness 
of a given method, which is a question our problem does not in- 
volve. W^e may apply any method we choose; we cannot however, 
interpret the obtained sentences as we choose. Tne meaning of a 
sentence, no matter how obtained, can unequivocally be deter- 
mined by a logical analysis of the way in which it is derived and 
tested. A psychologist who adopts the method of what is called 
“introspection” does not thereby expose himself to criticism. Such 
a psychologist admits sentences of the form “I have experienced 
such and such events of consciousness” into his experiment-protocol 
and then arrives at general conclusions of his own by means of 
inductive generalization, the construction of hypotheses, and, finally, 
a comparison of his hypotheses with the conclusions of other persons. 
But again we must conclude, both on logical and epistemological 
grounds, that the singular as well as the general sentences must be 
interpreted physically. Let us say that psychologist A writes sen- 
tence P2: ""(I am) now excited” into his protocol. An earlier investi- 
gation^ has shown that the view which holds that protocol sentences 
cannot be physically interpreted, that, on the contraiy^ they refer 
to something non-physical (something “psychical,” some “experience- 
content,” some “datum of consciousness,” etc.) leads directly to 
the consequence that every protocol sentence is meaningful only 
to its author. If A’s protocol sentence p2 were not subject to a 


6. Erkenntnis, Vol. 11, p. 454, (The Unity of Science, pp. 78-79). 


THE PHYSICALISTIC INTERPRETATION OF PSYCHOLOGICAL SENTENCES 





[ 194 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

physical interpretation, it could not be tested by B, and would, thus, 
be meaningless to B. On the previous occasion in question we 
showed, further, that the non-physical interpretation leads one into 
insoluble contradictions. Finally, we found that every protocol sen- 
tence has the same content as some physical sentence,'^ and that 
this physical translation does not presuppose an accurate knowledge 
of the physiology of the central nervous system, but is feasible even 
at present. Sentences about one’s own min d — ^whether one takes 
these to be inter-subjective system sentences or so-called introspective 
protocol sentences — are thus in every case translatable into sen- 
tences of the physical language. 

One may perhaps object that there is, after all, a difference be- 
tween an experience and an utterance about it, and that not evtry 
experience has to be expressed in a protocol sentence. The differ- 
ence referred to certainly exists, though we would formulate it 
differently. Sentences Pi: ‘'A now sees red” and P^: “A now says 
T see red’ ” do not have exactly the same content. Nor does Pi 
justify the inference of P2; only the conditional sentence “If this 
and that occurs, then Po” may be inferred. For Pi ascribes a physical 
state to A of such a kind that, under certain circumstances, it leads 
to the event of speaking the sentence referred to ia Po. 

If we consider the method in accordance with whicli the con- 
clusions of so-called introspection are generally integrated with the 
body of scientific knowledge, we shall note that these conclusions 
are, indeed, physically evaluated. It so happens that the physicalism 
adopted in practice is generally not acknowledged in theory. Psychol- 
ogist A announces his experimental results; reader B reads in them, 
among others, the sentence “A was excited” (for the sake of clarity 
we write “A” instead of the word “I” which B in reading must 
replace by “A”). For B, this is a sentence about someone else’s 
mind; nothing of its claim can be verified except that A’s body 
was in such and such a physical condition at the time referred to. 
(We argued this point in our analysis of sentence Pi about someone 
else’s mind.) B himself could not, indeed, have observed this con- 
dition, but he can now indirectly infer its having existed. For, to 
begin with, he sees the sentence in question in a book on whose 
title-page A is identified as the author. Now, on the basis of a 
general sentence for which he has already obtained indirect evidence, 
B infers (with some degree of probability) that A wrote the sen- 
tences printed in this book; from this, in its turn, on the basis of 


7. Ibid., pp. 457 ff., (The Unity of Science, pp. 84 ff.). 


Psychology in Physical Language [ 195 ] 

a general sentence, with regard to A’s reliability, for which he again 
has good indnctive evidence, B infers that, had he observed A’s 
body at the relevant time he would (probably) have been able to 
conj&nn the existence of the state of (physical) excitement. Since 
this confirmation can refer only to some physical state of A’s body, 
the sentence in question can have only a physical meaning for B. 

Generally speaJdng, a psychologist’s spoken, written, or printed 
protocol sentences, when they are based on so-called introspection, 
are to be interpreted by the reader, and so figure in inter-subjective 
science, not chiefly as scientific sentences, but as scientific facts. The 
epistemological confusion of contemporary psychology stems, to a 
large extent, from this confusion of facts in the form of sentences 
with the sentences themselves considered as parts of science. (Our 
example of the patterns in. the sky is relevant here.) The intro- 
spective statements of a psychologist are not, in principle, to be 
interpreted any differently from the statements of his experimental 
subjects, which he happens to be reporting. The only distinction the 
psychologist enjoys is that, when the circumstances justify it, one 
may accept his statements as those of an exceptionally reliable and 
well-trained experimental subject. Further, the statements of an 
experimental subject are not, in principle, to be interpreted differ- 
ently from his other voluntary or involuntary movements — though 
his speech movements may, under favorable circumstances, be re- 
garded as especially informative. Again, the movements of the 
speech organs and of the other parts of the body of an experimental 
subject are not, in principle, to be interpreted differently from the 
movements of any other animal — ^though the former may, under 
favorable circumstances, be more valuable in the construction of 
general sentences. The movements of an animal are not, again, in 
principle, to be interpreted any differently from those of a volt- 
meter — ^though under favorable circumstances, animal movements 
may serve scientific purposes in more ways than do the movements 
of a volt-meter. Finally, the movements of a volt-meter are not, in 
principle, to be interpreted differently from the movements of a 
raindrop — though the former offer more opportunities for draw- 
ing inferences to other occurrences than do the latter. In all these 
cases, the issue is basically the same: from a specific physical sen- 
tence, other sentences are inferred by a causal argument, i.e. with 
the help of general physical formulae — ^the so-called natural laws. 
The examples cited differ only in the degree of fruitfulness of their 
premises. Volt-meter readings will, perhaps, justify the inference 
of a greater number of scientifically important sentences than the 


[ 196 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

behavior of some speciic raindrop will; speech movements wUl, in 
a certain respect, justify more such inferences than other human 
bodily movements wiU. Now, in the case with which we are con- 
cerned here, the inference from the sign to the state of affairs signi- 
fied has a quite remarkable form. In using someone’s introspective 
statement about the state of his own mind (e.g. A’s statement; “A is 
excited”), the statement, taken as an acoustic event, is the sign; 
under favorable conditions, which are frequently satisfied in scien- 
tific contexts, the state of affairs referred to is such that it can be 
described by a sentence (“A is excited”) of the very same form 
as the acoustic event which functions as a sign of it. [The requisite 
conditions are that the person in question be considered reliable and 
qualified to make psychological reports, and further that the lan- 
guage of these reports be the same as that of the scientific system.] 
This identity of the form of the acoustic fact and the scientific sen- 
tence which is to be inferred from it explains why the two are so 
easily and so obstinately confused. The disastrous muddle into which 
this confusion leads us is cleared up as soon as we realize that here, 
as in the other cases cited, it is only a question of drawing an in- 
ference from a sign to that which it indicates. 

It becomes all the more clear that so-called introspective state- 
ments caxmot be given a non-physical interpretation when we con- 
sider how' their use is learned. A tired child says “Now I am happy 
to be in bed.” If we investigated how the child learned to talk 
about the states of his own mind we would discover that, under 
similar circumstances, his mother had said to him, “Now you are 
happy to be in bed.” Thus we see that A learns to use the protocol 
sentence p2 from B — who, however, interprets this series of words 
as constituting the system sentence P2, a sentence, for B, about 
someone else’s mind. Learning to talk consists of B’s inducing a 
certain habit in A, a habit of “verbalizing” (as the behaviorists 
put it) in a specific manner in specific circumstances. And, indeed 
one tends so to direct this habit that the series of words produced 
by the speech movements of the child A coincides with the sentence 
of the intersubjective physical language which not only describes the 
appropriate state of A, but — and this is the essential point — describes 
A’s state as B perceives it, that is, the physical state of A’s body. 
The example of the child shows this especially clearly. The sen- 
tence, “You are happy,” spoken by the mother, is a sentence about 
someone else’s mind, and thus, according to our earlier analysis, 
can designate nothing but some physical state of affairs. The child 
is thus induced to develop the habit of responding to specific cir- 


Psychology in Physical Language [ 197 ] 

cumstaEces by utteriiig a sentence which expresses a physical state 
observed by some other person (or inferred by some other person 
from observed signs). If the child utters the same sounds again on 
some other occasion, no more can be inferred than that the child’s 
body is again in that physical state. 

8. Summary 

So-called psychological sentences — whether they are concrete 
sentences abomt other minds, or about some past condition of one’s 
own mind, or about the present condition of one’s own mind, or, 
finally, general sentences — are always translatable into physical 
language. Specifically, every psychological sentence refers to physical 
occurrences in the body of the person (or persons) in question. On 
these grounds, psychology is a part of the domain of unified science 
based on physics. By “physics” we wish to mean, not the system 
of currently known physical laws, but rather the science character- 
ized by a mode of concept formation which traces ever}^ concept 
back to state-coordinates, that is, to systematic assignments of num- 
bers to space-time points. Understanding “physics” in this way, we 
can rephrase our thesis — a particular thesis of physicalism — as fol- 
lows: psychology is a branch of physics. 


REMARKS BY THE AUTHOR (1957) 

I would still maintain the essential content of the main thesis 
of this article, I would today modify some special points. Perhaps the 
most important of them is the following. In the article I regarded a 
psychological term, say “excited,” as designating a state characterized 
by the disposition to react to certain stimuli with overt behavior of 
certain kinds. This may be admissible for the psychological concepts 
of eveiy^day language. But at least for those of scientific psychology, as 
also of other fields of science, it seems to me more in line with the 
actual procedure of scientists, to introduce them not as disposition 
concepts, but rather as theoretical concepts (sometimes called “hypo- 
thetical constructs”). This means that they are introduced as primitives 
by the postulates of a theory, and are connected with the terms of the 
observ^ation language, which designate observable properties, by so- 
called rules of correspondence. This method is explained and discussed 
in detail in my article “The Methodological Character of Theoretical 
Concepts,” in H. Feigl and M. Scriven, (eds., Minnesota Studies in the 
Philosophy of Science ^ Vol. 1. 


{ 198 ] RUDOLF CARNAP 

The main thesis of physicalism remains the same as before. It says 
that psychological statements, both those of everyday life and of 
scientific psychology, say something about the physical state of the 
person in question. It is different from the corresponding statements in 
terms of micro-physiology or micro-physics (which at the present stage 
of scientific development are not yet known, comp. § 4A above) by 
using the conceptual framework of psychology instead of those of 
the two other fields. To find the specific features of the correspondence 
will be an empirical task (comp. § 6, the third part of the procedure of 
physicaiization). Once known, the correspondence can be expressed by 
empirical laws or, according to our present view, by theoretical pos- 
tulates. Our present conception of physicalism, the arguments for it, 
and the development which led to it, are represented in the following 
two articles by Herbert Feigi: (1) “Physicalism, Unity of Science and 
the Foundations of Psychology,” in: P. A. Schilpp, editor, The Philos- 
ophy of Rudolf Carnap (Library of Living Philosophers); see also my 
reply to Feigi in the same volume; (2) “The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical,’’’ 
in Voi. n of Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science. 



9 


Protocol Sentences 


BY OTTO NEURATH 


(translated by GEORGE SCHICK) 


With the progress of knowledge, the number of expressions which 
are formulated with a high degree of precision in the language of 
Unified Science is continually on the increase. Even so, no such 
scientific term is wholly precise; for they are ail based upon terms 
which are essential for protocol sentences; and it is immediately 
obvious to eveiy'one that these terms must be vague. 

The fiction of an ideal language constructed out of pure atomic 
sentences is no less metaphysical than the fiction of Laplace’s demon. 
The language of science, with its ever increasing development of 
symbolic systems, cannot be regarded as an approximation to such 
an ideal language. The sentence “Otto is observing an angry^ person” 
is less precise than the sentence “Otto is observing a thermometer 
reading 24 degrees,” insofar as the expression “angry person” can- 
not be so exactly defined as “thermometer reading 24 degrees.” But 
“Otto” itself is in many w^ays a vague term. The phrase “Otto is 
observing” could be replaced by the phrase “The man, whose care- 
fully taken photograph is listed no. 16 in the file, is observing”: 
but the term “photograph listed no. 16 in the file” still has to be 
replaced by a system of mathematical formulae, which is unam- 
biguously correlated with another system of mathematical formulae, 

This article first appeared in Volume III of Erkenntnis (1932/33). It is published 
here with the kind permission of Mrs. Marie Neurath and Professor Rudolf Carnap. 
At the beginning of Ms article Neurath had the following note: “References will be 
to Rudolf Carnap’s article, ‘Die Physikaiische Sprache als Universaisprache der 
Wissenschaft,’ Erkenntnis, 1932, VoL II, pp. 432ff.* Since there is widespread 
agreement with Carnap, we shall adopt his terminology. So that I need not repeat 
what I have already w-ritien elsewhere, I refer the reader to my articles ‘Physikal- 
ismus,’ Scientia, 1931, pp. 297 ff. and ‘Soziologie im Physikaiismus,’ Erkenntnis, 
VoL n, 1932, pp. 393 ff.’’ 

[* There is an English translation of this article by Max Black under the title 
“The Unity of Science.” It was published as a monograph by Kegan Paul, London.] 


'f! f ; 

f w. 




[ 200 ] OTTO NEUEATH 

the terms of which take the place of ‘‘Otto,” “angry Otto,” “friendly 
Otto,” etc. 

"^at is originally given to us is our ordinary natural language 
with a stock of imprecise, unanalyzed terms. We start by purifying 
this language of metaphysical elements and so reach the physicalistic 
ordinary language. In accomplishing this we may fund it veiy^ useful 
to draw up a list of proscribed words. 

There is also the physicalistic language of advanced science 
which we can so construct that it is free from metaphysical elements 
from the start. We can use this language only for special sciences, 
indeed only for parts of them. 

If one wished to express aU of the unified science of our time in 
one language, one would have to combine terms of ordinary language 
with terms of the language of advanced science, since, in practice, 
the two overlap. There are some terms which are used only in 
ordinary language, others which occur only in the language of ad- 
vanced science, and still others which appear in both languages. 
Consequently, in a scientific treatise concerned with the entire field 
of unified science only a “slang” comprising words of both languages 
will serve. 

We believe that every word of the physicalistic ordinary' language 
will prove to be replaceable by terms taken from the language of 
advanced science, just as one may also formulate the terms of the 
language of advanced science with the help of the terms of ordi- 
nary language. Only the latter is a very unfamiliar proceeding, and 
sometimes not easy. Einstein’s theories are expressible (somehow) 
in the language of the Bantus — but not those of Heidegger, unless 
linguistic abuses to which the German language lends itself are intro- 
duced into Bantu. .4 physicist must, in principle, be able to satisfy 
the demand of the talented writer who insisted that: “One ough\ 
to be able to make the outlines of any rigorously scientific thesis 
comprehensible in his own terms to a hackney-coach-driver.” 

The language of advanced science and ordinary language coin- 
cide today primarily in the domain of arithmetic. But, in the system 
of radical physicalism, even the expression “2 times 2 is 4,” a 
tautology, is linked to protocol sentences. Tautologies are defined in 
terms of sentences which state how tautologies function as codicils 
appended to certain commands under certain circumstances. For 
instance: “Otto says to Karl ‘Go outside when the flag waves and 
when 2 times 2 is four.’ ” The addition of the tautology here does 
not alter the effect of the command. 

Even considerations of rigorous scientific method restrict us to 


Frotocol Sentences [ 201 ] 

the use of a “universal slang" Since there is as yet no general agree- 
ment as to its composition, each scholar who concerns himself with 
these matters must utilize a universal slang to which he himself has 
contributed new terms. 

There is no way of taking conclusively established pure protocol 
sentences as the starting point of the sciences. No tabula rasa 
exists. We are like sailors who must rebuild their ship on the open 
sea, never able to dismantle it in dry-dock and to reconstruct it 
there out of the best materials. Only the metaphysical elements can be 
allowed to vanish without trace. Vague linguistic conglomerations 
always remain in one way or another as components of the ship. 
If vagueness is diminished at one point, it may well be increased 
at another. 

We shall from the ver\^ first, teach children the universal-slang 
— ^purged of all metaphysics — as the language of the historically 
transmitted unified science. Each child vdll be so trained that it 
starts with a simplified universal-slang, and advances gradually to 
the use of the universal-slang of adults. In this connection, it is 
meaningless to segregate this children's language from that of the 
adults. One would, in that case, have to distinguish several universal- 
slangs. Tne child does not learn a prlmiiive universal-slang from, 
which the universal-slang of the adults derives. He learns a ‘"poorer” 
universal-slang, which is gradnaily filled in. The expression “ball 
of iron” is used in the language of adults as well as in that of chil- 
dren. In the former it is defined by a sentence in which terms such 
as “radius” and ‘V” occur, while in the children’s definition words 
such as “nine-pins,” “present from Uncle Rudi,” etc. are used. 
But “Uncle Rudi” also crops up in the language of rigorous science, 
if the physical ball is defined by means of protocol sentences in 
which “Uncle Rudi” appears as “the observer who perceives a ball.” 

Carnap, on the other hand, speaks of a primitive protocol lan- 
guage.^ His comments on the primitive protocol language — on the 
protocol sentences which “require no verification” — are only mar- 
ginal to his significant anti-metaphysical views, the mainspring of 
which is not affected by the objections here brought forward, Carnap 
speaks of a primaiy^ language, also referred to as an experiential or 
as a phenomenalistic language. He maintains that “at the present 
stage of inquiry, the question of the precise characterization of this 
language cannot be answered.” These comments might induce 

1. Op, cit., Erkenntnis, VoL II, pp, 437 2. and 453 S. (Unity of Science, pp. 
42 2. and 76 2.). 


[ 202 ] OTTO NEORATH 

younger men to search for a protocol language of the sort described; 
and this might easily lead to metaphysical deviations. Although 
metaphysical speculation cannot altogether be restrained by argu- 
ment, it is important, as a means of keeping waverers in line, to 
maintain physicalism in its most radical version. 

Apart from tautologies, unified science consists of factual sen- 
tences. These may be sub-divided into 

(a) protocol sentences 

(b) non-protocol sentences. 

Protocol sentences are factual sentences of the same form as the 
others, except that, in them, a personal noun always occurs several 
times in a specific association with other terms. A complete protocol 
sentence might, for instance, read: “‘Otto’s protocol at 3:17 o’clock: 
[At 3:16 o’clock Otto said to himseK: (at 3:15 o’clock there was 
a table in the room perceived by Otto)].” This factual sentence is 
so constructed that, within each set of brackets, further factual sen- 
tences may be found, viz-: “At 3:16 o’clock Otto said to himself: (At 
3:15 o’clock there was a table in the room perceived by Otto)” and 
“At 3:15 o’clock there was a table in the room perceived Ijy Otto.” 
These sentences are, however, not protocol sentences. 

Each term occurring in these sentences may, to some extent, be 
replaced at the veiy^ outset by a group of terms of the language of 
advanced science. One may introduce a system of physicalistic desig- 
nations in place of “Otto,” and this system of designations may, in 
turn, further be defined by referring to the “position” of the name 
“Otto” in a group of signs composed of the names “Karl,” “Hein- 
rich,” etc. All the words used in the expression of the above protocol 
sentence are either words of the universal-slang or may without diffi- 
culty be replaced at any moment by words of the universal-slang. 

For a protocol sentence to be complete it is essential that the 
name of some person occur in it.“Now joy,” or “Now red circle,” 
or “A red die is lying on the table” are not complete protocol sen- 
tences.^ They are not even candidates for a position within the inner- 
most set of brackets. For this they would, on our analysis, at least 
have to read “Otto now joy,” or “Otto now sees a red circle,” or 
“Otto now sees a red die lying on the table” — ^which would roughly 
correspond to the children’s language. That is, in a full protocol sen- 

2. Cf. Carnap, op. cit., Erkenntnis, VoL II, pp. 438 ff. {Unity of Science, pp. 


Frotocol Sentences [ ] 

tence the expression within the innennost set of brackets is a sentence 
which again features a personal nonn and a term from the domain 
of perception-terms. The relative extent to which terms of ordinary 
langnage and of the language of advanced science are used is of 
no significance, since the universal-slang may be used with consid- 
erable flexibility. 

The expression “said to himself,” after the first bracket, recom- 
mends itself when, as above, one wants to construct various groups 
of sentences, as, for instance, sentences incorporating reality-terms, 
or hailucination-terms, or dream-terms, and especially when one 
wants to identify unreality as such. For instance, one could say: 
“Otto actually said to himself, There was nothing in the room but 
a bird perceived by Otto’ but, in order to amuse himself, he wrote, 
‘There w^as nothing in the room but a table perceived by Otto.’ ” This 
is especially pertinent to the discussion in the next section, in 
which we reject Carnap’s thesis to the efieci that protocol sentences 
are those “which require no verification.” 

The transformation of the sciences is effected by the discarding 
of sentences utilized in a previous historical period, and, frequently, 
their replacement by others. Sometimes the same form of words is 
retained, but their defiunitions are changed. Every Icnv and every 
physicalistic sentence of unified-science or of one of its sub-sciences 
is subject to such change. And the same holds for protocol sentences. 

In unified science we tiy’ to construct a non-contradictory system 
of protocol sentences and non-protocol sentences (including laws).- 
When a new sentence is presented to us we compare it with the 
system at our disposal, and determine whether or not it conflicts 
with that system. If the sentence does conSict wdth the system, we 
may discard it as useless (or false), as, for instance, w’ould be done 
with “In Africa lions sing only in major scales.” One may, on the 
other hand, accept the sentence and so change the system that it 
remains consistent even after the adjunction of the new' sentence. 
The sentence would then be called “true.” 

The fate of being discarded may befall even a protocol sentence. 
No sentence enjoys the noli me tangere w^hich Carnap ordains for 
protocol sentences. Let us consider a particularly drastic example. 
We assume that we are acquainted with a scholar called “Kaion,” 
who can write with both hands simultaneously. He writes with his 
left hand, “Kalon’s protocol at 3:17 o’clock: [At 16 minutes 30 

3. Cf. Carnap, op. cit., Brkenntnis, VoL II, pp. 439 ff. {Unity of Science, pp. 
47 ff.). 


[ 204 ] OTTO NEimATH 

seconds past 3 o’clock Kalon said to himself: (There was nothing 
in the room at 3:16 o’clock except a table perceived by Kalon)].” 
At the same time, with his right hand, he writes, ‘‘Kalon’s protocol 
at 3:17 o’clock: [At 16 minutes 30 seconds past 3 o’clock Kalon 
said to himself: (There was nothing in the room at 3:16 o’clock 
except a bird perceived by Kalon)].” What is he — and what are 
we — to make of the conjunction of these two sentences? We may, 
of course, make statements such as ‘‘Marks may be found on this 
sheet of paper, sometimes shaped this way and sometimes that.” 
With respect to these marks on paper, however, Carnap’s word 
“verification” finds no application. “Verification” can only be used 
with reference to sentences, that is, with reference to sequences of 
marks which are used in a context of a reaction-test and which may 
systematically be replaced by other marks.- Synonymous sentences 
may be characterized as stimuli which under specific reaction-tests 
evoke the same responses. Chains of ink-marks on paper and chains 
of air-vibrations which may under specific conditions be co-ordinated 
with one another are called “sentences.” 

Two conflicting protocol sentences cannot both be used in the 
system of unified science. Though we may not be able to tell which 
of the two is to be excluded, or whether both are not to be excluded, 
it is clear that not both are verifiable, that is, that both^do not fit 
into the system. 

If a protocol sentence must in such cases be discarded, may not 
the same occasionally be called for when the contradiction between 
protocol sentences on the one hand and a system comprising proto- 
col sentences and non-protocol sentences (laws, etc.) on the other 
is such that an extended argument is required to disclose it? On 
Carnap’s view, one could be obliged to alter only non-protocol 
sentences and laws. We also allow for the possibility of discarding 
protocol sentences. A defining condition of a sentence is that it be 
subject to verification, that is to say, that it may be discarded. 

Carnap’s contention that protocol sentences do not require veri- 
fication, however it may be understood, may without difficulty be 
related to the belief in immediate experiences which is current in 
traditional academic philosophy. According to this philosophy there 
are, indeed, certain basic elements out of which the world-picture is 
to be constructed. On this academic view, these atomic experiences 
are, of course, above any kind of critical scrutiny; they do not re- 
quire verification. 

Carnap is trying to introduce a kind of atomic protocol, with 


4. Cf. my article in Scientia, p. 302. 



Protocol Sentences [ 205 ] 

Ms demand that “a clear-cut distinction be made in scientific pro- 
cedure between the adoption of a protocol and the interpretation of 
the protocol sentences,” as a result of which “no indirectly acquired 
sentences would be accepted into the protocol.”^ The above for- 
mulation of a complete protocol sentence shows that, insofar as 
personal nouns occur in a protocol, interpretation must always 
already have taken place. When preparing scientific protocols, it 
may be useful to phrase the expression within the innermost set of 
brackets as simply as possible, as, for instance, “At 3 o'clock Otto 
was seeing red,” or — another protocol — “At 3 o’clock Otto was 
hearing C sharp,” etc. But a protocol of such a sort is not primitive 
in Carnap’s sense, since one cannot, after all, get around Otto’s 
act of perception. There are no sentences in the universal-slang 
which one may characterize as “more primitive” than any others. 
All are of equal primitiveness. Personal nouns, words denoting per- 
ceptions, and other words of little prhniiiveness occur in ail factual 
sentences, or, at least, in the hypotheses from which they derive. 
All of which means that there are neither primitive protocol sentences 
nor sentences which are not subject to verification. 

The universal-siapg, in the sense explained above, is the same 
for the child as for the adult. It is the same for a Robinson Crusoe 
as for a human society. If Crusoe wants to relate what he registered 
(“protokolliert”) yesterday with what he registers today, that is, 
when he wants to have any sort of recourse to a language, he cannot 
but have recourse to the inter-subjective language. The Crusoe of 
yesterday and the Crusoe of today stand to one another in pre- 
cisely the relation in which Crusoe stands to Friday. Consider a 
man who has both lost his memoiy* and been blinded, who is now 
learning afresh to read and to write. The notes which he himself 
took in the past and which now, with the aid of a special apparatus, 
he reads again are for him as much the notes of some other man 
as notes actually written by someone else. And the same would 
still be the case after he had realized the tragic nature of his cir- 
cumstances, and had pieced together the story of his life. 

In other words, every language as such is inter-subjective. The 
protocols of one moment must be subject to incorporation in the 
protocols of the next, just as the protocols of A must be subject 
to incorporation in the protocols of B. It is therefore meaningless 
to talk, as Carnap does, of a private language, or of a set of dis- 
parate protocol languages which may ultimately be dra\^m together. 

5. Op. ciL, p. 437 {Unity of Science, p. 42). 


[ 206 ] OTTO NEURATH 

The protocol languages of the Crusoe of yesterday and of the Crusoe 
of today are as close and as far apart from one another as are the 
protocol languages of Crusoe and of Friday. If, under certain cir- 
cumstances, the protocol languages of yesterday’s Crusoe and of 
today’s are called the same language, then one may also, under 
the same circumstances, call the protocol language of Crusoe and 
that of Friday the same language. 

In Carnap’s writings we also encounter an emphasis on the ‘T’ 
familiar to us from idealistic philosophy. In the universal-slang it 
is as meaningless to talk of a personal protocol as to talk of a here 
or a now. In the physicalistic language personal nouns are simply 
replaced by co-ordinates and coefficients of physical states. One can 
distinguish an Otto-protocol from a KarUprotocol, but not a proto- 
col of one’s own from a protocol of others. The whole puzzle of 
other minds is thus resolved. 

Methodological solipsism and methodological positivism^ do not 
become any the more serviceable because of the addition of the 
word ‘‘methodological.”^ 

For instance, had I said above, “Today, the 27th of July, I ex- 
amine protocols both of my own and of others,” it would have been 
more correct to have said “Otto Neurath’s protocol at 10:00 a.m., 
July 27, 1932; [At 9:35 o’clock Otto Neurath said to himself: (Otto 
Neurath occupied himself between 9:40 and 9:57 with a protocol 
by Neurath and one by Kalon, to both of which the following two 
sentences belong: . . .)].” Even though Otto Neurath himself for- 
mulates the protocol concerning the utilization of these protocols, 
he does not link his own protocol with the system of unified science 
in any different way from that in which he links Kalon’s. It may well 
happen that Neurath discards one of Neurath’s protocols, and adopts 
in its stead one of Kalon’s. The fact that men generally retain their 
own protocol sentences more obstinately than they do those of 
other people is a historical accident which is of no real significance 
for our purposes. Carnap’s contention that “every individual can 
adopt only his own protocol as an epistemological basis” cannot be 
accepted, for the argument presented in its favor is not sound: “Si 
can, indeed, also utilize the protocol of So — and the incorporation 
of both protocol languages in physicalistic language makes this utili- 
zation particularly easy. The utilization is, however, indirect: Si 
must first state in his own protocol that he sees a piece of writing 

6. Cf. Carnap, op. cit., Erkenntnis, Vol. II, p. 461 (Unity of Science, p. 93). 

7. Cf. my article in. Erkenntnis, VoL 11, p. 401. [Translated in the present volume, 
see p. 282 below.] 


Protocol Sentences [ ] 

of such and such a form.”^ But Neurath must describe Neurath's 
protocol in a manner analogous to that in which he describes Kalon's! 
He describes how Neurath’s protocol looks to him as well as how 
Kalon’s does. 

In this way we can go on to deal with everyone’s protocol sen- 
tences. Basically, it makes no difference at all whether Kalon works 
with Kalon’s or with Neurath’s protocols, or whether Neurath oc- 
cupies himself with Neurath’s or with Kalon’s protocols. In order 
to make this quite clear, we could conceive of a sorting-machine 
into which protocol sentences are thrown. The laws and other factual 
sentences (including protocol sentences) serving to mesh the ma- 
chine’s gears sort the protocol sentences which are thrown into the 
machine and cause a beU to ring if a contradiction ensues. At this 
point one must either replace the protocol sentence whose intro- 
duction into the machine has led to the contradiction by some other 
protocol sentence, or rebuild the entire machine. Who rebuilds the 
machine, or whose protocol sentences are thrown into the machine 
is of no consequence whatsoever. Anyone may test his own protocol 
sentences as well as those of others. 

Summing Up: 

Unified science utilizes a universal-slang, in which terms of the 
physicalistic ordinary language necessarily also occur. 

Children can be trained to use the universal-slang. Apart from 
it we do not employ any specially distinguishable “basic” protocol 
sentences, nor do different people make use of different protocol 
languages. 

We find no use in unified science for the expressions “methodo- 
logical solipsism” and “methodological positivism.” 

One cannot start with conclusively established, pure protocol 
sentences. Protocol sentences are factual sentences like the others, 
containing names of persons or names of groups of people linked 
in specific ways with other terms, which are themselves also taken 
from the universal-slang. 

The Vienna Circle devotes itself more and more to the task of 
expressing unified science (which includes sociology as well as 
chemistry, biology as well as mechanics, psychology — ^more properly 
termed “behavioristics” — as well as optics) in a unified language, 
and with the displaying of the inter-connections of the various 
sciences which are so often neglected; so that one may without 


8. Cf. Camap, op. ciu, Erkenntms, Vol. 11, p. 461 (The Unity of Science, p. 93). 


[ 208 ] OTTO NEimATH 

difficulty relate the terms of any science to those of any other. The 
word “man” which is prefixed to “makes assertions” is to be defined 
in just the same way as the word “man” occurring in sentences which 
contain the words “economic system” and “production.” 

The Vienna Circle has received powerful encouragement from 
various sources. The achievements of Mach, Poincare, and Duhem 
have been turned to as good account as the contributions of Frege, 
Schroder, and Russell. Wittgenstein’s writings have been extraordin- 
arily stimulating, both through what has been taken from them and 
through what has been rejected. His original plan — to use philosophy 
as a ladder which it is necessary to climb in order to see things clearly 
— ^may, however, be considered to have come to grief. The main 
issue in this, as in all other intellectual activities, will always be to 
bring the sentences of unified science — both protocol sentences and 
non-protocol sentences — into consonance with one another. For 
this, a logical syntax of the sort toward which Carnap is working 
is required — Carnap’s logical reconstruction of the world being the 
first step in this direction. 

The discussion I have initiated here — ^for Carnap will certainly 
find much in the corrections to correct again and to develop — serves, 
as do so many of our other efforts, to secure ever more firmly the 
common, broad foundations on which all the adherents (rf physicalism 
base their studies. Discussions of peripheral issues, such as this 
one, are, however, going to play a continuously diminishing role. The 
rapid progress of the work of the Vienna Circle shows that the 
planned co-operative project dedicated to the construction of unified 
science is in constant development. The less time we find it necessary 
to devote to the elimination of ancient confusions and the more we 
can occupy ourselves with the formulation of the inter-connections 
of the sciences, the quicker and more successful will this construction 
be. To this end it is of the first importance that we learn how to use 
the physicalistic language, on behalf of which Carnap, in his article, 
entered the lists. 


10 


The Foundation of Knowledge 
BY MORITZ SCHLICK 
(translated by DAVID RYNIN) 


All mportant attempts at establisiimg a theory of knowledge 
grow" out of the problem concerning the certainty of human knowl- 
edge. And this problem in turn originates in the wish for absolute 
certaiiit}\ 

The insight that the statements of daily life and science can at 
best be only probable, that even the most general results of science, 
which all experiences confirm, can have only the character of 
hypotheses, has again and again stimulated philosophers since 
Descartes, and indeed, though less obviously, since ancient times, to 
search for an unshakeable, indubitable, foundation, a firm basis 
on which the uncertain structure of our knowledge could rest. The 
uncertaint}^ of the structure was generally attributed to the fact that 
it was impossible, perhaps in principle, to construct a firmer one 
by the power of human thought. But this did not inhibit the search 
for the bedrock, which exists prior to all construction and does not 
itself vacillate. 

This search is a praiseworthy, healthy effort, and it is prevalent 
even among “relativists” and “sceptics, who would rather not ac- 
knowledge it.” It appears in different forms and leads to odd dif- 
ferences of opinion. The problem of “protocol statements,” their 
structure and function, is the latest form in which the philosophy or 
rather the decisive empiricism of our day clothes the problem of 
the ultimate ground of knowledge. 

What was originally meant by “protocol statements,” as the 
name indicates, are those statements which express the facts with ab- 
solute simplicity, without any moulding, alteration or addition, in 
whose elaboration every science consists, and which precede all know- 

This article, originally entitled “Dber das Fundament der Erkenntnis,” first ap- 
peared in Erkenntnis, VoL IV (1934). It is published here with the kind permission 
of Mrs. Schlick and Professor Camap. 


£209 ] 


MORITZ SCHLICK 


[210] 

mg, every judgment regarding the world It makes no sense to speak 
of uncertain facts. Only assertions, only our knowledge can be 
uncertain. If we succeed therefore in expressing the raw facts in 
“protocol statements,” without any contamination, these appear 
to be the absolutely indubitable starting points of all knowledge. 
They are, to be sure, again abandoned the moment one goes over 
to statements winch are actually of use in life or science (such a 
transition appears to be that from “singular” to “universal” state- 
ments), but they constitute nevertheless the firm basis to which all 
our cognitions owe whatever validity they may possess. 

Moreover, it makes no difference whether or not these so-called 
protocol statements have ever actually been made, that is, actuaffy 
uttered, written down or even only explicitly “thought”; it is required 
only that one know what statements form the basis for the notations 
which are actually made, and that these statements be at all times 
reconstructible. If for example an investigator makes a note, “Under 
such and such conditions the pointer stands at 10.5,” he knows that 
this means “two black lines coincide,” and that the words “under 
such and such conditions” (which we here imagine to be specified) 
are likewise to be resolved into definite protocol statements which, 
if he wished, he could in principle formulate exactly, although per- 
haps with difficulty. ^ 

It is clear, and is so far as I know disputed by no one, that 
knowledge in life and science in some sense begins with confirmation of 
facts, and that the “protocol statements” in which this occurs stand in 
the same sense at the beginning of science. What is this sense? Is 
“beginning” to be understood in the temporal or logical sense? 

Here we already find much confusion and oscillation. If I said 
above that it is not important whether the decisive statements have 
been actually made or uttered, this means evidently that they need 
not stand at the beginning temporally, but can be arrived at later 
just as well if need be. The necessity for formulating them would arise 
when one wished to make clear to oneself the meaning of the statement 
that one had actually written down. Is the reference to protocol state- 
ments then to be understood in the logical sense? In that event they 
would be distinguished by definite logical properties, by their struc- 
ture, their position in the system of science, and one would be 
confronted with the task of actually specitying these properties. In 
fact, this is the form in which, for example, Carnap used explicitly 
to put the question of protocol statements, while later^ declaring it 
to be a question which is to be settled by an arbitrary decision. 


1. See Carnap, “Ober ProtokoUsatze,” Erkennmis, Vol. Ill, pp. 216 ff. 


The Foundation of Knowledge [211 ] 

On the other hand, we find many expositions which seem to pre- 
suppose that by “protocol statements” only those assertions are to 
be understood that also temporally precede the other assertions 
of science. And is this not correct? One must bear in mind that it 
is a matter of the ultimate basis of knowledge of reality, and that it 
is not sufficient for this to treat statements as, so to speak, “ideal 
constructions” (as one used to say in Platonic fashion), but rather 
that one must concern oneself with real occurrences, with events that 
take place in time, in which the making of judgments consists, 
hence with psychic acts of “thought,” or physical acts of “speak- 
ing” or “writing.” Since psychic acts of judgment seem suitable 
for establishing inter-subjectively valid knowledge only when trans- 
lated into verbal or written expressions (that is, into a physical 
system of symbols) “protocol statements” come to be regarded 
as certain spoken, written or printed sentences, i.e., certain symbol- 
complexes of sounds or printer’s ink, which when translated from 
the common abbreviations into full-fledged speech, would mean 
something like: “Mr. N. N. at such and such a time observed so and 
so at such and such a place.” (This view was adopted particularly 
by O. Neurath).- As a matter of fact, when we retrace the path 
by which we actually arrive at all our knowledge, we doubtless 
always come up against this same source: printed sentences in books, 
words out of the mouth of a teacher, our own observations (in the 
latter case we are ourselves N. N. ) . 

On this view protocol statements would be real happenings in 
the world and would temporally precede the other real processes 
in which the “construction of science,” or indeed the production of 
an individual’s knowledge consists. 

I do not know to what extent the distinction made here between 
the logical and temporal priority of protocol statements corresponds 
to differences in the views actually held by certain authors — but 
that is not important. For we are not concerned to determine who 
expressed the correct view, but what the correct view is. And for this 
our distinction between the two points of view will serve well enough. 

As a matter of fact, these two views are compatible. For the 
statements that register simple data of observation and stand tem- 
porally at the beginning could at the same time be those that by 
virtue of their structure would have to constitute the logical starting- 
point of science. 

2. Neurath, "‘ProtokoUsatze,” Erkenntnis, Voi. Ill, pp. 104 S. (Tiiis article is 
translated in the present volume, see pp. 199-208 above.) 


[ 212 ] 


MORITZ SCHLICK 


II 

The question which wiU first interest us is this: What progress 
is achieved by formulating the problem of the ultimate basis of 
knowledge in terms of protocol statements? The answer to this 
question will itseK pave the way to a solution of the problem. 

I think it a great improvement in method to try to aim at the 
basis of knowledge by looking not for the primary facts but for the 
primary sentences. But I also think that this advantage was not made 
the most of, perhaps because of a failure to realize that what was 
at issue, fundamentally, was just the old problem of the basis. I be- 
lieve, in fact, that the position to which the consideration of protocol 
statements has led is not tenable. It results in a peculiar relativism, 
which appears to be a necessaiy’^ consequence of the \iew that proto- 
col statements are empirical facts upon which the edifice of science 
is subsequently built. 

That is to say: when protocol statements are conceived in this 
manner, then directly one raises the question of the certainty with 
which one may assert their truth, one must grant that they are ex- 
posed to all possible doubts. 

There appears in a book a sentence which says, for example, 
that N. N. used such and such an instrument to mikt such and such 
an observation. One may under certain circumstances have the 
greatest confidence in this sentence. Nevertheless, it and the observa- 
tion it records, can never be considered absolutely certain. For the 
possibilities of error are innumerable. N. N. can inadvenently or in- 
tentionally have described something that does not accurately repre- 
sent the observed fact; in writing it down or priming it, an error may 
have crept in. indeed the assumption that the symbols of a book 
retain their form even for an instant and do not “of themselves” 
change into new sentences is an empirical hypothesis, which as such 
can never be strictly verified. For eveiy verification would rest on 
assumptions of the same sort and on the presupposition that our 
memory does not deceive us at least dunng a brief interval, and 
so on. 

This means, of course — and some of our authors have pointed 
this out almost with a note of triumph — ^that protocol statements, so 
conceived, have in principle exactly the same character as all the other 
statements of science: they are hypotheses, nothing but hypotheses. 
They are anything but incontrovertible, and one can use them in the 
construction of the system of science only so long as they are sup- 


The Foundation of Knowledge [213] 

ported by, or at least not contradicted by, other hypotheses. We 
therefore always reserve the right to make protocol statements sub- 
ject to correction, and such corrections, quite often indeed, do occur 
when we eliminate certain protocol statements and declare that they 
must have been the result of some error. 

Even in the case of statements which we ourselves have put for- 
ward we do not in principle exclude the possibility of error. We 
grant that our mind at the moment the judgment was made may have 
been wholly confused, and that an experience which we now say we 
had two minutes ago may upon later examination be found to have 
been an hailucination, or even one that never took place at all. 

Thus it is clear that on this view of protocol statements they do 
not provide one who is in search of a firm basis of knowledge with 
anything of the sort. On the contrary, the actual result is that one 
ends by abandoning the original distinction between protocol and 
other statements as meaningless. Thus we come to understand how 
people come to think^ that any statements of science can be selected 
at will and called “protocol statements,” and that it is simply a 
question of convenience which are chosen. 

But can we admit this? Are there really only reasons of con- 
venience? It is not rather a matter of where the particular statements 
come from, what is their origin, their history? In general, what is 
meant here by convenience? What is the end that one pursues in mak- 
ing and selecting statements? 

The end can be no other than that of science itself, namely, that 
of affording a true description of the facts. For us it is self-evident that 
the problem of the basis of knowledge is nothing other than the ques- 
tion of the criterion of truth. Surely the reason for bringing in the 
term “protocol statement” in the first place was that it should 
serve to mark out certain statements by the truth of which the truth 
of all other statements comes to be measured, as by a measuring 
rod. But according to the viewpoint just described this measuring rod 
would have shown itself to be as relative as, say, all the measuring 
rods of physics. And it is this view with its consequences that has 
been commended as the banishing of the last remnant of “abso- 
lutism” from philosophy.^ 

But what then remains at all as a criterion of truth? Since the 
proposal is not that all scientific assertions must accord with certain 
definite protocol statements, but rather that all statements shall ac- 
cord with one another, with the result that every single one is consid- 


3. K. Popper as quoted by Carnap, op. cit., Erkenntnis, Vol. Ill, p. 223. 

4. Carnap, op. cit., p. 228. 


MORITZ SCHLICK 


[214] 

ered as, in principle, corrigible, truth can consist only in a mutual 
agreement of statements, 

in 

This view, which has been expressly formulated and represented 
in this context, for example, by Neurath, is well known from the 
history of recent philosophy. In England it is usually called the 
“coherence theory of truth,” and contrasted with the older “corre- 
spondence theory.” It is to be observed that the expression “theory” 
is quite inappropriate. For observations on the nature of truth have 
a quite different character from scientific theories, which always 
consist of a system of hypotheses. 

The contrast between the two views is generally expressed as 
follows: according to the traditional one, the truth of a statement 
consists in its agreement with the facts, while according to the other, 
the coherence theory, it consists in its agreement with the system 
of other statements. 

I shall not in general pursue the question here whether the latter 
view can not also be interpreted in a way that draws attention 
to something quite correct (namely, to the fact that in a quite 
definite sense we cannot “go beyond language” as Wittgenstein 
puts it). I have here rather to show that, on the interpretation re- 
quired in the present context, it is quite untenable. 

If the truth of a statement is to consist in its coherence or agree- 
ment with the other statements, one must be clear as to what one 
understands by “agreement,” and which statements are meant by 
“other.” 

The first point can be settled easily. Since it cannot be meant 
that the statement to be tested asserts the same thing as the others, 
it remains only that they must be compatible with it, that is. that no 
contradictions exist between them. Truth would consist simply in 
absence of contradiction. But on the question whether truth can 
be identified simply with the absence of contradiction, there ought 
to be no further discussion. It should long since have been gen- 
erally acknowledged that only in the case of statements of a tauto- 
logical nature are truth (if one will apply this term at all) and 
absence of contradiction to be equated, as for instance with the 
statements of pure geometry. But with such statements every con- 
nection with reality is purposely dissolved; they are only formulas 
within a determinate c^culus; it makes no sense in the case of the 
statements of pure geometry to ask whether they agree with the 
facts of the world: they need only be compatible with the axioms 


The Foundation of Knowledge [ ] 

"arbitrarily laid down at the begmning (in addition, it is usually 
also required that they follow from them) in order to be called true 
or correct. We have before ns precisely what was earlier called 
formal truth and distinguished from material truth. 

The latter is the truth of synthetic statements, assertions of 
matters of fact, and if one wishes to describe them by help of the 
concept of absence of contradiction, of agreement with other state- 
ments, one can do so only if one says that they may not contra- 
dict very special statements, namely just those that express “facts 
of immediate observation.” The criterion of truth cannot be com- 
patibility with any statements whatever, but agreement is required 
with certain exceptional statements which are not chosen arbitrarily at 
all. In other words, the criterion of absence of contradiction does not 
by itself suffice for material truth. It is, rather, entirely a matter of 
compatibility with very special peculiar statements. And for this com- 
patibility there is no reason not to use — ^indeed I consider there is 
every justification for using — the good old expression “agreement 
with reality.” 

The astounding error of the “coherence theory” can be explained 
only by the fact that its defenders and expositors were thinking only 
of such statements as actually occur in science, and took them as 
their only examples. Under these conditions the relation of non- 
contradiction was in fact sufficient, but only because these state- 
ments are of a very special character. They have, that is, in a certain 
sense (to be explained presently) their “origin” in observation 
statements, they derive, as one may confidently say in the traditional 
way of speaking, “from experience.” 

If one is to take coherence seriously as a general criterion of 
truth, then one must consider arbitraiy fairy stories to be as true as a 
historical report, or as statements in a textbook of chemistry, provided 
the story is constructed in such a way that no contradiction ever arises. 
I can depict by help of fantasy a grotesque world full of bizarre 
adventures : the coherence philosopher must believe in the truth 
of my account provided only I take care of the mutual compatibility of 
my statements, and also take the precaution of avoiding any collision 
with the usual description of the world, by placing the scene of my 
story on a distant star, where no observation is possible. Indeed, 
strictly speaking, I don’t even require this precaution; I can just as 
well demand that the others have to adapt themselves to my descrip- 
tion; and not the other way round. They cannot then object that, 
say, thiy^ happening runs counter to the observations, for according 


MORITZ SCHLICK 


[ 216 ] 

to the coherence theory there is no question of observations, but only 
of the compatibility of statements. 

Since no one dreams of holding the statements of a story book 
true and those of a text of physics false, the coherence view fails 
utterly. Something more, that is, must be added to coherence, namely, 
a principle in terms of which the compatibility is to be established, 
and this would alone then be the actud criterion. 

If I am given a set of statements, among which are found some 
that contradict each other, I can establish consistency in a number of 
ways, by, for example, on one occasion selecting certain statements 
and abandoning or altering them and on another occasion doing 
the same with the other statements that contradict the jfirst. 

Thus the coherence theory is showm to be logically impossible; 
it fails altogether to give an unambiguous criterion of truth, for by 
means of it I can arrive at any number of consistent systems of state- 
ments which are incompatible with one another. 

The only way to avoid this absurdity is not to allow any state- 
ments whatever to be abandoned or altered, but rather to specify 
tihose that are to be maintained, to which the remainder have to be 
accommodated. 

IV 

The coherence theory is thus disposed of, and We have in the 
meantime arrived at the second point of our criiical considerations, 
namely, at the question w^hether all statements are corrigible, or 
whether there are also those that cannot be shaken. These latter 
would of course constitute the "‘basis” of all knowledge which w^e 
have been seeking, without so far being able to take any step to- 
wards it. 

By what mark, then, are we to distinguish these statements 
which themselves remain unaltered, while all others must be brought 
into agreement with them? We shall in what follows call them not 
“protocol statements,” but “basic statements” for it is quite dubious 
whether they occur at all among the protocols of science. 

The most obvious recourse would doubtless be to find the rule 
for which we are searching in some kind of economy principle, 
namely, to say: we are to choose those as basic statements whose 
retention requires a minimum of alteration in the whole system of 
statements in order to rid it of all contradictions. 

It is worth noticing that such an economy principle would not 
enable us to pick out certain statements as being basic once and 
for all, for it might happen that with the progress of science the 


The Foundation of Knowledge [211 \ 

basic statements that served as such up to a given moment would 
be again degraded, if it appeared more economical to abandon them 
in favor of newly found statements which from that time on — 
until further notice — ^would play the basic role. This would, of course, 
no longer be the pure coherence viewpoint, but one based on econ- 
omy; “relativity,” however, would characterize it also. 

There seems to me no question but that the representatives of the 
view we have been criticizing did in fact take the economy principle 
as their guiding light, whether explicitly or implicitly; I have therefore 
already assumed above that on the relativity view there are pur- 
posive grounds which determine the selection of protocol statements, 
and I asked: Can we admit this? 

I now answer this question in the negative. It is in fact not 
economic purposiveness but quite other characteristics which dis- 
tinguish the genuine basic statements. 

The procedure for choosing these statements would be called 
economic if it consisted say in conforming to the opinions (or “proto- 
col statements”) of the majority of investigators. Now it is of course 
the case that we do not doubt the existence of a fact, for example a 
fact of geography or history, or even of a natural law, when we 
find that in the relevant contexts its existence is very frequently 
reported. It does not occur to us in those cases to wish to in- 
vestigate the matter ourselves. We acquiesce in what is universally 
acknowledged. But this is explained by the fact that we have pre- 
cise knowledge of the manner in which such factual statements tend 
to be made, and that this manner wins our confidence; it is not 
that it agrees with the view of the majority. Quite the contrary, 
it could only arrive at universal acceptance because everyone feels 
the same confidence. Whether and to what extent w'^e hold a state- 
ment to be corrigible or amiulabie depends solely on its origin, and 
(apart from veiy' special cases) not at all upon whether mamtaining 
it requires the correction of very many other statements and per- 
haps a reorganization of the whole system of knowledge. 

Before one can apply the principle of economy one must know 
to which statements it is to be applied. And if the principle were 
the only decisive rule the answer could only be: to all that are 
asserted with any claim to validity or have ever been so asserted. 
Indeed, the phrase “with any claim to validity” should be omitted, 
for how^ should we distinguish such statements from those which were 
asserted quite arbitrarily, as jokes or with intent to deceive? This 
distinction cannot even be formulated without taking into considera- 


[ 218 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

tion the derivation of the statements. So we find ourselves once more 
referred to the question of their origin. Without having classified 
statements according to their origin, any application of the economy 
principle of agreement would be quite absurd. But once one has ex- 
amined the statements with respect to their origin it becomes im- 
mediately obvious that one has thereby already ordered them in 
terms of their validity, and that there is no place left for the appli- 
cation of the principle of economy (apart from certain veiy special 
cases in still unfinished areas of science). We can see also that the 
establishment of this order points the way to the basis of which we 
are in search. 

V 

Here of course the greatest care is necessaiy’. For we are tread- 
ing on the path which has been followed from ancient times by all 
those who have ever embarked upon the journey towards the ultimate 
grounds of truth. And always they have failed to reach the goal. 
In the ordering of statements according to their origin which I un- 
dertake for the purpose of judging their certainty, I start by assigning 
a special place to those that I make myself. And here a secondary 
position is occupied by those that lie in the past, for we believe 
that their certainty can be impaired by “errors of memor}^” — and 
indeed in genera] the more so the farther back in time they lie. On 
the other hand, the statements which stand at the top, free from all 
doubt, are those that express facts of one’s own “perception,” or 
whatever you like to call it. But in spite of the fact that statements 
of this sort seem so simple and clear, philosophers have found them- 
selves in a hopeless labyrinth the moment they actually attempted 
to use them as the foundation of all knowledge. Some puzzling sec- 
tions of this labyrinth are for example those formulations and deduc- 
tions that have occupied the center of so many philosophical disputes 
under the heading “evidence of inner perception,” “solipsism,” “so- 
lipsism of the present moment,” “self-conscious certainty,” etc. 
The Cartesian cogito ergo sum is the best-known of the destinations 
to which this path has led — a terminating point to which indeed 
Augustine had already pushed through. And concerning cogito 
ergo sum our eyes have today been sufficiently opened: we know 
that it is a mere pseudo-statement, which does not become genuine 
by being expressed in the form '"cogitatio esf — “the contents of 
consciousness exist.”^ Such a statement, which does not express 
anything itself, cannot in any sense serve as the basis of anything. 

5. Cf. “Positivismus und Realismus,” Erkenntnis, Vol. Ill, p. 20 (see the present 
volume, p. 82 above) . 


The Foundation of Knowledge [ 219 ] 

It is not itself a cognition, and none rests upon it. It cannot lend 
certainty to any cognition. 

There exists therefore the greatest danger that in following the 
path recommended one will arrive at empty verbiage instead of the 
basis one seeks. The critical theory of protocol statements origi- 
nated indeed in the wish to avoid this danger. But the way out 
proposed by it is unsatisfactor}''. Its essential deficiency lies in ig- 
noring the different rank of statements, which expresses itself most 
clearly in the fact that for the system of science which one takes 
to be the “right” one, one’s own statements in the end play the 
only decisive role. 

It would be theoretically conceivable that my own observations 
in no way substantiate the assertions made about the world by 
other men. It might be that all the books that I read, all the teachers 
that I hear are in perfect agreement among themselves, that they never 
contradict one another, but that they are simply incompatible with 
a large part of my own obseiv^ation statements. (Certain difficulties 
would in this case accompany the problem of learning the language 
and its use in communication, but they can be removed by means 
of certain assumptions concerning the place in which the contra- 
dictions are to appear.) According to the view we have been criticiz- 
ing I would in such a case simply have to sacrifice my own “protocol 
statements,” for they would be opposed by the overwhelming mass 
of other statements which would be in mutual agreement themselves, 
and it would be impossible to expect that these should be corrected 
in accordance with my own limited fragmentary^ experience. 

But what wnuid actually happen in such a case? Well, under no 
circumstances would I abandon my own observation statements. 
On the contrary, I find that I can accept only a system of knowledge 
into which they fit unmutilated. And I can always construct such 
a system. I need only view^ the others as dreaming fools, in whose 
madness lies a remarkable method, or — ^to express it more ob- 
jectively — I would say that the others live in a different world from 
mine, which has just so much in common with mine as to make it 
possible to achieve understanding by means of the same language. 
In any case no matter what world picture I construct, I would test 
its truth always in terms of my own experience. I would never per- 
mit anyone to take this support from me: my own observation 
statements would ahvays be the ultimate criterion. I should, so to 
speak, exclaim “What I see, I see!” 










[220 ] 


MORITZ SCHLICK 


VI 

In the light of these preliminary critical remarks, it is clear where 
we have to look for the solution of these confusing difficulties: we 
must use the Cartesian road in so far as it is good and passable, 
but then be careful to avoid falling into the cogito ergo sum and 
related nonsense. We effect this by making clear to ourselves the 
role which really belongs to the statements expressing ‘‘the immedi- 
ately observed.” 

What actually lies behind one’s saying that they are “absolutely 
certain”? And in what sense may one describe them as the ultimate 
ground of all knowledge? 

Let us consider the second question first. If we imagine that 
I at once recorded every observation — and it is in principle indif- 
ferent whether this is done on paper or in memorv’ — and then began 
from that point the construction of science, I should have before 
me genuine “protocol statements” which stood temporally at the 
beginning of knowledge. From them would gradually arise the rest 
of the statements of science, by means of the process called “induc- 
tion,” which consists in nothing else than that I am stimulated 
or induced by the protocol statements to establish tentative generali- 
zations (hypotheses), from which those first statements, but also 
an endless number of others, follow logically. If now these others 
express the same as is expressed by later observation statements that 
are obtained under quite definite conditions which are exactly speci- 
fiable beforehand, then the hypotheses are considered to be confirmed 
so long as no observation statements appear that stand in contradic- 
tion to the statements derived from the hypotheses and thus to the 
hypotheses themselves. So long as this does not occur we believe our- 
selves to have hit correctly upon a law^ of nature. Induction is thus 
nothing but methodically conducted guessing, a psychological, bio- 
logical process whose conduct has certainly nothing to do with “logic.” 

In ffiis way the actual procedure of science is described schemati- 
cally. It is evident what role is played in it by the statements con- 
cerning what is “immediately perceived.” They are not identical 
with those written down or memorized, with what can correctly be 
called “protocol statements,” but they are the occasions of their 
formation. The protocol statements observed in a book or memory 
are, as we acknowledged long ago, so far as their validity goes, 
doubtless to be compared to hypotheses. For, when we have such a 
statement before us, it is a mere assumption that it is true, that it 


The Foundation of Knowledge [221 ] 

agrees with the observation statements that give rise to it, (Indeed 
it may have been occasioned by no obsen’ation statements, but 
derived from some game or other.) What I call an observation state- 
ment cannot be identical with a genuine protocol statement, if 
only because in a certain sense it cannot be v^Titten down at all — 
a point which we shall presently discuss. 

Thus in the schema of the building up of knowledge that I have 
described, the part played by observation statements is first that of 
standing temporally at the beginning of the whole process, stimulating 
it and setting it going. How much of their content enters into 
knowledge remains in principle at first undetermined. One can thus 
with some justice see in the observation statements the ultimate 
origin of all knowledge. But should they be described as the basis, 
as the ultimate certain ground? This can hardly be maintained, for 
this “origin” stands in a too questionable relation to the edifice of 
knowledge. But in addition we have conceived of the true process 
as schematically simplified. In reality whai is actually expressed in 
protocols stands in a less close connection wiih the observed, and in 
general one ought not to assume that any pure observation statements 
ever slip in between the observation and the “protocol.” 

But now a second function appears to belong to these statements 
about the immediately perceived, these “confirmations”* as we may 
also can them, namely, the corroboration of hypotheses, their verifi- 
cation. 

Science makes prophecies that are tested by “experience.” Its 
essential function consists in making predictions. It says, for ex- 
ample: “If at such and such a time you look through a telescope 
adjusted in such and such a manner you will see a point of light 
(a star) in coincidence with a black mark (cross wires).” Let us 
assume that in following out these instructions the predicted ex- 
perience actually occurs. This means that ^ve make an anticipated 

* The term used by the author is ‘'tConstatierung'* which he sometimes equates 
with “observation statement’* i.e., “Beobachiungssatz,” and generally tends to 
quote, in a manner indicating his awareness that it is a somewhat unusuil usage and 
perhaps a not altogether adequate technical term. Wilfred Sellars in a recently 
published essay (“Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind,” Minnesota Studies in 
the Philosophy of Science, Volume I, Universit>- of Minnesota Press, 1956) uses the 
term “report” in referring to what seems to be the kind of statement Schlick is 
discussing. I do not adopt this term, despite some undoubted advantages it has 
over “confirmation,” because of the close connection mat “Konstatierung” has with 
confirmation or verification, a connection so close tha: Schlick uses the same term 
unquoted to refer to confirmation. Furthermore, as the text shows, confirmations 
are never false, as Schlick understands them; but this is certainly not a characteristic 
of reports, as the term “report” is used in everyday or even scientific language. 
(Translator’s note.) 


[ 222 ] 

MORITZ SCHLICK 

^ ^ expected judgment of observation, 

isfflrHr>r,° ^ feeling of fulfilment, a quite characteristic sat- 

onnfi “• satisfied. One is fully justified in saying that the 

sio?^^ observation statements have fulfilled their true mis- 

soon as we obtain this peculiar satisfaction. 

talrec moment in which the confirmation 

the iu^r.ct • ™ observation statement is made. This is of 

the imm function of the statements about 

expenenced itself lies in the immediate present. 

moment duration, that the 

scrintio ‘^^sposa! in their place in- 

tenable ctrLl ^ ultimate certainty. One cannot build any logically 
mnrr, ructure upon the confirmations, for they are gone the 
the nloce^T construct. If they stand at the beginning of 

logically of no use. Quite other- 

also fakifirar verification (or 

renre th ^ completion, and in the moment of their occur- 

hepends already fulfiUed their duty. Logically nothing more 

StitUtt M °b?oiute“d”'’°‘“‘°“ ““ 

cnijf- Psyciiologically and biologicaliv a new process' of 

S'vLfiS“ ''“5 •'■‘S' “«“■ 

formi.i m them are considered to be upheld, and the 

searr'h V°° general hypotheses is sought, the guessing and 

sSl Z The observation statements con- 

in thsa “ ° Stimuli for these events that follow in time 

m the sense described earlier. 

cle 1 ^^^«h^•^ means of these considerations a new and 

edoe problem of the ultimate basis of knowl- 

edge’ tal-P-c, clearly how the construction of the system of knowl- 
®p l^es place and what role the “confirmations” play in it. 
tn fi ®^bon is originally a means in the service of life. In order 
event? environment and to adjust his actions to 

tent Fn foresee these events to a certain ex- 

and h^ ^ this he makes use of universal statements, cognitions, 

TPmp- occurs. Now in science this character of cognition 

wholly ^ 

the hfc> Is not sought because of its utility. With 

inu • of prediction the scientific goal is achieved: the 

J y m cognition is the joy of verification, the triumphant feeling of 


The Foundation of Knowledge [ 223] 

having guessed correctly. And it is this that the observation state- 
ments bring about. In them science as it were achieves its goal: it 
is for their sake that it exists. The question hidden behind the prob- 
lem of the absolutely certain basis of knowledge is, as it were, that 
of the legitimacy of this satisfaction with which verification fills us. 
Have our predictions actually come true? In every single case of 
verification or falsification a “confirmation” answers imambiguously 
with a yes or a no, with joy of fulfilment or disappointment The 
confirmations are final. 

Finality is a very fitting word to characterize the function of 
observation statements. They are an absolute end. In them the task 
of cognition at this point is fulfilled. That a new^ task begins with 
the pleasure in which they culminate, and with the h}TX)theses that 
they leave behind does not concern them. Science does not rest upon 
them but leads to them, and they indicate that it has led correctly. 
They are really the absolute fixed points; it gives us joy to reach 
them, even if we cannot stand upon them. 

VII 

In what does this fixity consist? This brings us to the question 
we postponed earlier: in what sense can one speak of observation 
statements as being “absolutely certain”? 

I should like to thrown light on this by first saying something about 
a quite different kind of statement, namely about analytic statements. 

I will then compare these to the “confirmations.” In the case of 
analytic statements it is well known that the question of their 
validity constitutes no problem. They hold c priori; one cannot 
and should not tiy to look to experience for proof of their correctness 
for they say nothing whatever about objects of experience. For this 
reason only “formal truth” pertains to them, i.e., they are not “true” 
because they correctly express some fact. What makes them true is 
just their being correctly constructed, i.e. their standing in agreement 
with our arbitrarily established definitions. 

However, certain philosophical writers have thought themselves 
obliged to ask: Yes, but how do I know^ in an individual case whether 
a statement really stands in agreement with the definition, whether 
it is really analytic and therefore holds without question? Must I 
not carry in my head these definitions, the meaning of all the words 
that are used when I speak or hear or read the statement even if it en- 
dures only for a second? But can I be sure that my psychological ca- 
pacities sufifice for this? Is it not possible, for example, that at the end 


[ 224 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

of the statement I should have forgotten or incorrectly remembered 
the beginning? Must I not thus agree that for psychological reasons I 
can never be sure of the validity of an analytic judgment also? 

To this there is the following answer: the possibility of a failure 
of the psychic mechanism must of course always be granted, but the 
consequences that follow from it are not correctly described in the 
sceptical questions just raised. 

It can be that owing to a weakness of memory, and a thousand 
other causes, we do not understand a statement, or imderstand it 
erroneously (i.e. differently from the way it was intended) — ^but what 
does this signify? Well, so long as I have not understood a sentence 
it is not a statement at all for me, but a mere series of words, of 
sounds or written signs. In this case there is no problem, for only 
of a statement, not of an uncomprehended series of words, can 
one ask whether it is analytic or synthetic. But if I have misinter- 
preted a series of words, but nevertheless interpreted it as a state- 
ment, then I know of just this statement whether it is analytic or 
synthetic and therefore valid a priori or not. One may not sup- 
pose that I could comprehend a statement as such and still be in 
doubt concerning its analytic character. For if it is anaMic 1 have 
understood it only when I have understood it as analytic. To under- 
stand means nothing else, that is, than to be clear about the rules 
governing the use of the words in question; but it is precisely these 
rules of usage that malce statements analytic. If I do not know 
whether a complex of words constitutes an anai}1;ic statement or not, 
this simply means that at that moment I lack the rules of usage: that 
therefore I have simply not understood the statement. Thus the 
case is that either I have understood nothing at all, and then noth- 
ing more is to be said, or I know whether the statement which I under- 
stand is synthetic or analytic (w^hich of course does not presuppose 
that these words hover before me, that I am even acquainted with 
them). In the case of an analytic statement I know at one and the 
same time that it is valid, that formal truth belongs to it. 

The above doubt concerning the validity of analytic statements 
was therefore out of order. I may indeed doubt whether I have 
correctly grasped the meaning of some complex of signs, in fact 
whether I shall ever understand the meaning of any sequence of 
words. But I cannot raise the question whether I can ascertain the 
correctness of an analytic statement. For to understand its meaning 
and to note its a priori validity are in an analytic statement one 
and the same process. In contrast, a synthetic assertion is charac- 
terized by the fact that I do not in the least know whether it is 


The Foundation of Knowledge [ 225 ] 

true or false if I have only ascertained its meaning. Its truth is 
determined only by comparison with experience. The process of 
grasping the meaning is here quite distinct from the process of 
verification. 

There is but one exception to this. And we thus return to our 
"‘confirmations.’" These, that is, are always of the form “Here now 
so and so,” for example “Here two black points coincide,” or “Here 
yellow borders on blue,” or also “Here now pain,” etc. What is 
common to all these assertions is that demonstrative terms occur in 
them which have the sense of a present gesture, i.e. their rules of usage 
provide that in making the statements in which they occur some 
experience is had, the attention is directed upon something ob- 
served. What is referred to by such words as “here,” “now,” “this 
here,” cannot be communicated by means of general definitions in 
words, but only by means of them together with pointings or ges- 
tures. “This here” has meaning only in connection with a gesture. 
In order therefore to understand the meaning of such an observa- 
tion statement one must simultaneously execute the gesture, one 
must somehow point to reality. 

In other words: I can understand the meaning of a “confirma- 
tion” only by, and when, comparing it with the facts, thus carr^mg 
out that process which is necessary for the verification of all syn- 
thetic statements. While in the case of all other synthetic statements 
determining the meaning is separate from, distinguishable from, 
determining the truth, in the case of obsen'ation statements they 
coincide, just as in the case of analytic statements. However difier- 
ent therefore “confirmations” are from analytic statements, they have 
in common that the occasion of understanding them is at the same 
time that of verifying them: I grasp their meaning at the same time 
as I grasp their truth. In the case of a confirmation it makes as 
little sense to ask whether I might be deceived regarding its truth 
as in the case of a tautology. Both are absolutely valid. However, 
while the analytic, tautological, statement is empty of content, the 
observation statement supplies us with the satisfaction of genuine 
knowledge of reality. 

It has become clear, we may hope, that here everything depends 
on the characteristic of immediacy which is peculiar to observ’'ation 
statements and to which they owe their value and disvaiue; the value 
of absolute validity, and the disvaiue of uselessness as an abiding 
foundation. 

A misunderstanding of this nature is responsible for most of 
the unhappy problems of protocol statements with which our en- 


[ 226 ] MORITZ SCHLICK 

quity began. If I make the confirmation “Here now bine,” this 
is not the same as the protocol statement “M. S. perceived blue 
on the nth of April 1934 at such and such a time and such 
and such a place.” The latter statement is a hypothesis and as such 
always characterized by uncertainty The latter statement is equiva- 
lent to “M. S. made . . . (here time and place are to be given) 
Ae confirmation ‘here now blue.’ ” And that this assertion is not 
identical with the confirmation occurring in it is clear. In protocol 
statements there is always mention of perceptions (or they are to 
be added in thought — the identity of the {>erceiving observer is im- 
portant for a scientific protocol), while they are never mentioned in 
confirmations. A genuine confirmation cannot be written down, for 
as soon as I inscribe the demonstratives “here,” “now,” they lose 
their meaning. Neither can they be replaced by an indication of 
time and place, for as soon as one attempts to do this, the result, 
as we saw, is that one unavoidably substitutes for the observation 
statement a protocol statement which as such has a wholly different 
nature. 

VIII 

I believe that the problem of the basis of knowledge is now 
clarified. 

If science is taken to be a system of statements' in which one’s 
interest as a logician is confined to their logical connections, the ques- 
tion of its basis, which would then be a ‘logical” question, can be 
answered quite arbitrarily. For one is free to'define the basis as one 
wishes. In an abstract system of statements there is no priority and 
no posteriority. For instance, the most general statements of science, 
thus those that are normally selected as axioms, could be regarded 
as its ultimate foundation; but this name could just as well be re- 
served for the most particular statements, which would then more 
or less actually correspond to the protocols written down. Or any 
other choice would be possible. But all the statements of science are 
collectively and individually hypotheses the moment one considers 
them from the point of view of their truth value, their validity. 

If attention is directed upon the relation of science to reality 
the system of its statements is seen to be that which it really is, 
namely, a means of finding one’s way among the facts; of arriv- 
ing at the joy of confirmation, the feeling of finality. The problem 
of the “basis” changes then automatically into that of the unshakeable 
point of contact between knowledge and reality. We have come to 
know these absolutely fixed points of contact, the confirmations, in 


The Foundation of Knowledge [ 227 ] 

their individuality: they are the only synthetic statements that are not 
hypotheses. They do not in any way He at the base of science; but 
lie a flame, cognition, as it were, Hcks out to them, reaching each 
but for a moment and then at once consuming it. And newly fed 
and strengthened, it flames onward to the next. 

These moments of fulfilment and combustion are what is essen- 
tial All the light of knowledge comes from them. And it is for the 
source of this Hght the philosopher is really inquiring when he seeks 
the ultimate basis of all knowledge. 



Verification and Experience 


BY A. J. AYER 


What IS it that determines the truth or falsehood of empirical 
propositions? The customary answer is, in effect, that it is their 
agreement or disagreement with reality. I say “in effect” because I 
■ftis to allow for alternative formulations. There are some who 
would speak of correspondence or accordance rather than agree- 
ment, some^who for the word “reality” would substitute “facts” or 
expenrace.” But I do not think that the choice of different words 
h T important difference of meaning. This answer, 

\Tiriv if to be correct, requires some elucidation. To 

quo e Willia m James; “Pragmatists and InteUectualists both accept 
y ; as a matter of course. They begin to quarrel only after the ques- 
lon is raised as to what precisely may be meant by the term ‘agree- 
men and what by the term ‘reality’ when reality is taken as some- 
1- hf to agree with.”^ I hope at least to throw some 

ngnt upon tMs question in the course of this paper. 

t simplify our undertaking if we can draw a distinction be- 
ween mose empirical propositions whose truth or falsehood can be 
etermined only by ascertaining the truth or falsehood of other 
propositions and those whose truth or falsehood can be determined 
directly by observation. To the former class belong all universal 
propositmns. We cannot, for example, directly establish the truth or 
lalsehood of the proposition that gold is dissoluble in aqua regia, 
unless of wurse we regard this as a defining attribute of gold and 
so make the proposition into a tautology. We test it by estabhshing 
me truth or falsehood of singular propositions relating, among other 
mmgs, to p articular pieces of gold. We may indeed deduce one uni- 

published in the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 
the Aristotelian Society * “ reprinted here with the permission of the secretary of 

1. Pragmatism, p. 198. 


Verification and Experience [ 229 ] 

versal proposition from another, or even infer it by analogy, but 
In all such cases we must finally arrive at a proposition for which 
the evidence consists solely in the truth or falsehood of certain 
singular propositions. It is here to be remarked that no matter how 
many such singular propositions we succeed in establishing we are 
never entitled to regard the universal proposition as conclusively 
verified. However often we may have observed the dissolution of 
pieces of gold in aqua regia, we must still allow it to be possible that 
the next piece with which we experiment will not so dissolve. On 
the other hand the falsity of any one of the relevant singular propo- 
sitions does entail the falsity of the universal proposition. It is this 
logical assymetiy in the relationship of universal and singular prop- 
ositions that has led some philosophers^ to adopt the possibility of 
falsification rather than that of verification as their criterion of em- 
pirical significance. 

We said that the way to test the validity of a universal proposi- 
tion about the dissolubility of gold was to ascertain the truth or 
falsehood of singular propositions referring to particular pieces of 
gold. But these propositions in their turn depend for their verification 
upon the verification of other propositions. For a piece of gold is a 
material thing; and to test the validity of propositions referring to 
material things we must ascertain the truth or falsehood of propo- 
sitions referring to sense-data. Here we have another instance of 
logical assymetr>\ A proposition referring to a material thing may 
entail propositions referring to sense-data but cannot itself be en- 
tailed by any finite number of them. 

Now at last we seem to have reached propositions which need 
not wait upon other propositions for the determination of their truth 
or falsehood, but are such that they can be directly confronted with 
the given facts. These propositions I propose to call basic proposi- 
tions. If the distinction which we have drawn between them and 
other propositions is legitimate, we may confine ourselves, for our 
present purpose, to questions concerning the nature of basic prop- 
ositions and the manner in which our determination of their validity 
depends upon our experience. 

It is noteworthy that the legitimacy of the distinction which we 
have drawn is implicitly acknowledged even by philosophers who re- 
ject the notion of agreement with reality as a criterion of truth. 
Neurath and Hempel, for example, have recently been maintaining 
that it is nonsensical to speak of comparing propositions with facts 


2. Notably Karl Popper. See his Logik der F orschung^ 


f 'j'2a " 


A. J. AYER 


r 230 1 ^tjosition, they say, can be compared 

1 -,, o-merience.® A * t the same time they assign a status 
‘A ^^nther proposition' -jc propositions to a class of propo- 
only with another|^^l^^ t^f^roposLns. According to NeuraA, 

corresponding to otoc^l ? 1 jtion it is necessary that 

sitions whch they ^ pf^^^scription of an observer and some 

for a sentence W or Nervation. He gives the following as 

It should cont^ 3.17/Otto’s speech-thought at 

words refe^g W protocol 3 ^5 ^ observed by 

^ examp ®- in tb® . y Neurath as the only legitimate w'ay 

Otto 17^11^3 is cot regarded position. If others care to adopt a 
f ? ' , „ a protocol P^^ as far as he is concerned, at hberty 

of fonnulatmg a F P chosen 

“ .'S' brclaims'for protocol propositions greater 

hHays this. He is thinking of 
stab^ty than „gh to so® .J^^Otto hi been having a hallucma- 
is . jt turns out a to be lying. In the former case the 

Je case m w^^ to be false; in the 

tion or that m wtt bracket. But the whole proposi- 

proposidon “ tbc ^ propositions within the brackets, 

after, the pro^ ^Jfunctioi of one another. We may 

tion IS not a t^^^^ trtrt^_ven when we have rdjected them. In 
my more . ^ to accept is surely inconsistent with Neurath s 

therefore contm^ Bbt/^re debired from appealing to the 

Itself, this is a vau^ ^ hallucination? 

mam position. ^ discover tb^ falsehood of any proposition whatso- 
facts, we e or incompatibility with other 

Neurath m^es compel other criterion. In this respect, his 

ever de^nd up b any advantage. If we are 

proposihons. ^ .^^tis are i^^^tjosition and also with a non-protocol 
protocol propositi not obliged to 

presented with a P the other. We have an 

proposition wlu^ proposit»^t if this is so we need not bother to 
accept the Ptot^ ^ propositions in order to ensure 

equal nght to for pff^ do if we wish a proposition to be 

detnse ^ we have \ and to reject any proposition that is 

then stabihty. accept -gtion whether such a decision is em- 

stable IS to decio® 

incomDatible ^ ‘ ** Erkenntnis, Volume III, p. 223, [see 

mcompatlD ie WX ‘Wirkliche writ.-” Erkennmis. Vol IV; 

3. Otto Neuratb, ‘ ^ Theory of Truth,;’ .4mily«r, Vol II 

p. 199], and “RadiK^®^ Lo^c^ F'^’^no/yrir, Voi. Ill, and Some Remarks 
Carl Hempel, “On. ]g; 333 piricism** 

“Some Remarks o^. ^ « Analysi^^ 

Tacts’ and Proposit^^ 




Verification ana i^^xperienut: 



piiically justified or not is one to which, according to the implications 
of Nenrath’s doctrine, no meaning can be attached. 

One wonders indeed why he and Hempel pay so much attention 
to protocol propositions, inasmuch as the only distinction which they 
are able to draw between them and other propositions is a distinction 
of form. They do not mean by a protocol proposition one which can 
be directly verified by observation, for they deny that this is possible. 
They use the term “protocoF’ purely as a S5mtactical designation for 
a certain assemblage of words. But why should one attach special 
significance to the word “observation”? It may be that there is no 
error involved in constructing sentences of a peculiar type and dig- 
nifying them with the title of Protokollsdtze, but it is arbitrary and 
misleading. There is no more justification for it than there would be 
for making a collection of all the propositions that could be cor- 
rectly expressed in English by sentences beginning with the letter 
B, and choosing to call them Basic propositions. If Neurath and 
Hempel do not recognize this it is probably because, in writing 
about Frotokollsdtze, they unconsciously employ the forbidden cri- 
terion of agreement with experience. Though they say that the term 
‘"protocol” is nothing more than a syntactical designation, they do 
not use it merely as such. We shall see later on that Carnap equivo- 
cates with this term in a similar w^ay. 

It is not, however, a sufficient reason for rejecting a theory that 
some of its advocates have failed consistently to adhere to it. And 
it is necessary for us to investigate more closely the view that in 
order to determine the validity of a system of empirical propositions 
one cannot and need not go beyond the system itself. For if this 
view were satisfactory we should be absolved from troubling any 
further about the use of the phrase “agreement v/ith experience.” 

The theory which we now have to examine is that wfiich is com- 
monly known as the coherence theory of truth. It should be noted 
that the theoiy^ is not, as we interpret it, concerned w'ith the definition 
of truth and falsehood but only with the means by which they are 
determined. According to it a proposition is to be accepted if it is 
found to be compatible with other accepted propositions, rejected 
if it is not. If, however, we are anxious to accept a proposition which 
conflicts with our current system we may abandon one or more of 
the propositions which we had previously accepted. In such a case 
we should, it is sometimes said, be guided by a principle of economy. 
We should make the smallest transformation of the system which 
ensured self-consistency. I think it is usually assumed also that we 
have, or ought to have, a preference for large and highly integrated 


A. J. AYER 


[ 232 ] 

systems; systems containing a great number of propositions which 

suDDort one another to a high degree. 

One strong objection to this theory is well put by Professor 
Price in his lecture on Truth and Corrigibility. “Suppose,” he says, 
“we have a groi^P of mutually supporting judgments. The extraor- 
dinary thin«’ is that however large the group may be, and however 
vreat the support which the members give to each other, the entire 
arniin hanes, SO to speak, in the air. If we accept one member, no 
dnnht it will he reasonable to accept the rest. But why must we 
anv of them? Why should we not reject the whole lot? Might 
thev^not all be false, although they all support each other?”^ He 
c^oes on to argue that we cannot consider such a system of judgments 
to have even'anv probability unless we can attribute to at least one 
of if<; constituents a probability which is derived from some other 
j than its membership of the system. He suggests therefore 
f-L.^ „n}y way to save the theory would be to maintain that some 
oronositions were intrinsically probable. But tins, though he does 
^ i so. is reduce it to absurdity. There is no case at ^ to 
. jp Qut for the view that a proposition can be probable inde- 
^nXntlv of all evidence. The most that could be said in favor of 
^vone w’ho accepted Price's suggestion would be that he had chosen 
the word “probabUity'” an unfamiliar sense. _ __ 

^ -jjt w'hich Price appears to have overlooked is that accord- 
• a t one well-known version of the coherence theory there can 
one completely coherent system of propositions. If this were 
theory would give us at least an unequivocal criterion for 
the truth of any proposition; namely, the possibility 
of 'n-oi-Dorating it in this single system. It would not, however, 
fr ^ rT IS anv around for supposing that the enlargement of an ap- 
.onerent system of propositions increased its probability, 
o ""th ^ contrary’, we ought rather to hold that it decreased it. For 
° ^ thesi uny set of propositions which is intemally coherent 
ex nypoi therefore, we have a set of propositions 

h °aDDsars to be self-consistent, either it is the unique coherent 
^ it contains a contradiction which we have failed to dis- 

system or greater the probability that it con- 

cover, an discover. But in saying 

tarns a c g^ssuniing the truth of a proposition about the limited 
^ ^ human understanding, which may or may not find a 

pla^rL coherent system. Perhaps, therefore, it would be 

— 4 Tru th^^^^ Corrigibility (Inaugural lecture, Oxford University Press, 1936), 
D 19. 


r 233 ] 

Verification and Experience 

better to say that the advocates of this form of the coherence theory 
HJCTwnse with the notion of probability altogether. 

Vt now we must ask. Why should it be assumed Aat gdy one 
completely coherent system of propositions is conceivable. H 
many empirical propositions we succeed m combimng mto an 
pareLy self-consistent system we seem always able to 
rival system which is equally extensive, appears equ^ free from 
contraction, and yet is incompatible with the first 
be held that at least one of these systems must contam a contra i 
tion even though we are unable to detect it? I can see no reason 
at ^ for this assumption. We may not be able to 
a given system is free from contradiction; but tms does not me 
thS it is probable that it contains one. This indeed is recoded by 
the more recent advocates of what we are calhng a coherence JT- 
They admit the possibility of inventing fictitious sciences and histones 
which would be just as comprehensive, elegant and free -ro“ c - 
tradiction as those in which we actually oeiieve. But how then do 
they propose to distinguish the true systems from the false/ 

The answer given® is that the selection of the true system does 
not depend upon any internal features of the system itseli. 1 
not be effected by purely logical means. But it can be carried out 
inside the realm of descriptive syntax. We are to say that the true 
system is that which is based upon true protocol propositions; and 
that true nrotocol propositions are those which are produceo by 
accredited ‘obser^'ers, including notably the scientists of our era 
Logically, it might be the case that the protocol propositions which 
each of us expressed were so divergent that no common system o^ 
science or only a very^ meagre system could De oaseo upon them. Bdi 
fortunately this is not so. People do occasionally proauce incon- 
venient protocol propositions. But being in a small minonty they 
are over-ridden. They are said to be bad observers or liars or, m 
extreme cases, mad. It is a contingent, historical fact that the rest 
of us agree in accepting an “increasingly comprehensive, co^on, 
scientific system.” And it is to this, so the theory runs, that we 
refer when out of the many coherent systems of science that are 
conceivable we speak of only one as being true. 

This is an ingenious answer; but it will not do. One reason why 
we trust “the scientists of our era” is that we believe that they give 
an accurate account of their observations. But this means that we 
shall be involved in a circle if we say that the reason why we accept 

5. E.g., by Rudolf Camap, “Erwidenmg auf die Aufsatze von E. Zilsel und 
EL Dimcker,” Erkenntnis, Vol. Ill, PP- 179-180. 






A. J. AYER 


[ 234 ] 

certain evidence is merely that it conies from the scientists of our 
era. And furthermore. How are we to determine that a particular 
system is accepted by contemporary scientists except by appealing 
to the facts of experience? But once it is conceded that such an 
appeal is possible there is no longer any need to bring in the con- 
temporary scientists. However great our admiration for the achieve- 
ments of the scientists of our era we can hardly maintain that it is 
only with reference to their behavior that the notion of agreement 
with reality has any meaning. HempeF has indeed attempted to meet 
this objection by telling us that instead of saying that “the system 
of protocol-statements which we call true may only be character- 
ized by the historical fact that it is actually adopted by the scientists 
of our culture circle” we ought to express ourselves “formally” and 
say: “The following statement is sufficiently confirmed by the 
protocol-statements adopted in our science; ‘Amongst the numerous 
imaginable consistent sets of protocol-statements, there is in practice 
exactly one which is adopted by the vast majority of instructed 
scientific observers; at the same time, it is just this set which we 
generally call true.’ ” But this does not remove the difficulty. For 
now we must ask, How is it determined that the protocol-statements 
which support the statement quoted really are adopted in our science? 
If Hempei is really speaking formally, as he says he is, then the 
phrase “adopted in our science” must be regarded merely as an 
arbitrary syntactical designation of a certain set of sentences. But it 
is clear that he does not intend it to be nothing more than this. He 
intends it to convey the information that the propositions expressed 
by these sentences actually are adopted. But this is to re-introduce the 
reference to historical fact which he is trying to eliminate. We have 
here a fallacy which is akin to the fallacy oi the ontological argu- 
ment. It is not legitimate to use the phrase “adopted in our science” 
simply as a means of naming certain statements and then proceed 
to infer from this that these statements really are adopted in it. But 
Hempei cannot dispense with this fallacious inference. For each of 
many incompatible systems might contain the statement that it alone 
was accepted by contemporary scientists, together with the protocol 
propositions that were needed to support it. 

We may conclude then that the attempt to lay down a criterion 
for determining the truth of empirical propositions which does not 
contain any reference to “facts” or “reality” or “experience,” has 
not proved successful. It seems plausible only when it involves a 
tacit introduction of that very^ principle of agreement with reality 


6. Analysis, Vol. Ill, pp. 39-40. 


Verification and Experience [ 235 ] 

which it is designed to obviate. Accordingly, we may return to our 
origmal question conceming the nature of basic propositions and 
the manner in which their validity depends upon fact. And first of 
aE I wish to consider how far this question admits of a purely con- 
ventional answer. 

According to Professor Carnap it is wholly a matter of conven- 
tion what propositions we take as basic. “Every concrete proposi- 
tion,” he tells us,^ “belonging to the physicalistic system-language can 
in suitable circumstances serve as a protocol proposition. Let G be 
a law (that is a general proposition belonging to the system lan- 
guage). For the purpose of verification one must in the first instance 
derive from G concrete propositions referring to particular space- 
time points (through substitution of concrete values for the space- 
time co-ordinates x, y, z, t which occur in G as free variables). 
From these concrete propositions one may with the help of addi- 
tional laws and logico-mathematical rules of inference derive further 
concrete propositions, until one comes to propositions which in the 
particular case in question one is willing to accept. It is here a 
matter of choice which propositions are employed at any given time 
as the terminating points of this reduction, that is as protocol propo- 
sitions. In every case the process of reduction, which serves the 
purpose of verification, must be brought to an end somewhere. But 
one is never obliged to call a halt at any one point rather than 
another.” 

In reasoning thus, Carnap says that he is following the example 
of Karl Popper. Actually Popper adopts a rather narrower conven- 
tion. He proposes, and takes the view that there can in this matter 
be no warrant for anything more than a proposal, that basic propo- 
sitions should have the form of singular existentials. They must, 
according to his convention, refer to particular spatio-temporal points 
and the events which are said to be occurring at these points must 
be observable events. But in case anyone should think that the use 
of the word “observable” brings in an element of psychology he 
hastens to add that instead of an “observable” event he might 
equally well have spoken of an event of motion located in (macro- 
scopic) physical bodies.® His views conceming the verification of 
these propositions are summed up as follows: “The basic proposi- 
tions are accepted by an act of wiE, by convention. Sie sitid Festset- 
zungenf’^ 

7. “trber Protokollsatze.” Erkenntnis, Vol. Ill, p. 224. 

8. Logik der Forschung, p. 59. 

9. Op. ciL, p. 62. 


C ] A. J. AYER 

The verification of all other empirical propositions is held to 
depend upon that of the basic propositions. So that if we take the 
remark I have quoted literally, we are presented with the view that 
our acceptance or rejection of any empirical proposition must be 
wholly arbitrary. And this is surely wrong. Actually, I do not think 
that Popper himself wishes to maintain this. His stipulation that 
basic propositions should refer to observable events suggests that he 
recognizes that our acceptance of them somehow depends upon our 
observations. But he does not tell us how. 

There is indeed this much truth in what Popper says. The prop- 
ositions which he calls basic refer to material things. As such, they 
can be tested by observation, but never conclusively established. 
For, as we have already remarked, although they may entah propo- 
sitions referring to sense-data they cannot be entailed by them. It 
follows that there is in our acceptance of them an element of con- 
vention. I cannot carry out all the tests which would bear upon 
the truth of even so simple a proposition as that my pen is lying 
on my table. In practice, therefore, I accept such a proposition after 
making only a limited number of tests, perhaps only a single test, 
which leaves it still possible that it is fsdse. But this is not to say 
that my acceptance of it is the result of an arbitrary decision. I have 
collected some evidence in favor of the proposition, even though 
it may not be conclusive evidence. I might have accepted it with- 
out having any evidence at aU; and then my decision would, in fact, 
have been arbitrary. There is no harm in Popper's insisting that our 
acceptance of such propositions as he calls basic is not wholly dic- 
tated by logic; but he ought still to distinguish the cases in which 
our acceptance of a “basic” proposition is reasonable from those in 
which it is not. We may say that it is reasonable when the proposi- 
tion is supported by our obsenmtions. But what is meant by saying 
that a proposition is supported by our obsewations? This is a ques- 
tion which in his discussion of the “Basis-problem” Popper does not 
answer. 

We find, therefore, that this “discover}'” of Popper's which has 
been fastened on to by Carnap amounts to no more than this; that 
the process of testing propositions referring to physical objects can 
be extended as far as we choose. What is conventional is our decision 
to carry it in any given case just so far and no farther. To express 
this, as Carnap does, by saying that it is a matter of convention 
what propositions we take as protocols is simply to give the term 
“protocol proposition” an unfamiliar meaning. We understand that 
he now proposes to use it to designate any singular proposition, be- 


Verification and Experience [ 237 ] 

longmg to '‘the physicalistic system-language,” which we are pre- 
pared to accept without further tests. This is a perfectly legitimate 
usage. What is not legitimate is to ignore the discrepancy between it 
and his former usage according to which protocol propositions were 
said to “describe directly given experience.” And in abandoning the 
original usage he has incidentaliy shelved the problem which it was 
designed to meet. 

Elsewhere/^ Carnap has suggested that problems concerning the 
nature of basic propositions, in our sense of the term, depend for 
their solution only on conventions about forms of words. I think 
that this, too, can be shown to be a mistake. Most people are by 
now familiar with his division of propositions into factual proposi- 
tions such as “the roses in my garden are red,” pseudo-factual prop- 
ositions such as “a rose is a thing,” which are also said to be syntacti- 
cal propositions, expressed in the material mode of speech, and 
propositions such as “ ‘rose’ is a thing-word,” which are syntactical 
and expressed in the formal mode of speech. Now when he raises 
the question “W^hat objects are the elements of given, direct experi- 
ence?” he treats it as if it were a syntactical question, expressed in 
the material mode of speech. That is, he considers it to be a loose 
way of raising the question “What kinds of word occur in protocol- 
statements?”^^ And he sets out various possible answers both in 
what he calls the material and in what he calls the formal mode. 
Thus, he says that it may be the case that “the elements that are 
directly given are the simplest sensations and feelings” or “more 
complex objects such as partial gestalts of single sensory fields” or 
that “material things are elements of the given”; and he takes these 
to be misleading w^ays of saying that “protocol-statements are of 
the same kind as: ‘joy now/ ‘here, now, blue’ ” or that “protocol- 
statements are of forms similar to ‘red circle, now' ” or that they 
have “approximately the same kind of form as ‘a red cube is on the 
table.’ assumes that questions about the nature of 

immediate experience are linguistic in character. And this leads him 
to dismiss all the “problems of the so-called given or primitive data” 
as depending only upon our choice of a form of ianguage.^^ But 
this is to repeat the error of Neurath and Hempel, which we have 
already exposed. If the term “protocol-statement” was being used 
merely as a syntactical designation for certain combinations of 

10. Logical Syntax of Language, pp. 305-6. 

11. The Unity of Science, p. 45. 

12. The Unity of Science, pp. 46-7. 

13. The Logical Syntax of Language, pp. 305-6. 


Iliil 

■,,'i 














[238 ] 

Sd tea mS °f “> applied it 

to all EngUsh sentences teJSJ Sthf BS'tht'-®”''°\“'’““” 

m whicli CamaD ‘ ^ sense 

iiot to mark out the fomfnf ^ ^smg the tenn. He is using it 

the fact that the^refe^to statements, but rather to express 

our answer to his question “Whaf ^twjrdingly, 

statements?” cm SneL ^ ^ PtotoSl- 

hnguistic forms. It musf denpnrt ^ conventional choice of 

the question “What object^ are ^ r answer 

perience?” And this is not a matt given, direct ex- 
fact. It is a plain question of ffr/ °h ^ 

theory of sensation is correct. atomistic or the 

directly given are &“^simDlest°^°^*^!°° elements that are 

takes tot C^niap 

of speech, is not syntacdcal a? S° “ ^^^“^^^tial mode 

gives as its formal eaiiiv^ilp^nf \ proposition which he 

of toe same S 2 wlr’S;'’*' >«““‘-totom=n,s are 
not syntactical either If wr wnni ^ ted’ ” is 

pseudo-syntactical proLition And h^tw ^ ®ay call it a 

seems to be about words hut it ^ “ean that it 

tant that the existenerS sn.h ™tior- 

for they are q^^tfa? dan^tuT^r^^^^^ T" 

propositions of which Caman ^,,7 i ^ pseudo-iactual 

the source of confustn isThe ?fu" “Stance 

without contradiction be Le^edtoth f 

tion and as involving a ^ ^ ^ ^°tmal desiana- 

is precisely bow CeL J Jn^. f ^ But this 

Jed to make STmisSTnf ^i^us that he is 

of basic propositions can bft-Tded meref^^h"^ 
indeed a matter of convention th ^ <hn f/ ft is 

of the letters “j o y” to denote inv ^ consisting 

is immediately experienced, which Is inToli^ 

d-srtSoi.’ Soix 

n? “Sr^S 22 2rS ? 

n..ne « priori. Wr toa; h„,d todaedZ,'’rpet‘„r2S22'S 




' Verification and Experience j 239 j 

always private to Mmself; but this is only because we happen so to 
use words that it does not make sense to say “I am acquainted with 
your sense-data” or “You and I are experiencing the same sense- 
datum.”^^ This is a point about which we are apt to be confused 
One says mournfully “I cannot experience your toothache” as 
though It revealed a lack of mental power. That is, we are inclined 
to think of the contents of another person’s mind, or the immediate 
objects of his experience, as being concealed from us by some sort 
of natural obstacle, and we say to ourselves: “If only we had a ray 
which would penetrate this obstacle!” (Intuition!) or “Perhaps we 
ran ^r^truct a reflector which will show us what is going on behind.” 
But m fact there is no obstacle but our usage of words. To sav that 
whatever is directly “given” to me is mine and mine only is to ex- 
press a tautology. A mistake which I, for one, have made in the past 
IS to co^se this with the proposition “Whatever is directly ‘given’ 
IS nune. This is not a tautology. It is an empirical proposition, and 

A further point which it is advisable to make clear is that we 
are not settmg any arbitrary boundaries to the field of possible ex- 
penence. As an iUustration of this let us consider the case of the 
who claims to have an immediate, non-sensory experience of 

content of his experience, I have no right to disbelieve him. Not 
aving such experiences inyself I cannot understand him fully. I do 
not m 5 'self know what it is like to be acquainted with God. But I 
S ^ rin understand Aat he is having some experience of a kind 
ftat I do not have. And this I may readily beUeve. I should cer- 
J’® “ assuming that the sort of experiences that I 

myself had were the only sort that could be had at aU. At the same 
time It must be remarked that “God,” in this usage, cannot be the 
name of a transcendent bemg. For to say that one was immediately 

S^thoul'^f a transcendent being would be self-contradictory*, 
^d though It rnight be the name of a person who in fact endur^ 

Hbfl? 1- immediately acquainted with 

Sbf. too, would be self^ontradicto^ 

wouM the fact that people were acquainted with God in 
s sense, afford a valid ground for inferring that the world had a 
mst cause, or that human beings survived death, or in short that 
ything existed which had the attnbutes that are popularly ascribed 


A. J. AYER 



[ 240 ] 

® experience. 

KTfx \p srtainly not be justified in den3diig a priori the Dossi- 

thaf^th experience. But this does not mean that we recognize 

Sv? worTd^n/ ground for inferring the existence of an idealf^ 
of “God” or i *!, to say this because the use 

kind of ^ “ a designation of the content of a certain 

expenence often misleads people into thinking that they are 

adi-? and we must make it clear that in 

mittmg the possibility of such experiences we are not also ud 
mg the conclusions which are iUegitimately drawn from them 
We have tned to show that neither the form nor the vSdiW 
asic propositions is dependent merely on convention Since It is 
their function to describe what can be immediaS exSenid 
Will depend upon the general nature of the “given ” their 
St? ^g^^^^ent with it in the relevanTpaSSr ctsT 

do S relation of agreement? What kind of Correspondence 

It IS sometimes suggested that this relation of agreement of 
Ae saine kmd as that which holds between a pttuS“S o 

iSeeVS " is true. Itl ptsibCe 

* construct picture-languages; no doubt they have their ad 
iSfeSe- Cr thaS"? maintained that they alone are 

lauguage ;ithoug^.? 

&'SlhSsSSC“'‘'°CJ ^re sometimes veri- 

S^doTfhf ■ rSr concerned is one of picturing. Be- 

presumably false prCposTti^Tr^so^^ar^KCS^ SS 

Z tht I ? r “ toat case the introduction 

of the notion of picturing does not serve our purpose It does nCS 
enaWe us to dispense with the notion of agreemCn? 

tion nf objections hold against those who say that this rela- 

tion of agreement is one of identity of stmctnrp Tt,;c v * f . 

rfS’f^°“ “^P®- is to’ be supposed 

a false proposition is ako a map The mer^ f^rrr, ';^“PP°s®“.tnat 

wiii .0. «n . 


Verification and Experience [ 241 ] 

imagmaiy or real. Can we then avoid saying that we test the truth 
of such a map by seeing whether it agrees with reality? But then 
the notion of agreement is still left imciarified. And, in any case, 
why should it be assumed that if a proposition is to describe what 
is directly given it must have the same structure as the given? One 
might, perhaps, allow the possibility of creating a language in which 
all basic propositions were expressed by sentences functioning as 
maps, though I am by no means sure that it would be possible to 
draw a map of our internal sensations; but I can see no ground at all 
for assuming that only a language of this kind is legitimate, or that 
any of the European languages with which I am acquainted is a 
language of this ]^d. Yet propositions, expressed in these languages, 
are frequently verified. There is, perhaps, a historical connection 
between the view that basic propositions must be identical in struc- 
ture with the facts that verify them and the view that only structure 
can be known or expressed.^^ But this too is arbitrary, and indeed 
self-defeating. To maintain that content is inexpressible is to behave 
like Ramsey's child. “ ‘Say breakfast.’ ‘Can't.’ ‘What can’t you say?’ 
‘Can’t say breakfast.’ 

What is being assumed in the theories which we have just been 
discussing is not so much that a proposition cannot be verified as 
that it, or, to speak more accurately, the sentence expressing it, can- 
not have a sense at all unless it is a picture or a map. The difficulty 
with regard to sentences that express false propositions is got round 
by sa}ing that they depict or map possible facts. But surely this 
assumption is quite gratuitous. If I am speaking English I may use 
the words “I am angiy^” to say that I am angry. You may say, if 
you like, that in doing so I am obeying a meaning-rule^'^ of the English 
language. For this to be possible it is not in the least necessary that 
my words should in any w'ay resemble the state of anger which they 
describe. That “this is red” is used to say that this is red does not 
imply that it bears any relation of resemblance, whether of structure 
or content, to an actual or hypothetical red patch. 

But if the words “I am angry” are used to say that I am angry, 
then it does not seem in any way mysterious that my being angry 
should verify the proposition that they express. But how do I know 
that I am angiy? I feel it. How do I know that there is now a loud 
sound? I hear it. How do I know that this is a red patch? I see it. 

15. Cf. E. Ziisel, “Bemerkimgeii zur Wissenschaftslogii:,” Erkenntnis, VoL III, 
p. 143. 

16. Foundations of Mathematics^ p. 268. [Vide pp. 321-6 of this volume.] 

17. Cf. K. Ajdukiewjcz, “Sprache und Sinn,” Erkenntnis, Vol. IV, pp. 114-116. 





[ 248 ] 

[242 1 

A. J. AYER 

If this answer is not regarded as satisfactory, I do not know what 
other can be given. 

It may be suggested that we ou^t in this connection to intro- 
toce the notion of causation. The relation, it may be said, between 
me proposition “I am in pain” and the fact that verifies it is that 
me feet causes me to assert the proposition, or at any rate to believe 
It. that such a relation often exists is not to be denied But we 
cammt andyze verification in terms of it. For if I am a habitual liar 
my bemg m pam may cause me to deny that I am in pain; and if 
1 am a sufficiently hidebound Christian Scientist it may not cause 
me to believe it. But in either case my being in pain wiU verify the 
proposition that I am in pain. Why? Because when I say “I am in 
pam I mean that I am m pain, and if p then p. But how do I estab- 

c2 oLy J it IS'Z 

propositions must be regarded as in- 
comgible. I find this question difficult to answer because I do not 
Know what precise meaning those who have discussed it have been 
givmg to the term “incorrigible.” Probably, difierent philosophers 
ve given it different meanings. Professor Price, for example, when 
ne argues that basic propositions are incorrigible appears to mean 
no more than that our re^ons for acceptmg them are found in our 
75 justified in saying of a %'isua] sense-datum 

*3ecause one sees it so. For the only arguments 
^ ~ ^ favor of the view that some first-order propositions 

are incorrigible are arguments against the coherence theoA' of truth.is 
snould of course agree that basic propositions were incorrigible, 
^ unnatural sense. Dr. von Juhos makes the same state- 

ment. But what he appears to mean by it is that there can never 
be any ground for abandoning a basic proposition: that once it is 
acceptea it cannot subsequently be doubted or denied. In a sense 

q ently doubted or demed is always a different proposition. What 
I accept now is the proposition “this is red”; what I may doubt or 
deny m thirty seconds’ time is the proposition “I was seeing some- 
red thirty seconds ago.” But in this sense every proposition 
which contains a demonstrative is incorrigible, and not only basic 
propositions. And if von Juhos wishes to maintain that some special 
sacrosanctity attaches to propositions which purport to be records 
of our unm ediate expenences, I think that he is wrong. If I find the 

18. Vide Truth and Corrigibility. 

19. See his articles in Analysis, Vol. H, and Erkenntnis, Vol TV. 


Verification and Experience [ 243 ] 

sentence "‘I feel happy” written in my diary under the heading 
February 3rd I am not obliged to believe that I really did feel happy 
on February Srd, merely because the sentence has the same form 
as that which I should utter if I felt happy now. I may indeed be- 
lieve it on the ground that I am not in the habit of writing down 
false statements in my diary. But that is a different matter. 

Professor Moore has suggested to me that what some of those 
who say that basic propositions are incorrigible may have in mind 
is that we cannot be mistaken about them in the way that we can 
be mistaken about other empirical propositions. If I say "'I am in 
pain” or “this is red” I may be lying, or I may be using words 
wrongly; that is, I may be classifying as “pain” or as “red” some- 
thing that would not normally be so classified. But I cannot be mis- 
taken in any other way. I cannot be mistaken in the way that I can 
be mistaken ff I take this red patch to be the cover of a book. If 
this is a fact, it is not a fact about human psychology. It is not just 
a merciful dispensation of Providence that we are secured from 
errors of a certain kind. It is, if anything, a fact about language.-^^ 
If Moore is right, it does not make sense to say “I doubt whether 
this is red” or “I think that I am in pain but I may be mistaken,” 
unless it is merely meant that I am doubting whether “pain” or 
“red” is the correct w^ord to use. I believe now that Moore is right 
on this point. But whether it is a fact from which any important 
conclusions follow I do not profess to know. 


20. Cf. John Wisdom, “Philosophical Perplexity,” Proc. Arist, Soc., 1936-7, p. 81. 





12 


What Is the Aim of Ethics? 
BY MORITZ SCHLICK 
(translated by DAVID RYNIN) 


I. Ethics Seeks Nothing but Knowledge 


If there ARE ethical questions which have meaning, and are there- 
fore capable of being answered, then ethics is a science. For the cor- 
rect answers to its questions will constitute a system of true propo- 
sitions, and a system of true propositions concerning an obiect is 

and nothing else; its only goal is the truth. Ever^• science is, as such 
purely theoretical; it seeks to understand: hence the questfons S 

to^nd T- *eo^eticaI problems. As philosophers w-e trv 

to find their correct solutions, but their practical 'apDlicatioa. if such 
IS possible, does not fall within the sphere of ethics, if anvone studies 
aese questions m order to apply the results to life and action his 
dealing with ethics has, it is true, a practical end; but ethics itself 
never has any other goal than the truth. 

So long as the philosopher is concerned viih his pur-="lv th'=‘o 
S iie has a human interest 'as 4ll 

there t object of his invesiiaation. For him 

there is no greater danger than to change from a philosonher into 
a morahst, from an investigator into a preacher. Deske for the' truth 
Siii. I aPProprmte inspiration for the thinker when he phhoso- 
S hk thoughts run the danger of being led^ astray 

by his feelings. His wishes, hopes, and fears threaten to encroach 
upon tliat objectivity which is the necessars^ presupposition of aU 

^ person; but one cannot at the same moment serve 


Slf.New'^YoS/lttfS^d Prentice-HaU 

Uie publishers. Schlick’s book was first publishe^^ °93o'!“' 


[ 247 ] 



2. The Subject-matter of Ethics 

relaS SS oS’ 

in daily iS “ ™ ns^ them so often 

mean by them The e*h?«! exactly what we 

is morSy ‘‘v“iuS >’ tS “ “morality,” or what 

human cLSt what or “norm” of 

by the oldest simplest word" ^ tv to name it 

And wdS 

s’;“oft\s ™idS“c“*d“ to'/rSo* 

else with it. Since ethics is ireSenS 'th-S 2 *™*r°“f “>’l>inS 

" i£ 

STrs,' nor“i afsSj ta uTa f H I-"-" 

ro^sf ~s.eT 22 

:r~slfHSr" ““-nfLS: 

is obviins that no sci-nce caifhf* *' ™ ‘i'iP=™n“' It 

"“-SSian?raloS:.a“^^^ 
P aiX tv»T;re“ 'STead'\“t“- 
itShl^^resTmlS’^S*”'”'* ^ 

i-s dte diins or event as o„eVr4L"2?Jt.*S,tn“: 


[ 248 ] 

. . MOMTZ SCHLICK 

i^es the two problems wiU solve neither. 

sl^n^y to?" ^ ^"0^2 

is concenied and wLrw2sh^X 



What Is the Aim of Ethics? [ 249 ] 

tiBguisMiig it from all others in a special way. If this were not so 
we would have no opportunity and no motive to call it by a special 
, name. Every name which is used in discourse for communication 
I must have a meaning capable of being indicated. This is indeed self- 
i eiddent, and it would not be doubted of the object of any other 
I science — only in ethics has it sometimes been forgotten. 

I Let us consider some examples outside the field of ethics. Bi- 
I ology, the science of life, finds its sphere limited by a group of 
I characteristics (a special kind of motion, regeneration, growth, and 
I so forth) which belong to all living things, and stand out so clearly 
I for everyday observation that — apart from certain critical in- 
I stances — the difference between the animate and inanimate is very 
; sharply distinguished, without the use of any scientific analysis. It 
is only because of this that the concept of life could have first been 
formed, and obtained its special name. If the biologist succeeds, 
with progressive knowledge, in establishing new and sharper defini- 
tions of life, in order better to bring the events of life under general 
laws, this means only more precision in, and perhaps extension of, 
the concept, without however altering its original meaning. 

Similarly the word “light” had a definite meaning before there 
:was a science of light, that is, optics, and this meaning determined 
the subject-matter of optics. The distinguishing mark tvas in this 
case that immediate experience which we call “iighi-sensation,” that 
is, a not-fuither-definable datum of consciousness, known only to 
the perceiver, the occurrence of which — again apart from critical 
instances — indicates the presence of those e\’ents w'hich constitute 
the subject-matter of optics. The fact that optics in its modem devel- 
oped form is the science of Roentgen rays and radio-* telegraphic 
waves as well (because their laws are identical with the laws of 
light) enlarges the meaning of the word “optics** without changing 
its basis. 

As certainly, then, as the expression “moral good*’ makes good 
sense, just as certainly must we be able to discover it in a w'ay 
analogous to that by which one discovers the meaning of the word 
“life” or “light.” But many philosophers see in this a serious difficulty 
of ethics, indeed the difficulty, and they are of the opinion that the 
sole task of ethics is the discovery of the definition of “good.” 

3. On the Definition of Good 

! This view can be interpreted in two ways. In the first place, it 
could mean that the task of the philosopher is exhausted in describ- 
ing exactly the sense in which the word “good” — or bon or gut 



[ 250 ] 


MORITZ SCHUCK 

ayafeWin its moral signification is actuaUy used, 
known merely with making clear the already well- 

knoTO mea^g, by a stnct formulation of it in other words^fwere 

for example 

MoorlShS^^f - definitions is (as G. E. 

the hiicinp ^ Ethica has pointed out in a similar connection) 

f h'S,' r^'? >“S”>Se. Ought wu reaUy to bS= 

science shoulcTbp” word? A veiy peculiar case, that a whole 
SrindTn anv merely the definition of a con- 

are 'after ah Tnlv ’ mterested in mere definitions? They 

S\f stand at the besinninl 

be a^t mSl ^ ^ definition it would 

inter f philosopher woSd 

interest himself only m what comes after it. No, the real problems 

of ^ different sort. Even though th» task 

of etkcs couM be formulated as that of stating what the c-Sod “reaUv 

£u“?rt°al^ “?*■"““" “ - the n,e/dloSl 

does uo. s.sive tor\°LLTS« ^of^ii^rR^TfS Si 

t^ssi rf r s" 

d.y wi.h““h1S1fStSS,S1Jr“"”‘="^ 

of a cSS teSSSA'h ''" “”“® 

terpreted ns not . the concept “good” could be in- 

Slhfronnp t K ! ^^te formulation of the content 

evef be exaS’v^h J^*^"^ f ^ '^^ts would, how- 

sSfSii"?S?i;HS 

be dieSed“bSesTS;s'‘'kToM' °' f ' 

y inese norms. The philosopher would have merely 



WMt Is the Aim of Ethics? 251 j 

to find a fornnilation of it, and we should have before ns the previ- 

ousiy considered case.) However, it would be quite absurd to de- 
mand of ethics nothing but the arbitrary establishment of the mean- 
ing of a word. That would be no achievement at all. Even the prophet 
me creator of a new morality, never forms a new concept of morality^ 
but presupposes one, and asserts only that other modes of behavior 
are subsumed under it than those which people have believed up 
to that tune. In logical terms, the prophet holds that the acknowl- 
^ged content of the concept has a different range from that supposed. 

alone can be the meaning when he declares: “Not that is ‘good’ 
which yon have held as such, but something else!” 

pus we see &e view confirmed that in no way is the formulation 
of the con^pt of the moral good to be considered as the final task 
of e^cs; It cannot be regarded as anything but a mere preparation. 

To be sure, tms preparation is not to be neglected; ethics ought 
not to spare itself the task of determining the meaning of its Sn- 
cept, even though, as we have said, the meaning of the word “f^ood” 
may m one sense be assumed as known. 


4* Is THE Good Indefinable? 

. dangerous to withdraw from this task under the pre- 

te:rt that the word “good” is one of those whose meanincr is simple 
and unanalyzable, of which therefore a definition, a statement of £ 
J^otation. IS impossible. What is demanded here need not be a 

S?hnw '' sufficient to indi- 
te u state what must 

sPictlv Lfi acquainted with its content. It is, 

stnctiy speaking, also impossible to define what the word “ore-n” 

't.e'^® 5 tdeless fix its meaning unambiguousTy, for 
'V® a summer meadow, or by point- 

u tree. We mentioned above that a" “iic-ht- 

1 noTdefiniS fundamental concept of opfics 

^ not definable; however, we know exactly what is meant by it be- 

seSinn T conditions under which we have'a light- 

sensation. In the same way, in ethics we must be able to give ''the 

ffiough Its fundamental concept be indefinable. In thirmanner it 

wo5d^hi’°"''^^^ meaning of any word, for othenvise it 

would have no meamng at aU. It must even be capable of teincr 

pMlosophical analysis cannot be necessary for 
IS, for the matter concerns merely a question of fact, namely a 





[ 251 ] 

^ , MC3K1T2. SCHLICK 

<^cnption of those conditions under which the ward / 

even^tpm^^'^^ for many philosophers to stick to the realm of facts 
the facK^ a™ “ ‘^oty to tiasaribe 

"IS'J” ?i.sss“rf ”7^ -<S3 

xnis theory is of course wholly hvoothetiral tJw> tv.,, j 

theXiaS.^ L^JSrwSe«‘‘f ^ 

assumption that the moral seif is poorirdevSSed kmSf 

” sriff utrs; £l“ SeTsr 

Its characmrisfe must L can^ f percepdon. 

to certain known facts, withoS My°i£ ^ Sn'Soin^“?f 

=SHSHSH#H- 


. The Formal Characteristic of the Good 

iS^S?'fF-=““at 

erally been expressed since tTant- tu ^ S^n- 

ouph, m do. ifow, to TtLSS a*iSu”ff dSialrff 

someone who dem?3Tidc nic^rr^a ^ ’ ii ^ Qesire there belongs 

r£-?H7S~? - 

S It, m this case the formal characteristic (to be a command 


What Is the Aim of Ethics? [ 253 ] 

of God) woEld express the very essence of the good. According to 
another, perhaps profounder, interpretation, God desires the good 
because it is good. In this case its essence must be given by certain 
material characters previously to and independently of those formal 
determinations. In traditional philosophical ethics the opinion pre- 
vails that the author is, for example, human society (utilitariamsm) 
or the active seif (eudaimonism) or even no one (the categorical 
imperative). From this last proceeds Kant’s doctrine of the ‘‘abso- 
lute ought,” that is, a demand without a demander. One of the worst 
errors of ethical thought lies in his belief that the concept of the 
moral good is completely exhausted by the statement of its purely 
formal property, that it has no content except to be what is de- 
manded, “what should be.” 

6. MaterialL Characteristics- 

In opposition to this, it is clear that the discovery of the formal 
characters of the good constitutes only a preliminary step in the 
determination of the content of the good, in the statement of material 
characteristics. If we know that the good is what is demanded, we 
must still ask: What is it then that is actually demanded? In answer 
to this question we must turn to the author of the command and 
investigate his wUi and desire, for the content of his desire is that 
which he wishes to happen. When I recommend an action to some- 
one as being “good,” I express the fact that I desire it. 

So long as the lawgiver is not known with certainty, we must stick 
to the laws as they are generally observed, to the formulations of 
moral rules as we find them among men. We must discover which 
ways of acting (or dispositions, or whatever be the term used) are 
called “good” by different people, at different times, by different 
wise men or religious writers. Only in this way do come to know^ 
the content of this concept. From the content it may then be pos- 
sible to infer the lawgiving authority, if it cannot be ascertained 
otherwise. 

In grouping together the individual cases in which something is 
designated as morally good, we must search for the common ele- 
ments, the characters in which these examples agree or show simi- 
larities. These similar elements are the characters of the concept 
“good”; they constitute its content, and within them must lie the 
reason why one and the same word, “good,” is used for the several 
cases. 

To be sure, one will at once come upon cases in which nothing 



[ 254 ] 

MORITZ SCHLICK 

common can be found, in which there seems to be a comolete in 
«mpatbd.ty; om apd the same thing-for example, poS^^tSl 
be ^nsidered moral m one community, and in Lother a^Le^ 
such a situation Aere are two possibilities. First, there co^?S 
eral irr^ucibly different concepts of “good” (which aeree in 
purey (^al properly of being somehow “demanded”)- if this 

leaas to it, which actions should therefore be demanrif^rl ^ 

mmmm 

or experimce.) 

"K r.her» — 

„Ser°t pMos„pS”wouId tod 

^ ssrSs .‘tr/d^^Sr 

meat frL S orl'^" Lr b« S'ifr" Y 

SSSS##SSi 

IS quite as important to make out the content L causes of Sei 


Wimi Is the Aim of Ethics? [ 255 ] 

opinions as in any other more regular cases, if the persons in question 
axe importaiit as prophets, moral writers, or morally creative men; 
or if their teachings disclose hidden currents or impress their morai 
judgments on humanity and the future, 

7. Moral Norms and Moral Principles 

The common characteristics which a group of “good” acts or 
dispositions exhibits can be combined in a rule of the form: A mode 
of action must have such and such properties in order to be called 
“good” (or “evil”). Such a rule can also be called a “norm.” Let 
it be understood at once, however, that such a “norm” is nothing 
but a mere expression of fact; it gives us only the conditions under 
which an act or disposition or character is actually called “good,” 
that is, is given a moral value. The setting up of norms is nothing 
but the determination of the concept of the good, which ethics under- 
takes to understand. 

This determination would proceed by seeldng ever new groups 
of acts that are recognized to be good, and showing for each of them 
the rule or norm which all of their members satisfy. The different 
norms, so obtained, would then be compared, and one w^ould order 
them into new classes such that the individual norms of each class 
had something in common, and thus would all be subsumed under 
a higher, that is, a more general, norm. With this higher norm the 
same procedure would be repeated, and so on, until in a perfect 
case, one would at last reach a highest, most general rule that in- 
cluded all others as special cases, and would be applicable to every 
instance of human conduct. This highest norm would be the defini- 
tion of “the good” and would express its universal essence; it would 
be what the philosopher calls a “moral principle.” 

Of course, one cannot know beforehand whether one will actu- 
ally arrive at a single moral principle. It might w^ell be that the 
highest series of rules to which the described way leads simply show^s 
no common character, that one has, therefore, to stop with several 
norms as highest rules, because despite ah attempts none higher 
can be found to which these could be reduced. There would then 
be several mutually independent meanings of the expression “moral 
good,” several mutually independent moral principles which only in 
their totality would determine the concept of morality, or perhaps 
several different concepts of the moral, depending upon the time 
and the people. It is significant how little these possibilities have, 
in general, been considered by philosophers; almost all have at once 


sought a single moral principle Quite the cont schlick 

practical moral systems whin! ^ true of the 

lish an aU-incIusiw Drincinle ° “°t attempt to estab- 

stops at the ten"7mSS:;; “ which 

the determ^ation^of^the'co^Dt^f consists in 

lisfament of one or n ^^tab- 

described procedure would exhaust^S"??^^’ ““P^^tion of the 
a pure “normative science”* for ifc stlucs. It would be 

of a hierarchy of no^s or’mL tv ^ ^ ‘^^^'^^ery 

eral points, the moral Drinciolp? criminated in one or sev- 

explained or “justified” bj the hlS^r^l? ? ^ower levels would 
thrs act moral?” the “XDlflnafir.n the question, “Why is 

under these definite rule?’- and if*?° St'ieo, “Because it falls 
the acts falling under Ais ^ “^y ^re all 

saying, “Because they all faU under Saf be explained by 

wirii the highest norm4 h the 1 t nW 

— ts the knowledne of th“ vaL^^n^ * Principles 

longer possible in “this way" Th-re ^ Justification, no 

sees it as a mere normatSe sde;^ “ who 


8. Ethics as a “Normative Science” 


can have, and in^w^It phrase “nonnative science” 

vaiaata I. “ Srs-“'s“'; “ 

appears that ethics as a normatiL ^ repeatedly 

different from the “factual sciSJes ” T? H "" completely 

person judged to be good"?” or “When is a 

These questions concern mer°\.^^' to be good?” 

does ask, “With w/tar ri?ht is explanation. But it 

does not trouble itself with what k J^ n ^ 

is valuable? What should be Jalued^”'S 

tioc is quite different. ’ obviously the ques- 

fundamentally false^ For°^°eSi^s°fi™^^’'^^ factual sciences is 

so only in the sense jusrex^lS?.^'“f^-^ " Justification it does 

way, not absolutely. It “i^tifies”’ f^^^rive-hypothetical 

extent that it shows that the iudSient “ Judgment only to the 
Aat this norm itself is “right ” or certain norm; 

by itself, determine. ’ ®^»ow nor. 

Even as a nonnaUveVcieSfHeiS^e^ei'r " 


mm 


' WhM is ihe Aim of Ethics? [ 257 J 

more than explain; it can never set up or establish a norm (which 
alone would be equivalent to an absolute justification). It is never 
' able to do more than to discover the rules of the judgment, to read 
them from the facts before it; the origin of norms always lies out- 
side and before science and knowledge. This means that their origin 
can only be apprehended by the science, and does not lie within it 
In other words: if, or in so far as, the philosopher answers the 
question “What is good?’* by an exhibition of norms, this means 
only that he teUs us what “good” actually means; he can never tell 
us what good must or should mean. The question regarding the 
validity of a valuation amounts to asking for a higher acknowledged 
norm under which the value falls, and this is a question of facL 
The question of the justification of the highest norms or the ultimate 
values is senseless, because there is nothing higher to which these 
could be referred. Since modem ethics, as we remarked, often speaks 
of this absolute justification as the fundamental problem of ethics, it 
must be said, unfortunately, that the formulation of the question from 
which it proceeds is simply meaningless. 

The perversity of such a formulation of the question vill be ex- 
hibited by a famous example. John Stuart Mill has often been justly 
criticized because he thought himself able to deduce from the fact 
that a thing was desired that it was in itself desirable. The double 
meaning of the word desirable (“capable of being desired” and “worth 
desiring”) misled him. But his critics were also wrong, for they 
rested their criticism upon the same false presupposition (expressly 
formulated by neither), namely, that the phrase “in itself desirable” 
had a definite meaning (by “in itself’ I mean “for its own sake,” 
not merely as a means to an end); but in fact they could give it 
no meaning. If I say of a thing that it is desirable, and mean that 
one must desire it as a means if one desires a certain end, then tvcry- 
thing is perfectly clear. If, however, I assert that a thing is desirable 
simply in itself, I cannot say what I mean by this statement; it is 
not verifiable and is therefore meaningless. A thing can be desirable 
only with respect to something else, not in itself. Mill believed him- 
self able to deduce what is in itself desirable from what actually is 
desired; his opponents held that these had nothing to do with one 
another. But ultimately neither side knew what it said, for both 
failed to give an absolute meaning to the word “desirable.” The 
question whether something is desirable for its own sake is no ques- 
tion at all, but mere empty words. On the other hand, the question 
of what actually is desired for its own sake is of course quite sensible, 
and ethics is actually concerned only with answering this question. 


258 J 

w^ ^op^ne^ »o^:d“2r.rH^°^ SaiXrs: 

an absolute justification of desire. ^ ^ continued to search for 
9 . Ethics as Factual Science 

values, musTbe SrhJd froTw^ or iigbest 

fore, no result of eftfcs cSi sten!? ^ ^re- 

cannot declare as evil or false those 

of life; its norms cannot demand or m at the foundation 

a real opposition to those final nnrmQ ^^-^’raing that is in 

such opposition occurs it is a^su^e^ rewgiu^d by life. Where 
misunderstood his problem, and has fefed " P^osopher has 
miwntmgly become a mor^st tha‘ he l»i ^ 
role of a knower and would orefer tr ancomiortabie in the 

The demands and claims of^a mnraTi^ “ creator of moral values, 
subjects for investigation for the creative person are merely 

five con,ideraao”®Sd £ MS arl';;' 

raeanmg of tbe word^“eoc^^^^a^- °° opposition betwesc Ihe 
tie Pioaoiog found W Sihilcstir' a?' 

Of course occur, for' lanmia^^e and thn"^^ <^PP^£ra ourerence can 
daily life. Often the speaker°c,nH ^ thou^t^ are verj- imperfect in 
what he expresses, and often his valSion^^°^' as to 

pretation of the facts, and wonld\TlT ^ 

of the mistake. The philosopher would ’ ^ correction 

such errors and faulty expressions and^- discovering 

true norms that lie at ‘the root’ of -Cave to recognize 

them in opposition to the apparSt ' °^ace 

beheves himself to follow. in's^rio 

It necessaiy to delve deep into the hum^ P^^^aps, find 

-ouid .a au ac^al. a.f Vfuit 

ness, and even if elifc^were T'uoSL™''”® “ couscions- 

-ons WMC de.^e ,s'r^- - 


Whai Is the Aim of Ethics? 

I* 259 1 

pMosophei^ who hold the questions of ethics to be the most noble 

and elevated of quesuons just because they do not refer to Se wm 

mon IS but concern the pure ought. “ 

Of course, after one is in the possession of such a svstem of 
norms, of a system of applications of the concents 7noH w f 

system. And this holds eveii°if tC stnicttire of the 

oies, b« are falseinoSSmd luer?" are not the really valid 

arbitrarily established. The last case would unagmed and 

interest of a game and would makf ^ ^ 

Ethics as a nonnatSe sSceTooH “"‘hies.” 

order of rules, in which all acts and aSSS’ ^ ^'^^^rchical 

possess a definite place with resnect to th^ characters would 

course this would be true not onlv of • value. And of 

also of all possible oS to- S L LT 

must beforeLnd supply a plai for '' k-? 

bavior. After beconSg'acqVatotefwftrLT^^^ 

consider the whole svstem withoiit ™ highest norms, one can 

by merely considering S vS^l Th behavior, 

his moral philosophy^ it wfs indifferenr whi? that for 

will actually existed' Hence efhioc o ^hether or not any moral 

would exhibit chScSrisrics ofTn -H 
have to do with a system of Sfi ^^uld 

apphed to actuahtr^d wodd be 

but the rules would have meanin<» oifito^' possess any mterest, 
cation, and could be investi<^ated“ in J .“bependently of this appli- 
Thus someone might have invented relations to one another, 
have considered their application tn tb chess, and might 

the game had never beeTSeTex^^^^^ if 

nary opponents. " " ’ ™ b's mind, between imagi- 

10. Ethics Seeks Causal Explanation 

ethic?is"S^? xpkfn Z"mo"T "bat the task of 

of thing this “good”% whiS '^bat sort 

this subject-matter of ethics is not <dv^ tn found that 

object-matter of optics, light thatls bv a ‘be 

for Its determination the discover? of ,^w , but that 

Of ov 



[ 260 ] 

MORITZ SCHLICS 

^ ^ “normative science,” we see 

ft? tSI * ^ ^ toe discovery of 

fee meaning of the concept “good.” In this it exhausts itse? SeS 

oT.^ “ It of a real explanation of the good. It offers ethics 

orfy the object which h to be explained. Therefore we have tom 
tolje the view of those philosophers who consider ethics 

IndT “®"®^yf^?tomative science. No, only where the theory of nomi 
to ie Se f™ ^fPl^^tion begin. The former fails 'com^S^ 
-I important, excitmg questions of ethics, or, worse ^turm 
to aside as foreign in essence to ethics; in truth h S eSS 

mintog thTmeaSngs o?ke^^^^^ 

back to one“anothef umH th?t ^ referred 

nrniHr>i<.c. ^ untd the highest are reactied. Thece the moral 

te relied °o XScil'i”''’''’' 

a special cas™rf shown to be 

rsf “ bTsi-iS“?s 

bavicr '‘5“ “™'- is moral be- 

justified by means of an fii Jbest moral norm would be 

be ^errej bac “o1 S£ "roge^f'Se'^' 

1="' >be 

very reason that it is the Jt '* *e 

ther justification a f. 3, be senseless to ask for a fur- 

ciples, or values themtostoat^SSiT-^* is not the norms, prin- 
of explanation but rather th^ f tf^ i f “ capable 

stracted. These facts are the 

approbation in bnmar. givmg rules, of valuation, of 

the life of the soul “VaS’e°’°Te°“^’d “ 

som. Value, the good,” are mere abstractions, but 


WhM is the Aim of Ethics? [ ] 

f atoatioE, approbation^ are actual psychic occurrences, and separate 
acts of this sort are quite capable of explanation, that is, can be 
reduced to one another. 

And here lies the proper task of ethics. Here are the remarkable 
facts which excite philosophic wonder, and whose explanation has 
always been the final goal of ethical inquiry. That man actually 
approves of certain actions, declares certain dispositions to be "‘good,” 
appears not at all self-explanatory to the philosopher, but often very 
astonishing, and he therefore asks his “Why?” Now, in all of the 
natural sciences every explanation can be conceived as a causal 
explanation, a truth which we need not prove here; therefore the 
“why” has the sense of a question concerning the cause of that psy- 
chical process in which man makes a valuation, establishes a moral 
claim. (We must make clear that when we speak of the discoveiy^ of 
the “cause,” we mean by the term “cause” only a popular abbrevia- 
tion for the statement of the complete laws governing the event to be 
known.) 

In other words, the determination of the contents of the concepts 
of good and evil is made by the use of moral principles and a system 
of norms, and affords a relative justification of the lower moral rules 
by the higher; scientific knowledge of the good, on the other hand, 
does not concern norms, but refers to the cause, concerns not the 
justification but the explanation of moral judgments. The theory of 
norms asks, "'What does actually serve as the standard of conduct?” 
Explanatory^ ethics, however, asks '*Why does it serve as the standard 
of conduct?” 

11. Formulation of the Fundamental Question 

It is clear that in essence the first question is a dry, formal matter 
that could win little interest from man did it not have such importance 
for practice, and if the path to its answer did not offer so many op- 
portunities for profound insight into human nature. The second 
question, however, leads directly to these profundities. It concerns 
the real grounds, the actual causes and motives that drive one to 
distinguish between good and evil, and call forth the acts of moral 
judgment. Not only judgments, but also conduct, for this follows upon 
judgment. The explanation of moral judgment cannot be separated 
from the explanation of conduct. To be sure, one should not be- 
lieve, without further reason, that everyone arranges his conduct 
according to Ms moral judgments. Obviously, that would be a false 
assumption. The connection, although indissoluble, is more compli- 





r 262 ] 

*■ ^ MORITZ SCHLICK 

^ted mat a man values, approves, and desires is finally inferred 
rom ins actions — better from these than from his assertions, though 
toese, too, are Imds of action. What kind of demands one makes 
of himself and others can only be known from one’s conduct. A man’s 
y^uations must somehow appear among the motives of his acts- 
mey cannot, m any case, be discovered anywhere else. He who traces 
the causes of conduct far enough must come upon the causes of 
all approbation. The question of the causes of conduct is, therefore 
more general than that of the grounds of moral judgments; its answer 
would give more comprehensive knowledge, and it would be meth- 
ooopcally profitable to start with it even if it were not necessary 
to l^n with the study of conduct as the only thing observable. 

should replace the question raised above. 
What mohyes cause us to establish moral nonns?” by the other 
question, ‘What are the motives of conduct in general?” (We for- 
mulate the question in this general way and do not at once restrict 
It to moral actions because, according to what has been said, it might 
-possible to deduce valuations and their motives just as well, if not 
better, irom immoral or neutral acts.) We are the more warranted in 
relating our question at once to conduct, since man interests himself 
m valuations only because conduct depends upon them. If moral 
approbation were something that remained enclosed in the depths 

i i! . ^ ™ ^'^y could not exert 

e least mfiuence on the life, happiness and unhappiness of man, 

^ one would botner himself with it, and the philosopher would 
become acquamted with this unimportant phenomenon only by an 

.5 concerning the moral judgments 

oescribed as the earliest impulse leading to 
the formulation of ethical questions, is above aU wonder at his own 
actual moral behavior. 

'S, the regularity and 

ord-r, of all human actions, with the aim of discovering the motives 
of moral actions. And we profit in so doing because we can post- 
pone the question regarding the essence of morality, the moral prin- 
ciple, until we solve the problem of the natural law governing be- 
havior in general. When, however, we come to know about action 
m general, it will certainly be much easier to leam what is peculiar 

define the content of the concept “good” 
TOthout difficulty Perhaps it will turn out that we no longef feel 
the necessity of detenninmg a sharp boundary for it (just as, after 
me physical explanation of light, the question of how and whether 
the concept of hght” is to be distinguished from that of heat radi- 
ation or ultra-violet radiation loses afl interest). 



[ 263 ] 


'■ ' ^ WhM Is the Aim of Ethics? 

- - : ' ' ■ 12 . The Method of Ethics Is Psychological 

Tinas the cenixai problem of ethics concerns the causal explana- 
ir’ tioE of moral behavior; all others in relation to it sink to the level of 
preliminary or subordinate questions. The moral problem was most 
clearly formulated in this way by Schopenhauer, whose sound sense 
of reality led him to the correct path here (if not in the solution) 
and guarded him from the Kantian formulation of the problem and 
from the post-Kantian philosophy of value. 

' The problem which we must put at the center of ethics is a purely 
psycholo^cal one. For, without doubt, the discovery of the motives 
I or laws of any kind of behavior, and therefore of moral behavior, is 
a purely psychological afiair. Only the empirical science of the laws 
which describe the life of the soul can solve this problem. One 
might wish to derive from this a supposedly profound and destructive 
objection to our formulation of the problem. For, one might say, 
“In such case there would be no ethics at aU; w^hat is called ethics 
would be nothing but a part of psychology!” I answer, "'Why 
shouldn’t ethics be a part of psychology?” Perhaps in order that 
the philosopher have his science for himself and govern autonomously 
in tMs sphere? He w^ould, indeed, thereby be freed of many burden- 
some protests of psycholog}^ If he laid down a command, ''Thus 
shall man act,” he w^ould not have to pay attention to the psycholo- 
^t who said to him, “But man cannot act so, because it contradicts 
psychological laws!” I fear greatly that here and there this motive, 
though hidden, is at work. However, if one says candidly that “there 
is no ethics,” because it is not necessary to label a part of psychology 
by a special name, then the question is merely terminological. 

It is a poor recommendation of the philosophical spirit of our 
age that w^e so often attempt to draw strict lines of division between 
the sciences, to separate ever new disciplines, and to prove their 
autonomy. The true philosopher goes in the opposite direction; he 
does not wish to make the single sciences self-sufficient and inde- 
pendent, but, on the contrary, to unify and bring them together; he 
wishes to show that what is common to them is what is most essen- 
tial, and that what is different is accidental and to be viewed as 
belonging to practical methodology. Sub specie aeiernitatis there is 
for him only one reality and one science. 

Therefore, if we decide that the fundamental question of ethics, 
i “Why does man act morally?” can be answered oiffy by psychology, 

1 we see in this no degradation of, nor injury to, science, but a happy 
simplification of the world-picture. In ethics we do not seek inde- 
i pendence, but only the truth. 



13 



The Emotive Meaning 

of Ethical Terms 

BY C. L. STEVENSON 


I 

Ethical questions first arise in the form “Is so and sc good?” or 
‘Is this alternative better than that?” These questions are difficult 
partly because we don’t quite know what we are seeking. We are 
asking, “Is there a needle in that haystack?” without even knowing 
just what a needle is. So the first thing to do is to examine the ques- 
tions themselves. We must tiy^ to make them clearer, either by de- 
fining the terms in w^hich they are expressed, or by any other method 
that is available. 

The present paper is concerned wholly with this preliminar}^ step 
of making ethical questions clear. In order to help answer the ques- 
tion ‘Ts X good?” we must subsutute for it a question which is 
free from ambiguity and confusion. 

It is obvious that in substituting a clearer question we must not 
introduce some utterly different land of question. It won’t do (to 
take an extreme instance of a prevalent fallacy) to substitute for ‘Ts 
X good?” the question “Is X pink with yellow trimmings?” and 
then point out how^ easy the question really is. This would beg the 
original question, not help answer it. On the other hand, we must not 
expect the substituted question to be strictly “identical” with the 
original one. The original question may embody hypostatization, 
anthropomorphism, vagueness, and all the other ills to which our 
ordinary discourse is subject. If our substituted question is to be 
clearer, it must remove these ills. The questions wiU be identical only 
in the sense that a child is identical with the man he later becomes. 
Hence we must not demand that the substitution strike us, on imme- 
diate introspection, as making no change in meaning. 

This article first appeared in Mind, 1937. It is reprinted with tiie kind perxoission 
of Professor Stevenson and the editor of Mind. 


[ 264 ] 


: Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms . [ 265 ] 

• Just how, then, must the substituted question be related to the 
original? Let us assume (inaccurately) that it must result from re- 
placing “good” by some set of terms which define it. The question 
then resolves itself to this: How must the defined meaning of “good” 
■'he related to its original meaning? 

I answer that it must be relevant. A defined meaning will be 
called “relevant” to the original meaning under these circumstances: 
Those who have understood the definition must be able to say all 
that they then want to say by using the term in the defined way. 
They must never have occasion to use the term in the old, unclear 
sense. (If a person did have to go on using the word in the old 
sense, then to this extent his meaning would not be clarified, and the 
philosophical task w^ould not be completed.) It frequently happens 
that a word is used so confusedly and ambiguously that we must 
give it several defined meanings, rather than one. In this case only 
the whole set of defined meanings will be called “relevant,” and any 
one of them will be called “partially relevant.” This is not a rigorous 
treatment of relevance, by any means; but it will strvQ for the 
present purposes. 

Let us now turn to our particular task — that of giving a relevant 
definition of “good.” Let us first examine some of the ways in which 
others have attempted to do this. 

The word “good” has often been denned in terms of approval, 
or similar psychological attimdes. We may take as typical examples: 
“good” means desired by me (Hobbes); and “good” means ap- 
proved by most people (Hume, in effect).* It will be convenient 
to refer to definitions of this sort as “interest theories,” following 
Mr. R. B. Perry, although neither “interest” nor “theory” is used in 
the most usual way. 

Are definitions of this sort relevant? 

It is idle to deny their partial relevance. The most superficial 
inquiry wiH reveal that “good” is exceedingly ambiguous. To main- 
tain that “good” is never used in Hobbes’s sense, and never in 
Hume’s, is only to manifest an insensitirity to the complexities of 
language. We must recognize, perhaps, not only these senses, but 
a variety of similar ones, differing both with regard to the kind of 
interest in question, and with regard to the people who are said to 
have the interest. 

* [The author has requested that the following note be added here: For a more 
adequate treatment of Hume’s views see my Ethics and Language (Yale University 
Press, 1944), Chap. XII, Sect. 5. In the present paper the references to Hume are 
to be taken as references to the general family of definitions of which Hume’s is 
typical; but Hume’s own definition is somewhat different from any that is here 
specifically stared. Perhaps the same should be said of Hobbes.] 



[ 266 ] 

„ . C. L. STEVENSON 

Z ^ Tlie essential question is not whether 

GmISd Briefly : 

teS^ of SSreT^ ^ relevantly be defined L 

SO defined? w relevantly 

*1! qSm “l5 y ”j?“°”f = " ““i" it”' *‘>"”'1 

thfc ^ good?” SO difficult, they have been graspin-^ for 

terms orinterest°Tf"^°°^’”- relevantly defined in 

Srani anl. r? °° “^ood” in terns of inter- 

3 ^ nswer the question when thus interpreted we mav be 

entirely. Of course this oSer sense of “gLd^ 
TmS Sv" ■' ""i' ** “ “■*-=; bu. .ha. 

Now many have maintained that interest theories are inr fmm 
being completely relevant. They have arid SfsS SeSe^ 

neglech the very sense of “good” which is iSost vital And^certainlv 
their apments are not without plausibility. certainly, 

“vital” sense of “good”? The answers 

scarcely detfnJnT’ 

whether' LmethiS'is “'ojd”"' ■ni."'''' •' lisagres about 

de^Mou. For cf„siher".r 

cTmS:‘“'r,3re'li?; SS”. *?, HobbL.ViTbt 

aesire tins. ihat isn t so, xor / don't” Th^ sd^^Wq 
J not contraaicting one another, and think thev are, oniv becaute 

“Jood” pronouns. The definition, 

cfuld neonw”^ Community, is also excluded, for how 

could people from different communities disasree?i 

In the second place, “goodness” must have so to sneal- 

a?™- ^ recognizes X to be “good” mist )pso 

facto acquire a stronger tendency to act in its favor than he other- 

Foi accordin^To^HuiT^^t the Humian type of definition, 

^imnixr tr. ^ Tccognize that something is “good” is 

Tv if I*' ““’'’"‘y “PP"”' ”P ■'• 6'arly: a mrS 

may see ri iat Uie majonq- approve of X wittiout haviug, iLself, a 

L See G. E. Moore’s Philosophical Studies, pp. 332 - 334 . 


Xke Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [267] 

Stronger tendency to favor it. This requirement excludes any attempt 
"to define “good” in terms of the interest of people other than the 
speaker.^ 

In the third place, the “goodness” of anything must not be verifi- 
able solely by use of the scientific method. “Ethics must not be 
psychology.” This restriction rules out all of the traditional interest 
theories, without exception. It is so sweeping a restriction that we 
must examine its plausibility. What are the methodological implica- 
tions of interest theories which are here rejected? 

According to Hobbes’s definition, a person can prove Ms ethical 
judgments, with finality, by showing that he is not making an intro- 
spective error about Ms desires. According to Hume’s definition, one 
may prove ethical judgments (roughly speaking) by taking a vote. 
This use of the empirical method, at any rate, seems Mghly remote 
from what we usually accept as proof, and refiects on the complete 
relevance of the definitions which imply it. 

But aren’t there more complicated interest theories which are 
immune from such methodological implications? No, for the same 
factors appear; they are only put off for a wmle. Consider, for ex- 
ample, the definition: “X is good” means most people would approve 
of X if they knew its nature and consequences. How, according to 
this definition, could prove that a certain X was good? We should 
first have to find out, empirically, just what X w^as like, and what 
its consequences would be. To tMs extent the empirical method, as 
required by the definition, seems beyond inteliigent objection. But 
what remains? We should next have to discover w^hether most 
people would approve of the sort of thing we had discovered X to 
be. TMs couldn’t be determined by popular vote — ^but only because 
it would be too difficult to explain to the voters, beforehand, w^hat the 
nature and consequences of X really w^ere. Apart from this, voting 
would be a pertinent method. We are again reduced to counting 
noses, as a perfectly final appeal. 

Now we need not scorn voting entirely. A man w^ho rejected 
interest theories as irrelevant might readily make the follo\ring state- 
ment: “If I believed that X would be approved by the majority, 
when they knew all about it, I should be strongly led to say that X 
was good.” But he would continue: "'Need I say that X w^as good, 
under the circumstances? Wouldn’t my acceptance of the alleged 
""final proof result simply from my being democratic? What about 
the more aristocratic people? They would simply say that the ap- 
proval of most people, even when they knew^ aU about the object 


2. See G. C. Field’s Moral Theory, pp. 52, 56-57. 


I : C 268 ] 

of their approval simnlv t.- ^'^'^^enson 

^ything, and they woiJld probX’^df of 

low state of people’s iotereL ’’ Jt the 

^nsiderations, that the definhion w JS? h these 

^p^sed democratic ideals from the stnrf ^-ri? has pre- 

theories and others may method, as implied by interest 

different way. Mr. G. E ^ “S 

question is chiefly pertinent the open 

scientifically knowable properties a thfnl*^’ ®^tter what set of 
m effect), you will find, on carrful im ° hfoore, 

question to ask whether anwhin^ hf “ ts an open 

It IS difficult to believe that 'thic ^ properties is good 

fused one, or that it seems fpen o Jv hi " totally^cot 

good. Rather, we must be usmcr ^ ■'^uuse of the ambiguity of 
not definable, relevantly in term^ which is 

able_ That is, the scientifc method ? know- 

These, then are th^ ° sufficient for ethics s 

mteffigent disagreement; (2) fl'inusi jl 7"'® a topic for 

-s. ao, ^ u;zzt 

II 

I^me prLem my'posiS dogmrnfcSy judgments. First 

vary irom tradition. aticallj, showing to what extent I 

fZVTlZToi ^^ven above, are perfectly 
l£ ^^^^rements; and that no traditinl satisfies all 

£™ J' S "°‘ topl/lha “Cf.rt” 

a Platonic Idea, or of a Cntf> ^ • ^ust be explained in 

unique, unanalyxable property On th Imperative, or of an 

ments cap be me. by ““ -I*” 

prauppostuon xhich all the traditionaUm^' ‘a “P 

Traditional interest theories hold rh f rlieor/ei’ have made 
scnpuve of the existing s^afo of statements are de- 

information about Wesr (mU sL 

!!!i7 what the state of ffiS?’- Judgments 





The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [ 269 ] 

or to indicate what the state of interests would be under specified 
circnmstaBces.) It is this emphasis on description, on informatioji^ 
which leads to their incomplete relevance. Doubtless there is al- 
ways some element of description in ethical judgments, but this is 
by "no means aH. Their major use is not to indicate facts, but to 
create an influence. Instead of merely describing people’s interests, 
they change or intensify them. They recommend an interest in an 
object, rather than state that the interest already exists. 

For instance: When you tell a man that he oughtn’t to steal, your 
object isn’t "merely to let him know that people disapprove of 
stealing. You are attempting, rather, to get him to disapprove of it. 
Your ethical judgment has a quasi-imperative force which, operating 
through suggestion, and intensified by your tone of voice, readily 
permits you to begin to influence ^ to modify^ his interests. If in the 
end you do not succeed in getting him to disapprove of stealing, you 
will feel that you’ve failed to convince him that stealing is wrong. 
You will continue to feel this, even though he fully acknowledges 
that you disapprove of it, and that almost everv^one else does. V/hen 
you point out to him the consequences of his actions — consequences 
which you suspect he already disapproves of — these reasons w^hich 
support your ethical judgment are simply a means of facilitaticg 
your infiuence. If you think you can change his inieresis by maldng 
vivid to him how' others wiU disapprove of him, you will do so: 
otherwise not. So the consideration about other people’s interest is 
just an additional means you may employ, in order to move him, 
and is not a part of the ethical judgment itself. Your ethical judg- 
ment doesn’t merely describe interests to him. it directs his very 
interests. The difference between the traditional interest theories 
and my view’ is like the difference between describing a desert and 
irrigating it. 

Another example: A munition maker declares that w’ar is a 
good thing. If he merely meant that he approved of it, he would 
not have to insist so strongly, nor grow so excited in his argument. 
People would be quite easily convinced that he approved of it. If 
he merely meant that most people approved of war, or that most 
people would approve of it if they knew the consequences, he w^ould 
have to yield his point if it were proved that this wasn’t so. But he 
wouldn’t do this, nor does consistency require it. He is not describing 
the state of people’s approval; he is trying to change it by his influ- 
ence. If he found that few people approved of war, he might insist 
all the more strongly that it wms good, for there would be more 
changing to be done. 


rp, - , C. L. STEVENSON 

oto.T“ M iXS r- f “ “y 

MMicmg pe<2k bS^ "S “* “S^i” I ™ oo^ 

times goes o? S 4e ^ 

influence is bad ^that is if the h ^ naunition maker’s 

disapproval of the man, ’and^o people’s 

actions — ^I should ai- arinths.,- +• u ^ disapprove of his own 

taking. But this is not the preS 

ter^, but am indicating how they are Sd^^S v“° 
in his use of “good ” niustratL mumtion maker, 

just as weh as" does 

each of us a desire for thf-hc^ * to encourage in 

good is peLe " that the sup?em“ 

interplay and readj ™mem^ of^ complicated 

plainly from more gS oL^Z T 

arated communities have d T °°f ‘ sep- 

extent because IZl otn 

Now clearly this influence doesn’t onp t° influences, 

alone; words play a great oart PpS ^^ through sticks and stones 
courage certaiS ihnSSs'^ a^d bS 

others. Those of forceful D-r^nnfr?^ anotner, to discourage 

people, for complicated hTstm^f commands which weaker 

obey, quite auart from fears rn dificult to. dis- 

brought to bear by w-riters and influence is 

erted, to an enormous ext^ bvT^^^^^ 

pbysical force or material rewa^rcT Th^ nothing to do with 

influence. Being suited for use in’ facilitate such 

which men’s attitudesinay bSTed^^nif ^ bv 

that we find a greater then, 

munity than in those of different attitudes of one com- 

JHdgments propagate themselves 

t^ may influence the arrival of ?nn^ S°°d”; 

the same ethical judgment whirh ^ person, who then makes 
son, and so on. In C L L Per- 

r"r-“ ~ 

ow does an ethical sentence acquire its 


The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [ 271 ] 

l^wer of mflnencmg people — why is it suited to suggestion? Again, 
what has this influence to do with the meaning of ethical terms? 
And finally, do these considerations really lead ns to a sense of 
“good” which meets the requirements mentioned in the preceding 
■ section? 

Let ns deal first with the question about meaning. This is far 
from an easy question, so we must enter into a preliminary inquiry 
about meaning in general. Althou^ a seeming digression, this will 
prove indispensable. 

m 

Broadly speaking, there are two different purposes which lead 
us to use language. On the one hand we use words (as in science) 
to record, clarify, and communicate beliefs. On the other hand we 
use words to give vent to our feelings (interjections), or to create 
moods (poetry), or to incite people to actions or attitudes (oratory). 

The first use of words I shall call “descriptive”; the second, 
“dynamic.” Note that the distinction depends solely upon the pur- 
pose of the speaker. 

When a person says “Hydrogen is the lightest known gas,” his 
purpose may be simply to lead the hearer to believe this, or to be- 
lieve that the speaker believes it. In that case the words are used 
descriptively. W^en a person cuts himself and says “Damn,” his 
purpose is not ordinarily to record, clarify, or communicate any 
belief. The word ig used dynamically. The two ways of using words, 
however, are by no means mutuaiiy exclusive. This is obvious from 
the fact that our purposes are often complex. Thus when one says 
‘T want you to close the door,” part of his purpose, ordinarily, is 
to lead the hearer to believe that he has this want. To that extent 
the words are used descriptively. But the major part of one’s purpose 
is to lead the hearer to satisfy the want. To that extent the w^ords 
are used d3mamicaiiy. 

It very frequently happens that the same sentence may have a 
dynamic use on one occasion, and may not have a dynamic use on 
another; and that it may have different dynamic uses on different 
occasions. For instance: A man says to a visiting neighbor, “I am 
loaded down with work.” His purpose may be to let the neighbor 
know how life is going with him. This would not be a dynamic 
use^ of words. He may make the remark, however, in order to drop 
a hint. This would be dynamic usage (as well as descriptive). Again, 
he may make the remark to arouse the neighbor’s sympathy. This 
would be a different dynamic usage from that of hinting. 


C, L. STEVBNSON 



Or agaiii, when we say to a man, “Of course you won’t make 
those mistakes any more,” we may simply be making a prediction. 
But we are more likely to be using “suggestion,” in order to en- 
courage Mm and hence keep Mm from making mistakes. The first 
use would be descriptive; the second, mainly dynamic. 

From these examples it will be clear that we can’t determine 
whether words are used dynamically or not, merely by reading the 
dictionary — even assuming that everyone is faithful to dictionary 
meanings. Indeed, to know whether a person is using a word 
dynamically, we must note Ms tone of voice, Ms gestures, the gen- 
eral circumstances under which he is speaking, and so on. 

We must now proceed to an important question: What has the 
dynamic use of words to do with their meaning? One thing is clear 
— ^we must not define “meaning” in a way that would make meaning 
vary with dynamic usage. If we did, we should have no use for the 
term. All that we could say about such “meaning” would be that it 
is very complicated, and subject to constant change. So we must 
certainly distinguish between the dynamic use of words and their 
meaning. 

It doesn’t follow, however, that we must define “meaning” in 
some non-psychological fashion. We must simply restrict the psy- 
chological field. Instead of identifying meaning with all the psycho- 
logical causes and effects that attend a word’s utterance, we must 
identify it with those that it has a tendency (causal property, dis- 
positional property) to be connected with. The tend^enc}’^ must be of 
a particular kind, moreover. It must exist for all who speak the 
language; it must be persistent; and must be realizable more or less 
independently of determinate circumstances attending the word’s 
utterance- There will be further restrictions dealing with the inter- 
relation of words in different contexts. Moreover, we must include, 
under the psychological responses which the words tend to produce, 
not only immediately introspectabie experiences, but dispositions to 
react in a given way with appropriate stimuli. I hope to go into these 
matters in a subsequent paper. Suffice it now to say that I think 
“meaning” may be thus defined in a way to include “propositional” 
meaning as an important kind. Now a word may tend to have causal 
relations which in fact it sometimes doesn’t; and it may sometimes 
have causal relations which it doesn't tend to have. And since the 
tendency of words which constitutes their meaning must be of a 
particular kind, and may include, as responses, dispositions to reac- 
tions, of which any of several immediate experiences may be a sign, 
then there is nothing surprising in the fact that words have a per- 


/The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [ 273 ] 

-laaiieBt meaning, in spite of the fact that the immediately intro- 
spectable experiences which attend their usage are so highly varied. 

When “meaning” is defined in this way, meaning will not include 
dynamic use. For although words are sometimes accompanied by 
dynamic purposes, they do not tend to be accompanied by them in 
the way above mentioned. E.g., there is no tendency realizable inde- 
pendently of the determinate circumstances under which the words 
are uttered. 

There will be a kind of meaning, however, in the sense above 
defined, which has an intimate relation to dynamic usage. I refer 
to “emotive” meaning (in a sense roughly like that employed by 
Ogden and Richards).^ The emotive meaning of a word is a tendency 
of a word, arising through the history of its usage, to produce 
(result from) affective responses in people. It is the immediate 
aura of feeling which hovers about a word. Such tendencies to pro- 
duce affective responses cling to words vory tenaciously. It would 
be difficult, for instance, to express merriment by using the inter- 
jection “alas.” Because of the persistence of such afiective tenden- 
cies (among other reasons) it becomes feasible to classify them as 
“meanings.” 

Just what is the relation between emotive meaning and the 
dynamic nse of words? Let us take an example. Suppose that a 
man is talking with a group of people which includes Miss Jones, 
aged 59. He refers to her, without thinking, as an “old maid.” Now 
even if his purposes are perfectly innocent — even if he is using the 
words purely descriptively — Miss Jones won’t think so. She will 
think he is encouraging the others to have contempt for her, and 
wiU draw in her skirts, defensively. Tne man might have dons better 
if instead of saying “old maid” he had said “elderly spinster.” The 
latter words could have been put to the same descriptive use, and 
would not so readily have caused suspicions about the dynamic use. 

“Old maid” and “elderly spinster” differ, to be sure, only in 
emotive meaning. From the example it will be clear that certain 
words, because of their emotive meaning, are suited to a certain 
kind of dynamic use — so well suited, in fact, that the hearer is likely 
to be misled when we use them in any other way. The more pro- 
nounced a word’s emotive meaning is, the less likely people are to 
use it purely descriptively. Some words are suited to encourage 
people, some to discourage them, some to quiet them, and so on. 

4. Sec The Meaning of Meaning, by C. K. Ogden and I. A, Ricimrda. Offl p. 
125, second edition, there is a passage on ethics which was the source of the 
ideas embodied in this paper. 


[ 274 ] 

. C. L. STEVENSON 

to dynamic purposes are not 

piuSriut fhli “ persistently than do the dynamic 

5.H / “ contingent relation between emo- 

W^nrvx -f ^ dynamic purpose: the former assists the latter 
th?. 7® terms in a way tharneieS 

SliSfc°S S!T^’ we are likely to be confusing. L /eod pfople 
thJy te dynamically less often tLn 


(•‘W=- incW« tt?hetro”‘h“ei“ ^■ 

s!tpM tofind If used, we should 

see. to cast d^uht 

that - ‘W™*!"??,' '’“T"’ ““ •" “ assuming 

take the place of “This is crnnrf’^ ^ 

not purelv descriotivelv Juft ^ former sentence must be used 

be used to promL a very « must 

question, a veiw easily resisted! kiifrf'^ non-moral sense in 

that “we” refers to th- ^ ^ 'Po the extent 

tial to suggestion o?Ie2S\e 

rather than merely to believe it AnH f 2 ^ 

to the speaker thl sentenr^ i t k ° 

of indicatin^bSef ?£°f 7“^^ descriptive use 

inteijecto^'dSaSc fank-?' Q^usi- 

interest. (This immediate exnreQs° direct expression to the 

of sugsestion It is difficuit^tn Poolings assists in the process 

enthuS'asm.) disapprove in the face of another’s 

For an example of a case where “We like this” is used in the 


■ The Emotive Mecming of Ethical Terms [ 275 ] 

dynamic way that “This is good” is used, consider the case of a 
^ mother who says to her several children, “One thing is certain, we 
Ml like to be neat/' If she really believed this, she wouldn’t bother 
to say so. But she is not using the words descriptively. She is en- 
couraging the children to like neatness. By telling them that they 
like neatness, she will lead them to make her statement true, so to 
speak. If, instead of saying “We all like to be neat” in this way, 
she had said “It’s a good thing to be neat,” the effect would have 
been approximately the same. 

But these remarks are stiH misleading. Even when “We like it” 
is used for suggestion, it isn’t quite like “This is good.” The latter 
is more subtle. With such a sentence as “This is a good book,” for 
example, it would be practically impossible to use instead “We 
like this book.” When the latter is used, it must be accompanied 
by so exaggerated an intonation, to prevent its becoming confused 
with a descriptive statement, that the force of suggestion becomes 
stronger, and ludicrously more overt, than when “good” is used. 

The definition is inadequate, further, in that the definiens has 
been restricted to dynamic usage. Having said that dynamic usage 
was different from meaning, I should not have to mention it in giv- 
ing the meaning of “good.” 

It is in connection with this last point that we must return to 
emotive meaning. The word “good” has a pleasing emotive meaning 
which fits it especially for the dynamic use of suggesting favorable 
interest. But the sentence “We like it” has no such emotive mean- 
ing. Hence my definition has neglected emotive meaning entirely. 
Now to neglect emotive meaning is likely to lead to endless con- 
fusions, as we shall presently see; so I have sought to make up for 
the inadequacy of the definition by letting the restriction about dy- 
namic usage take the place of emotive meaning. What I should do, 
of course, is to find a definiens whose emotive meaning, like that of 
“good,” simply does lead to dynamic usage. 

Why didn’t I do this? I answer that it isn’t possible, if the 
definition is to afford us increased clarity. No two words, in the first 
place, have quite the same emotive meaning. The most we can 
hope for is a rough approximation. But if we seek for such an ap- 
proximation for “good,” we shall find nothing more than synonyms, 
such as “desirable” or “valuable”; and these are profitless because 
they do not clear up the connection between “good” and favorable 
interest. If we reject such synonyms, in favor of non-ethical terms, 
we shall be highly misleading. For instance: “This is good” has 
something like the meaning of “I do like this; do so as well.” But 





f 276 ] 

J c. L. STEVENSON 

this is certainly not accurate. For the imperative makes an appeal 
to the consdous efforts of the hearer. Of course he can’t Uke some- 
tog just by tiymg. He must be led to like it through suggestion. 
Hence an ethical sentence differs from an imperative in that it en- 
ables one to make changes in a much more subtle, less fully con- 
scious way. Note that the ethical sentence centers the hearer’s 
attention not on his interests, but on the object of interest, and 
thereby facilitates suggestion. Because of its subtlety, moreover, an 
ethical sentence readily permits counter-suggestion, and leads to the 

^e and take situation which is so characteristic of arguments 
about values. 

Strictly sf^aking, then, it is impossible to deffne “good” in terms 
of favorable interest if emotive meaning is not to be distorted. Yet 
It IS possiole to say that “This is good” is about the favorable interest 
of tne speaker and the hearer or hearers, and that it has a pleas- 
meaning which fits the words for use in suggestion. 
Tms is^a rough description of meanine. not a definition. "But it 
seiwes the same clarifying function that a definition ordinarily does: 
and that, after all, is enough. 

added about the moral use of “aood.” This 
differs from the above in that it is about a different kind" of interest, 
nstead of being about what the hearer and sneaker lik^, it is about 
a stronger sort of approval. When a person likes something, he is 
pleased wnen it prospers, and disappointed when it doesn’t When 
a person morally approves of something, he experiences a rich feel- 
mg or_ security when it prospers, and is indignant, or “shocked” 
w en It doesn’t.^ These are rough and inaccurate examples of the 
many factors ivhich one would have to mention in distineuishina 
tne two^itmds^or interest. In the moral usage, as well as in the non- 
morm, good” has an emotive meaning which adapts it to suggestion. 

And now, are these considerations of anv * importance? Why 
do I stress emotive meanings in this fashion? Does the omission of 
them really lead people into errors? I think, indeed, that the errors 
resulting from such omissions are enormous. In order to see this 
however, we must return to the restrictions, mentioned in section I,’ 
with which the ‘vital” sense of “good” has been expected to comply. 


The first restriction, it will be remembered, had to do with dis- 
agreement. Now there is clearly some sense in which people disagree 
on ethical points; but we must not rashly assume that all disagree- 


'The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [ 277 ] 

meiit is modelled after the sort that occurs in the natural sciences. 
We must distinguish between “disagreement in belief’ (typical of 
the' sciences) and “disagreement in interest.” Disagreement in belief 
occurs when A believes p and B disbelieves it. Disagreement in 
interest occurs when A has a. favorable interest in X, when B has 
an unfavorable one in it, and when neither is content to let the 
other’s interest remain unchanged. 

Let me give an example of disagreement in interest. A. “Let’s 
go to a cinema to-night.” B. “I don’t want to do that. Let’s go to 
the symphony.” A continues to insist on the cinema, B on the sym- 
phony. This is disagreement in a perfectly conventional sense, lliey 
can’t agree on where they want to go, and each is trying to redirect 
the others interest. (Note that imperatives are used in the example.) 

It is disagreement in interest which takes places in ethics. When 
C says “This is good,” and D says “No, it’s bad,” we have a case of 
suggestion and counter-suggestion. Each man is trying to redirect 
the other’s interest. There obviously need be no domineering, since 
each may be willing to give ear to the other’s influence; but each 
is trying to move the other nonetheless. It is in this sense that 
they disagree. Those who argue that certain interest theories make 
no provision for disagreement have been misled, I believe, simply 
because the traditional theories, in lea\ing out emotive meaning, 
give the impression that ethical judgments are used descriptively 
only; and of course when judgments are used purely descriptively, 
the only disagreement that can arise is disagreement in belief. Such 
disagreement may be disagreement in belief about interests; but 
this is not the same as disagreement in interest. My definition doesn’t 
provide for disagreement in belief about interests, any more than, 
does Hobbes’s; but that is no matter, for there is no reason to be- 
lieve, at least on common-sense grounds, that this kind of disagree- 
ment exists. There is only disagreement in interest. (We shall see 
in a moment that disagreement in interest does not remove ethics 
from sober argument — that this land of disagreement may often be 
resolved through empirical means.) 

The second restriction, about “magnetism,” or the connection 
between goodness and actions, requires only a word. This rules out 
only those interest theories which do not include the interest of the 
speaker, in defining “good,” My account does include the speaker’s 
interest; hence is immune. 

The third restriction, about the empirical method, may be met 
in a way that springs naturally from the above account of disagree- 
ment. Let us put the question in this way: When two people dis- 


C. L. STEVENSON 



agree over an ethical matter, can they completely resolve the dis- 
agreement through empirical considerations, assuming that each 
applies the empirical method exhaustively, consistently, and with- 
out error? 

I answer that sometimes they can, and sometimes they cannot; 
and that at any rate, even when they can, the relation between 
empirical knowledge and ethical judgments is quite different from 
the one which traditional interest theories seem to imply. 

This can best be seen from an analogy. Let’s return to the ex- 
ample where A and B couldn’t agree on a cinema or a symphony. 
The example differed from an ethical argument in that imperatives 
were used, rather than ethical judgments; but was analogous to 
the extent that each person was endeavoring to modif}? the other’s 
interest. Now^ how would these people argue the case, assuming that 
they were too intelligent just to shout at one another? 

Qearly, they would give “reasons” to support their imperatives.- 
A might say, “But you know*, Garbo is at the Bijou.” His hope is 
that B, who admires Garbo, will acquire a desire to go to the cinema 
when he knows what play will be there. B may counter, ‘"But Tos- 
canini is guest conductor tonight, in an all-Beethoven program.” 
And so on. Each supports his imperative C‘Lefs do so and so”) 
by reasons which may be empirically established. 

To generalize from this: disagreement in interest mav be rooted 
in disagreement in belief. That is to say, people who disagree in 
interest would often cease to do so if they knew the precise nature 
and consequences of the object of their interest. To this extent 
disagreement in interest may be resolved by securing agreement m 
belief, which in turn may be secured empirically. 

This generalization holds for ethics. If A and B. instead of using 
imperatives, had said, respectively, “It would be beirer lo go to the 
cinema,” and “It would be better to go to the svmphonv,” the reasons 
which they would advance would be roughly the same. They would 
each give a more thorough account of the object of interest, with the 
purpose of completing the redirection of interest wffich w^as began 
by the suggestive force of the ethical sentence. On the whole, of 
course, the suggestive force of the ethical statement merely exerts 
enough pressure to start such trains of reasons, since the reasons are 
much more essential in resolving disagreement in interest than the 
persuasive effect of the ethical judgment itself. 

Thus the empirical method is relevant to ethics simply because 
our knowledge of the world is a determining factor to our interests. 
But note that empirical facts are not inductive grounds from w^hich 


Jke Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [ 279 ] 

* iJie etMcal jiidgment problematically follows. (This is what traditional 
interest theories imply.) If someone said ‘‘Qose the door,” and added 
the reason ‘"We’ll catch cold,” the latter would scarcely be called 
an inductive ground of the former. Now imperatives are related to 

• the reasons which support them in the same way that ethical judg- 
"ments are related to reasons. 

Is the empirical method sufficient for attaining ethical agree- 
\iiient? Qearly not. For empmcal knowledge resolves disagreement 
in interest only to the extent that such disagreement is rooted in 
disagreement in belief. Not all disagreement in interest is of this sort. 
For Instance: A is of a sympathetic nature, and B isn’t. They are 
arguing about whether a public dole would be good. Suppose that they 
discovered all the consequences of the dole. Isn’t it possible, even 
so, that A will say that it’s good, and B that it’s bad? The disagree- 
ment in interest may arise not from limited factual knowledge, but 
simply from A’s sympathy and B’s coldness. Or again, suppose, in 
the above argument, that A was poor and unemployed, and that 
B was rich. Here again the disagreement might not be due to different 
factual knowledge. It would be due to the different social positions 
of the men, together with their predominant self-interest. 

When ethical disagreement is not rooted in disagreement in belief, 
is there any method by which it may be settled? If one means by 
“method” a rational method, then there is no method. But in any 
case there is a “way.” Let’s consider the above example, again, 
where disagreement was due to A’s sympathy and B’s coldness. 
Must they end by saying, “Well, it’s just a matter of our having 
different temperaments”? Not necessarUy. A, for instance, may try 
to change the temperament of his opponent. He may pour out his 
enthusiasms in such a moving way — present the sufferings of the 
poor with such appeal — ^that he will lead his opponent to see life 
through different eyes. He may build up, by the contagion of his 
feelings, an inffuence which will modif}^ B’s temperament, and 
create in him a sympathy for the poor which didn’t previously exist. 
This is often the only way to obtain ethical agreement, if there is 
any way at aU. It is persuasive, not empirical or rational; but that 
is no reason for neglecting it. There is no reason to scorn it, either, 
for it is only by such means that our personalities are able to grow, 
through our contact with others. 

The point I wish to stress, however, is simply that the empirical 
method is instrumental to ethical agreement only to the extent that 
disagreement in interest is rooted in disagreement in belief. There 
is Httle reason to believe that ail disagreement is of this sort. Hence 



And now, have I really pointed out the ^‘vital” sense of “good’’? 
suppose that many will still say “No,” ciaimins that I have 
simply failed to set down enough requirements which this sense must 
meet, ana that my analysis, like all others given in terms of interest, 
is a way of begging the issue. They will say: “When we ask Is X 
good? we don’t want mere influence, mere advice. W^e decid- 
edly don’t want to be influenced through persuasion, nor are 
we fully content when the influence is supported by a wide scientific 
knowledge of X. The answer to our question will, of course, modify 
our interests. But this is only because an unique sort of iruth will be 
revealed to us — a truth v/hich must be apprehended a priori. We 
want our interests to be guided by this truth, and nothing else, 
io substitute for such a truth mere emotive meaninc and suasesiion 
is to conceal from us the very object of our search.’* 

I can only answer that I do not understand. What is this truth 
to be about? For I recollect no Platonic Idea, nor do I know what to 
try to recollect. I find no indefinable property, nor do I know’ w^hat 
to look for. And the “self-evident” deliverances of reason, which so 
many philosophers have claimed, seem, on examination, to be de- 
liverances of their respective reasons only (if of anvone’s) and not 
of mine. 

I strongly suspect, indeed, that any sense of “good” which is 


t I C. L. STEVENSON 

&e empirical method is not sufficient for ethics. In any case, ethics 
is not psychologjq since psychology doesn’t endeavor to direct our 
mterests;^ it discovers facts about the ways in which interests are or 
can be directed, but that’s quite another matter. 

To summarize this section: my analysis of ethical judgments 
meets the three requirements for the “vital” sense of “good” that 
were mentioned in section 1. The traditional interest theories fail to 
meet these requirements simply because they neglect emotive mean- 
ing. This neglect leads them to neglect dynamic usage, and the sort 
of disagreement that results from such usage, together with the 
method of resohnng the disagreement. I may add that my analysis 
amwers Moore’s objection about the open question. Wliatever 
scientifically knowable properties a thing may have, it is alw’ays 
open to question whether a thing having these (enumerated) qualities 
is good. For to ask whether it is good is to ask for influence. And 
whatever I may know about an object, I can still ask, quire pertinently, 
to be influenced with regard to my interest in it. ' 


Tlie Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms [ 

' expected both to unite itself in synthetic a priori fashion with other 
■ concepts, and to influence interests as well, is really a great confusion. 
I extract from this meaning the power of influence alone, which I 
find the only intelligibie part. If the rest is confusion, however, then 
it certainly deserves more than the shrug of one’s shoulders. What 
I should like to do is to account for the confusion — ^to examine the 
psychological needs which have given rise to it, and to show how 
these needs may be satisfied in another way. This is the problem, if 
confusion is to be stopped at its source. But it is an enormous prob- 
lem, and my reflections on it, which are at present worked out only 
roughly, must be reserved until some later time. 

I may add that if ‘‘X is good” is essentially a vehicle for sugges- 
tion, it is scarcely a statement which philosophers, any more than 
many other men, are called upon to make. To the extent that ethics 
predicates the ethical terms of anything, rather than explains their 
meaning, it ceases to be a reflective study. Ethical statements are 
social instruments. They are used in a co-operative enterprise in 
which we are mutually adjusting ourselves to the interests of others. 
Philosophers have a part in this, as do all men, but not the major part. 



Sociology and Physicalism 


(translated 


BY OTTO NEURATH 

BY MORTON MAGNUS AND RALPH RAICO) 


I. Physicalism: A Non-metaphysical Standpoint 

WittgensKto and 

World-Outlook (Wei?^ffaJ ^ Dissemination of the Scientific 
will be fr^ToJ^JS^iZTfJ 
in all fields by meS? S W., 

to speak of a i misleadiaa 

temTwhich does ^ 

world-outlook (Weltauffassuncrl tc science, and smce 

(Weltanschauun<^l coniused with world-view 

meat that ‘^Sont^ 

sciencp QOwS not exist as a discipline, alon<^side 

viruT 1 f ™ meaningful statements 

thafr chSer " f ^'P » ”»«■ 

emphasized. Unified science is thf. ”°t “always been sufficiently 
collective labor-^ th- ^L I of comprehensive 

heolosy biolo^w or pv^n ti, structure of chemistn.-, 

TT -i: ^'^en mathematics and io«ic 

dM„'?'4““rh.va‘h’” •»« in- 

witfaout a school” will have^no mo^^^ hitherto. Thus, the “thinker 

P»po^nhovaao„ Must be » foSSt? rri“be egpIS' 

me KrirtS2'(tSSi% •PKwta la Vol- 
™. of Mr., Mrt.'N.w.i L ;SorC«'cS,;“ ■*' 


^'Sodology and Fhysicdism [ 283 ] 

to gain iiaiversal acceptance. Only through the cooperative effort of 
many thinkers do all its implications become clear. If it is false or 
meaningless, i.e., metaphysical, then, of course, it falls outside the 
range of uihfied science. Unified science, alongside of which there 
exists no ‘‘philosophy” or “metaphysics,” is not the achievement of 
isolated individuals, but of a generation. 

Some representatives, of the “Vienna Circle” who, like all their 
colleagues in this group, explicitly declare that there are no peculiarly 
“philosophic truths,” nevertheless still occasionally employ the word 
“philosophy.” By this they mean to designate “philosophizing,” the 
“operation whereby concepts are clarified.” This concession to 
traditional linguistic usage, though understandable for a number of 
reasons, easily gives rise to misconceptions. In the present exposition 
the term is not employed. We are not here seeking to oppose a new 
“Weltanschauung” to an old one, or to improve on an old one by 
the clarification of concepts. The opposition, rather, is between ail 
world-views and science w^hich is “free of any world-view,” In the 
opinion of the “Vienna Circle,” the traditional edifice of metaphysics 
and other constructions of a similar nature, consist, insofar as they 
do not “accidentally” contain scientific statements, of meaningless 
sentences. But the objection to the expression, “philosophizing,” is 
not merely a terminological one; the “clarification of the meaning of 
concepts” cannot be separated from the “scientific method,” to 
which it belongs. The two are inextricably intertwined. 

The contributions to unified science are closely interrelated, 
whether it be a question of thinking out the implications of new 
astronomical observation-statements, or of inquiring into the chemical 
laws which are applicable to certain digestive processes, or of re- 
examining the concepts of various branches of science in order to 
find out the degree to which they are already capable of being con- 
nected with one another, in tlie way that unified science demands. 
That is to say, every law in unified science must be capable of being 
connected, under given conditions, with every other law, in order 
to reach new formulations. 

It is, of course, possible to delimit different kinds of laws from 
one another, as for instance, chemical, biological or sociologicaL 
But one may not assert that the prediction of a concrete individual 
event depends solely on laws of one of these kinds. Whether, for 
example, the burning down of a forest at a certain spot on the earth 
will proceed in a certain way depends just as much on the weather 
as on whether or not human beings will undertake certain measures. 
These measures, however, can only be predicted if the laws of human 



r 284 1 

; OTTO NEURATH 

behavior axe known. That is to say, all types of laws must, under 
Siven conditions, be capable of being connected with one another 
^ laws, whether chemical, climatological or sociological, must, 
therefore, be conceived of as constituents of a system, viz., of unified 
science. 

construction of unified science a unified language 
_( Einheitsprache")\ with its unified syntax, is required. To the 
imperfections of syntax in the period preparatory to unified science 
one may trace the respective positions of particular schools and ages. 

Wittgenstem and other proponents of the scientific world-outlook 
who deserve great credit for their rejection of metaphysics, i.e. for 
the eh^ation of meaningless statements, are of the opinion that 
every individual, m order to arrive at scientific knowledge, has 
meaningless word-sequences for “elucidation” 
(Wiitgenstsm, j ractatus 6. 54): “My propositions are elucidato.n' 
m this way: he who understands me finally recognizes them as 
-nseles^^when he has climbed out through them, on them, over 
speak, throw away the ladder after he has 
^hmbed up on it.) This sentence seems to suggest that one must 
as It were undergo repeated purgations of meaningless, i.e., meta- 
physic^ statements, that one must repeatedly make use of and then 
Jscard^tnis ladder. Only with the help of elucidations, consisting 
vha^ are later recog^ed to be mere meaningless sequences of 
woras, IS one aple to arrive at the unified language of science. ITiese 
e ucidations, which may, indeed, be pronounced metaphysical, do 
not, however, appear in isolation in Wittgenstein’s writings: we find 
there further expressions which resemble less the rungs df a ladder 
parts or an unobtrusively formulated subsidiary metaphysical 
doctnne. The conclusion of the Traciatus, “Whereof one cannot 
speak, tnereof one must be silent,” is, at least grammaticallv, mis- 
Lading. It sounds as if there were a “something” of which one could 
not sf^ak. We should rather say: if one really wishes to avoid the 
metaphysical attitude entirely, then one will “be silent " but not 
about something.” 

We have no need of any metaphysical ladder of elucidation. We 

matter, although his great signifi- 
cance for logic is not, for that reason, to be less highly valued. We 
owe him among other things, the distinction between "“tautologies” 
md statements about empirical events.” Logic and mathematics 
show us w hat linguistic transformations are possible rviihout any 


Sociology and Fhysicdism [ 285 ] 

extension of meaning, independently of the way in wMch we choose 
to fonniilate the facts. 

Logic and mathematics do not require any observation state- 
ments to complete their structures. Logical and mathematical errors 
can be eliminated without recourse to any outside field. This is not 
contradicted by the fact that empirical statements may be the occasion 
for such corrections. Let us suppose that a captain sails his ship on 
to a reef. AU the rules of calculation have been correctly applied, and 
the reef is to be found on the maps. In this way an error in the 
logarithm tables, which was responsible for the misfortune, could be 
discovered, but it also could be discovered independently of such 
an experience. 

In his “elucidations,” which may also be characterized as “mytho- 
logical introductor}^ remarks,” Wittgenstein seems to be attempting 
to investigate, as it were, a pre-linguistic state from the point of view 
of a pre-linguistic stage of development. These attempts must not 
only be rejected as meaningless; they are also not required as a 
preliminary step towards unified science. One part of language can, 
to be sure, be used to discuss other parts; but one cannot make 
pronouncements concerning language as a whole from a “not yet 
liaguistic” standpoint, as Wittgenstein and certain representatives of 
the “Vienna Circle” seek to do. A part of these endeavors, although 
in a modified form, may be suitably incorporated into scientific 
work. The rest would have to be discarded. 

Nor may language as a whole be set against “experience as a 
whole,” “the world,” or “the given.” Thus, every’ statement of the 
kind, “The vtiy possibility of science depends on the fact of order 
in the universe,” is meaningless. Such statements cannot be salvaged 
by counting them as “elucidations,” to which a somewhat less rigorous 
criterion applies. There is little difference between such an attempt 
and metaphysics in the conventional sense. The possibility of science 
is demonstrated by the existence of science. We e.xtend its domain by 
augmenting the body of scientific propositions, by comparing new 
propositions with the legacy of past scientists, and thus creating a 
self-consistent system of unified science capable of being utilized for 
successful prediction, Wt cannot as deponents stand aside, as it were, 
from our depositions and serve simultaneously as plaintiff, defendant 
and judge. 

That science keeps within the domain of propositions, that 
propositions are its starting point and terminus, is often conceded 
even by metaphysicians, of course with the rider that besides science 
there exists yet another domain, containing statements which are 


( 286 ] 

?o“S”^ 1^“% -£ — s 

Unified science formulates statements corrects , 

predictions. But it cannot flnt5r-;r,ot» v ’ and makes 

even as a fiStS concS W^ ^ t^g 

ing today with the spacJ-'tiTe svstem wSrthtf 
responds, and thus achieve sucrp^^J ^ ^ ptiysics cor- 

statements is that of unified science system of 

may be designated phvsicalistr « If ’thi^ t 

iished, then it would i ldvIShle i should become estab- 

one has in mind sStiStTrn “physicahstic” when 

of contempS^ai^- ^IS^To^rfl framed in the spirit 

“physical” would then be reserved ^description. The term 

narrower sense,” e « for those nf k Pirysical statement in the 
Ignoring aU meanfo^ss stilnt «=■ 

given historical S proTeSs W Proper to a 

blending them into a <iQF^nnc’ Proposition to proposition, 

for sucSess,.“ 


II. The Unified Language of Physicalism 


vrithoS®e1«5oTrf 

not statements, but mer-li °°5 another. Laws are 

statements to prediction. (Schiick? from observation 

common to the Snd^2?Se^eS'^?de™f language, 

"intersensual” and “intersubiective Clearing. It is 

asserts today with what he'^ ^ a ^^nccts what the soliloquizer 
makes when hL elrs ^ cW? statements he 

thorn. Tie oSy S“ss SS “P™ 

present even in a Uforse cSe P something 

sensual" lanie teLs 1 '"f subjective" or “intert 

tween," etc.nhat1s ™ n \°° <“”™ < 0 ." “be- 

— ' - ’ “• PP "‘“sh E eipressed in the symbol 

3 O 'o«r5 ^irklichkeit, 1931. 

J. Cf. Otto Neurath, Empirische Soziologie. p. 2. 


:'r''-SodaI^>gy md Pkysicdism [ 287 ] 

"'scqiieaces of logic and mathematics. It is in this langisage that all 
'■‘■predictions are formulated. 

The unified language of unified science, which is derivable by 
" ''."'and large from modifications of the language of eyeryday life, is 
the language of physics. In this connection, it is a matter of indiffer- 
ence for the uniformity of the language of physicalism what particular 
language the physics of a given period may use. It is of no significance 
whether it explicitly employs a four-dimensional continuum in its 
more hi^y refined formulations, whether it recognizes a spatio- 
temporal order of such a t}^ that the locus of every event is pre- 
cisely determined, or whether couplings of placer and velocity- 
dispersions, whose precision is limited in principle, figure as basic 
elements. It is essential only that the concepts of unified science, 
both where they are thought out in the most subtle detail and where 
the description remains imprecise, be made to share the current fate 
of fundamental physical concepts. It is precisely in this that the point 
of view of physicalism is expressed. But all predictions, in whose 
confirmation or rejection we see the measure of science, are reducible 
to observation-statements, to statements mvolving percipient in- 
dividuals and objects emitting stimuli. 

The belief that wath the abandonment, as in modem physics, of 
the ideal of complete precision, the more or less complex relations 
which this yields proride a less intelligible picture thin we should 
obtain by the introduction of h}pothetical electron paths is probably 
due to our persistence in certain habitual w^ays of thinking.^ 

The unified language of physicalism confronts us wherever we 
make a scientific prediction on the basis of laws, ^r^nen someone 
says that if he sees a certain color he will hear a certain sound, or 
vice versa, or when he speaks of the “red patch” next to the ‘'blue 
patch,” which will appear under certain conditions, he is already 
operating within the frame w'ork of physicalism. As a percipient he 
is a physical stmciure: he must iocalke perception, e.g., in the cen- 
; tral nervous system or in some other place. Only in this way can he 
I make predictions and reach agreement with others and with himself 
I at different times. Ever\^ temporal designation is already a physical 
formulation. 

; Science endeavors to transform the statements of everyday life. 

I They axe presented to us as “agglomerations,” consisting of physical- 
I istic and pre-physicalistic components. We replace them by the “uni- 
fication” of physicalistic language. If one says, for instance, “the 

! ^ 4. Cf. Concerning this, Philipp Frank, *'Der Charaktei der heutigen physikal- 

; ischen Theorien,” Scientia, March 1931. 



[ 288 ] OTTO NEURATH 

screeching saw cuts through the blue wooden cube,” ‘‘cube” is 
obviously an “intersensual” and “intersubjective” concept, equally 
available for the blind and the deaf. If a man soliloquizes and makes 
predictions, which he can himself control, he is able to compare 
what he said of the cube when he saw it with what he communicates 
in the dark when he touches it. 

With the word “blue,” on the other hand, there is, at first, a 
doubt as to how it is to be incorporated into the unified language. 
It can be used in the sense of the rate of vibration of electromagnetic 
waves. But it can also be used in the sense of a “field statement,” 
meaning: when a seeing man (defined in a certain way) enters, as 
a test body, the range of this cube, he behaves in a certain manner, 
describable physicalisticaily; e.g., he says, “I see ‘blue.’ ” While 
there may be doubt as to what people mean when they use “blue” 
in colloquial speech, “screeching” would be chiefly intended as a 
“field statement,” i.e., as an expression in which the auditor is al- 
w’ays included. Closer consideration, however, reveals that “cube,” 
“blue” and “screeching” are all words of the same type. 

Let us attempt to follow up our analysis by giving a more exact 
rendering of the above sentence, in accordance with physicaiism, 
and reformulating it in a way that will make it more suitable for 
prediction. 

“Here is a blue cube.” (This formulation, like those which foi- 
lov/, may be restated as a physical formula, in which the locus is 
determined by means of coordinates.) 

“Here is a screeching saw.” (The screeching enters into the 
formulation, at first, only as vibrations of the saw and the air, 
which could be expressed in physical formulae.) 

“Here is a percipient man.” (Possibly a “field statement” could 
be added indicating that under certain conditions the percipient en- 
ters into a relationship with the physical blue and the physical 
screeching.) 

This perceiving may perhaps be divided into: 

“Neural changes are occurring here.” 

“Cerebral changes are occurring here in the perception area 
and, perhaps, in the speech area also.” (It is immaterial for our 
purposes whether these areas can be defined locationaliy or whether 
they have to be defined structurally. Neither is it necessary to dis- 
cuss whether changes in the speech area — the “speech-thought” of 
the behaviorists — are connected with the larynx or laryngeal inner- 
vation.) 

Perhaps, in order to exhaust the physicaUstic meaning of this 


'^^^dogy --andThysicaMsm [ 289 ] 

seBtence, some£Miig more has still to be added, e.g., parties- 
^iars coHcerniBg time, or positional coordinates; but the essential thing 
'is that, in every case, the additions should be statements involving, 
physick concepts. 

^ It would be a mistake to suppose, because physical formulae 
bf a very complex nature, which are still not fully at our disposal, 
^ required for the computation of certain correlations, that, there- 
fore, the physicalistic expressions of everyday life must also be 
complex. Physicalistic everyday language will arise from existing 
common speech, only parts of which will have to be discarded; others 
will be integrated, while supplements will make up for certain defi- 
ciencies. The occurrence of a perception will be, from the outset 
more closely connected than hitherto with the observ^ation statement 
and with the identification of the object. The analysis of certain 
groups of statements, e.g., observation staiemenis, will proceed in 
a different manner from before. 


Children are capable of learning physicalistic every-day lan- 
^age. They are able to advance to the rigorous symbolic language 
of science and learn how to make successful predictions of all kinds, 
without having to resort to “elucidations” supposedly functioning 
as a meaningless introduction. It is a question of a more lucid mode 
of speech, so formulated as to omit such expressions, for instance 
as “illusion of the senses,” which create so much confusion. But 
even though the physicalistic language has the capacity some day 
to become the universal language of social intercourse, we must 
continue to devote ourselves, for the present, to cutting away the 
metaphysical appendages from the “agglomerations” of our lan- 
guage and to defining physicalisticaliy ever\ihing that remains. 
When the metaphysical cord is no longer present, much of what is 
left may present itself as disconnected heaps. The further use of 
such remnants would not be profitable, and a reconstruction would 
be indispensable. 

I We can often continue to make use of available “agglomerations” 
by reinterpreting them. But caution is required here: men who are 
ready enough to adjust their views, but at the same time comfort- 
loving, frequently console themselves with the belief that a great 
deal can be “systematically” reinterpreted. It is more than question- 
able whether it would be convenient to continue to employ terms 
like “instinct,” “motive,” “memory,” “world,” etc., attaching to 
them a wholly unusual sense, which one may easily forget when one 
goes on using these terms for the sake of peace. Certainly there are 
^any cases in which a reconstruction of language is superfluous, or 



[ 290 ] OTTO NEimXH 

even dangerous. So long as one expresses oneself “approximately/" 
one must guard against the desire to be, at the same time, excessively 
subtle. 

Since the views presented here are most nearly similar to the 
ideas of Carnap, let it be emphasized that they exclude the special 
“phenomenal” language from which Carnap seeks to derive the 
physical language. The elimination of the “phenomenal” language, 
which does not even seem to be usable for “prediction” — the essence 
of science — ^in the form it has assumed up to now, will probably 
necessitate many modifications in his system of concept construction.’®' 
In the same way, we must exclude “methodological solipsism” (Car- 
nap, Driesch), which seems to be an attenuated residue of idealistic 
metaphysics, a position from which Carnap himself constantly at- 
tempts to get away. The thesis of “methodological solipsism,” as 
even Carnap would probably concede, cannot be scientifically for- 
mulated. Nor can it be used to indicate a particular standpoint, 
which would be an alternative to some other standpoint, because 
there exists only one physicalism, and everything susceptible of sci- 
entific formulation is contained in it. 

There can be no contrasting of the “ego” or the “thinking per- 
sonality,” or anything else with “experience,” “what is experienced,” 
or “thought.” The statements of physicalism are based on statements 
connected vdth seeing, hearing, feeling and other “sense perceptions” 
(as physical events), but also with “organic perceptions,” which, 
for the most part, are only roughly noted. We can, of course, close 
our eyes, but we cannot stop the process of digestion, the circulation 
of the blood, or the occurrence of muscular inneiv^ations. What 
people are at pains to separate off as “the ego” are, in the language 
of physicalism, events of this sort also, of which we are not informed 
through our ordinary “external” senses. All “personality co-efficients” 
which separate one individual from another are of a physicaiistic 
kind! 

Although the “ego” cannot be set off against either the “world 
or “thinking,” one is able, without abandoning physicalism, to 
distinguish statements about the “physicalistically described person,” 
besides those concerning the “physicalistically described cube,” and 
can, under certain conditions, make “observation statements,” thereby 
creating a substitute for the “phenomenal language.” But careful 
investigation will show that the mass of observation statements is 
contained in the mass of physical statements. 


* [This is a reference to the “Konstitutionssystem” elaborated by Carnap in his 
book Der Logische Aufbau der Welt, Vide the Introduction p. 24. Ed.I 


: §adohgy and Physicalism { 291 ] 

- The protocol statements of an astronomer or a chronicler (ap- 
'peanng as physical formulations) will, of course, be distinguished 
from statements having a precisely determined position in the con- 
'■ text of a physical system, despite the fact that between the two there 
"are fiuid transitional stages. But there is no special “phenomenal” 
as opposed to physicalistic language. Every one of our statements 
■' Cm, from the very outset, be a physicalistic one — and it is this that 
distinguishes what is said here from all the pronouncements of the 
'^Vienna Circle/' which otherwise constantly stresses the importance 
of predictions and their verification. Unified language is the language 
of predictions, which are the very heart of physicalism. 

In a certain sense, the doctrine here proposed proceeds from 
a given condition of everyday language, which in the beginning is 
essentially physicalistic, and, in the usual course of events, is grad- 
ually developed in a metaphysical direction. Tnis forms a point of 
contact with the “natural concept of the world” (“Nattirlicher 
Weltbegriff”) in Avenarius. The language of physicalism is, sc to 
speak, in no way new; it is the language familiar to certain “naive” 
chfidren and peoples. 

It is always science as a system of statements which is at issue. 
Statements are compared with statements, not with “experiences,” 
“the world,” or anything else. All these meaningless duplications 
belong to a more or less refined metaphysics and are, for that reason, 
to be rejected. Each new statement is compared with the totality 
of existing statements previously coordinated. To say that a state- 
ment is correct, therefore, means that it can be incorporated in this 
totality. What cannot be incorporated is rejected as incorrect. The 
alternative to rejection of the new^ statement is, in general, one 
accepted only with great reluctance: the whole previous system of 
statements can be modified up to the point where it becomes possible 
to incorporate the new statement. Within unified science there is 
important work to be done in making transformations. The defini- 
tion of “correct” and “incorrect” proposed here departs from that 
customary among the “Vienna Circle,” which appeals to “meaning” 
and “verification.” In our presentation we confine ourselves always 
to the sphere of linguistic thought. Systems of statements are subjected 
to transformation. Generalizing statements, how^ever, as well as 
statements elaborated by means of determinate relations, can be 
compared with the totality^ of protocol statements. 

Unified science thus comprehends a variety’ of types of state- 
ments. So, for example, whether one is dealing with “statements about 
^ality,” “hallucination statements,” or “untruths” depends on the 



[ 292 J 

degree to which one can otto neuratm 

si—sisfiSsSss 

perception centers; the latter evenfc ^ ‘^°^esponding events in the 
for a hailucination If heqidt-c other hand essent* i 

OBC can also infer,- P-epdoVcenSf 

_ y> then one is dealing with “statp ^P^^^^ed, events outside the' 
case, we can continue tn » i statements about realitv ” Tn tl- 
f fitting i. f S fe 

IS always compared with annrL^^l statement. A statement 

statements, never with a “realitv ” or wth the system of 

S?id b? ‘S’th : ‘‘^e’^Sr/Jof h^ 

fom Tc^ouJ? Physicaiism 

physics, that is rS, ofVe'u''^^"^ S^sfSf 

Many of the problems of the theo^^^fT^ meaningless piiras“= 
rausformed into empirical ouesfiri ^ knowledge wili, perhaps C 
accommodated in uSfied sSr ^ £y cS b1 

Of how S' “StemSS “c'an ^e question 

Pnysicaiistic constructioS “Two “ ohysicSs^ S 

s^r “ <-X- u?f u? 

“Tf A kTu ^“Oimands connected with nJi o^ bv a 

If A behaves in such and sSh a wav 5 statements, e . 

f’n,. . second. When tautoiories ar» statement is equivalew 

‘■aintiug nachine" s„l “perimentaliy with , 0 , j . 

could te fomSS ‘aidT“'1' ®-'' means of thi*: 
“tS^-*^' machine would not even^^ °w automaticahy 

two times red is hard.” ^hle to write the sentence 

orientariom best combined with a he^ ■■ ■’ ' 


\Soci€fi0sy and Fhysicalism 

: traced back to a past speech-thou<^ht or ^ ^ 

are only now evoking a reaction in speecb-tWhr-^'’^’”T^ 
of no essential importance. AU too often th7 h regard, 

as if the refutation of some minor assertir^ discussion is conducted 
somehow shaken the fu^JaSi behaviorists had 
statements have a meaning i e can^hpn ^ physicalistic 

There are no “elucidations” whiS are statements. 

If someone wished to conceive of °i P^y®*=^sbc statements. 
U,». like wtetfa and carS'aL 

analysis. The physicalistic lanmiage^ilS^ °° ^°Sical 

and Omega of all science. Thefe’ ^Pba 

teside the “physical language ” no language” 

side some other possible positioiT no sohpsism” be- 

knowledge,” no new “Weltanschaunn° » P^?f0P^^y> no “theoiy of 
only Unified Science, with its aS prSSiot " 


HI. Sociology No “Moral Science” 


just as h dSrSSthat^ftSSs^^r^ tbe behavior of machines 
us about that of plants. SoL offts comnl 
analyze even today, while the anaiw • statements we could 

Here are .la^- S Ve 'raporarily elades 

The .laws" of machines an red°c.?,f “f ““ “f"’ 

m this sphere, a law in terms of But even 

often suffices, without recourse to measurement 

s^e way, the laws of the animal ho? ®^^®onts. In the 

there is no need to fall back on • often so formulated that 

-here much has been Lr ftoTfh 

structural laws, they have SfJn 2 ^ ^ investigation of macri 
^ylarife mmaj ° «"h°n 

Wn1 'i ‘£sc"7““^r 

todamental diSere'La I* mSkes no 

tons are involved. No mrnter wSlh f descrip- 

s atispcal behavior of atomf investigatins the 

P%ed in establishing corrS2?ns ? °^^fhods em! 

afiove, all the law^of nntn ? ® same. As v/e s2 

connected with one another ?f th21'^ ^ 

serving, as often as possible to2 ^be task of 

groups of events. ’ individual events or certain 




f i OTTO NEURATH 

^ This does away, at the outset, with any fundamental division of 
i^ed science, for instance, into the “natural sciences” and the 
“moral sciences,” the latter being often referred to also in other 
ways, e.g., “Kidturwissenschaften” (“sciences of culture”). The 
theses by which it is intended to establish this division vary, but are 
always of a metaphysical character, that is, meaningless. It is sense- 
less to speak of different “essences” reposing “behind” events. 
What cannot be expressed in terms of relations among elements 
cannot be expressed at aU. It is consequently meaningless to go 
beyond correlations and speak of the “essence of things.” Once it is 
understood what the unified language of science really means, there 
will be no more tdk of “different kinds of causality.” One can only 
compare the organization of one field and its laws with the organiza- 
tion of another, and ascertain, perhaps, that the laws in one field 
are more complex than those in another, or that certain modes of 
orgai^ation lacking in one are found in another; that, for example, 
certain mathematical formulae are required in one case but not in 
the other. 

. ^ sciences” cannot be delimited from the “moral 

sciences, it is even less p>ossible to make the distinction between the 
philosophy of nature and the “philosophy of the moral sciences.” 
Even leaving aside the fact that the former term is unsuitable because, 
^ mentioned above, it still contains the word “philosophy,” by 
“philosophy of nature” one can only understand a sort of introduc- 
tion to the whole work of unified science. For how should “nature” 
be distinguished from “non-nature”? 

One cannot even adduce the practical exigencies of everyday 
life or of the conduct of scientific investigations as justification for 
this dichotomy. Is the theory of human behavior seriously to be 
opposed to that of the behavior of all other objects? Is it seriously 
intended that the theory of human societies should be fitted into one 
discipline and the theory' of animal societies into another? Are the 
natural sciences to deal with “cattle-breeding,” “slavery” and “war- 
fare among ants, and the moral sciences with these same institutions 
among men? If this is not meant, then the distinction is no sharper 
than thm between different “scientific fields” in the older sense. 

Or is there something to be said, perhaps, for the linguistic usage 
according to which one simply speaks of “moral sciences” whenever 
social sciences” are meant? But, to be consistent, one would have 
to count the theory of animal societies together with the theory of 
human societies as social sciences, and therefore as “moral sciences,” 
an implication from which most people would recoil. And quite 


f ^ Fhyskdism [ 295 ] 

nmJeistaiidably so, for then where would be tli^ great cleavage con- 
' c^ed beMnd all this, the cleavage depending on the maintenance of 

■ the centuries-old theological habit of thought which divides up all 

■ existence ' into at least two departments, e.g., a "‘noble’” and an 
^Ignoble”? The dualism of “natural sciences” and “moral sciences,” 
and the dualism of “philosophy of nature” and “philosophy of cul- 
ture” are, in the last analysis, residues of theology. 

The ancient languages are, on the whole, more physicalistic 
than the modem. They are full of ma^cal elements, to be sure, but 
above all they treat “body” and “soul” as simply two forms of 
jnatter: the soul is a diminutive, shadowy body wMch issues from 
the mouth of the individual at dleath. It is theology which first re- 
places the contrast of “matter-soul” and “matter-body” with that of 
“nos-matter-soul” and “matter-body,” as well as “non-matter-God” 
and “matter-world,” adding a whole hierarchy of subordinate and 
superior entities, natural and supernatural. The opposition of 
“natural” and “supernatural” can be formulated only by means of 
meaningless phrases. These phrases, because they are meaningless, 
do not contradict the statements of unified science; neither are they 
in accord with them. But they are certainly the cause of great con- 
fusion. It is when it is asserted that these expressions are just as 
meaningful as those of science that the trouble starts,® 

What part the mental habit of theological dualism plays in the 
creation of such dichotomies can perhaps be gathered from the fact 
that as soon as one such division is discarded another easily estab- 
lishes itself. The opposition of the “Is” and the “Ought,” which is 
encountered especially among philosophers of law, may be men- 
tioned here. In part, of course, this may be traced to the theological 
opposition of “Ideal” to “Reality,” But the capacity of language for 
fonning nouns facilitates all these- meaningless schemes. One can, 
without violating syntactical rules, as serenely say “the Ought” as 
“the sword.” And then people go on to make statements about this 
“Ought” just as they would about a “sword,” or at least as they 
would about the “Is,” 

The “moral sciences,” the “psychical world,” the world of the 
“categorical imperative,” the realm of Einfiihlung (empathy), the 
reato of Verstehen (“the ‘understanding’ characteristic of the his- 
torian”) — ^these are more or less interpenetrating, often mutually 
substitutable, expressions. Some authors prefer one group of mean- 
ingless phrases, some another, some combine and accumulate them^ 

5. Cf. Hans Haim, Vberfiussige Wesenheiten (Publications of the Verein Ernst 
Mach, Vol. 11). 



[ 296 ] 

un,-i u neurath 

°°^y margmal decorations of science 

ZdTj Zir “Snence the entS 

to of their pronouncements. Even if the practical effect of the 

do^es on which the school of “moral sciences” is based are not 
brt/^ confusion in empirical investigation wrought 
y It IS not exaggerated, stUl, in the systematic establishment of 

'‘““S' “ cl“e'p b1 

take a^Seminerf"® practitioners of unified science to 

cete^ed position against such distinctions; this is not a 
matter for their arbitrary choice. 

over these questions even among anti- 
^ niinded thinkers, it is partly connected with the fact 
that there does not exist sufficient clarity about the subject matter 

wl- discipimes is concurrent with the separation 

has nSf H ^ fields. This detachS 

ISs eslv w“ efiminatsd by behaviorism, which, in 

fiu essaj, w. always unoerstand in the widest sense. Onlv physica!- 

s4em SeTth incorporated ffi'to Is 

S sociologist makes predictions about human groups 

iZluT-T ^ individual riTor 

^ ^ .°“^/PP™P^^^cly be called social behaviorism 

C^r conclusion is as follows: sociology is not, a “moral science” or' 

st^d rUbm?’ “Geisteswissenschaft”) 

‘ n?tnrJ f • opposition to some other sciences, called 

unifie fsSZT ’ behaviorism, sociology is a part of 

IV. Sociology as Social Beh.a.vioris.m 

, in the same terms of men's paintin'’ 

housebuddmg religion, agriculture, poetry. And yet, it is maintained 
agm and again that “understanding” human beings is fundamentaUv 
Qifferent from merely” observing them and determining remilarities 
^ “understanding,” of “empathy” 

clahnS^hv closely connected with that traditionally 

,. . ^ ® sciences.” We find here a resurrection of the 

Principl^already eliminated on a previous 

(experience, 

possess the same empirical character. 

Philosophical literature, especially the literature of the philosophy 
ot history, frequently msists that without “empathy” and “under- 


Physicalism [ 297 ] 

'staacfiiig” it would be impossible to pursue historical studies or 
comprehensively to arrange and describe human actions at all. 

- “ How can we attempt to dispose in general of these obstacles 
from the point of view of physicalism? It must be assumed from the 
■ outset that the persistent asseverations of many sociologists and 
philosophers of history concerning the unavoidability of recourse to 
/Understanding’’ are also aimed at preserving the results of some 
Ycry worthy scientific researches. Here, as so often elsewhere, it 
may be a case of a not easOy disentangled combination of the dual- 
istic habits of mind, originating in theolog}% and the actual procedure 
of science. It will be apparent to anyone familiar with the monism 
of unified science that even statements v>rhich are fully capable of 
formulation in physicalistic terms have been presented in an un- 
physicalistic form. 

Sentences such as “I see a blue table in this room,” and “I feel 
angry” do not lie far apart. The “I” is appropriately replaced by 
some personal name, since all such statements may be applied to 
anyone, and an ‘T-statement,” therefore, must be capable of being 
asserted by someone else. Now we have: “There is a blue table in 
this room,” and “There is anger in this man.” The discussions con- 
cerning “primary” and “secondary” qualities are at an end when it 
is realized that, in the last analysis, all statements about qualities 
are of one type, only tautologies being excluded from the class of 
such statements. Then all statements about qualities become physical- 
istic statements. Besides these, there are tautologies, rules for the 
combination and connection of statements. The propositions of 
geometry can be interpreted as physicalistic statements or as tautolo- 
gies, thereby removing many difficulties. 

What, among other things, is characteristic of the sentence, 
“There is anger in this man”? Its peculiarity is that it is open only to 
inadequate analysis. It is as if someone were able to tell us, “Here is 
a severe storm” without being in a position to state in what manner 
it was composed of lightning, thunder, rain, etc., nor yet whether 
he arrived at his discoveries by means of his eyes, ears or nose. 

When one speaks of anger, organic perceptions are made use 
of. Changes in the intestinal tract, internal secretions, blood pressure 
and muscle contraction are essentially equivalent to changes in the 
eye, ear or nose. In the systematic construction of behaviorism, a 
man’s statement, “I am angry” is incorporated into physicalism not 
only as the reaction of the speaker, but also as the formulation of 
his “organic perceptions.” Just as, from the enunciation of “color 
perceptions,” one can infer physicalistic statements about retinal 



[ 298 ] 

and other events, so from assertions about anger ie 
ateut organic perceptions,” one can derive phvsicalistic 
about “intestinal changes,” “changes in b£,d SS? « ef 4? 
nomena which become known to others often only by means of 4ch 
statements. This may be appended as a suppleminrrfm^^ 
^cussions on ti^ subject, where the fidl value^of statements ab4t 

"0 

requires this experience of “organic 
fterceptions m order to have empathy with another person^ h{« 

pnysica^Uc statements concemmg one’s own bodv in tnoHr,,. 
physicateac statements aboM another's is complei* in 

PoiaS”^i'^°^^’ throu^out makes this sort of “extra- 

such “xtensions mduction leads us constantly to 

m-nts''S4 ?Kf'nt?^® s^e prmciple is involved in making state- 
ments about Ae other side of tne moon on the basis of our exirien'- 
^ncemmg the side which faces us. That is to say, orS^Ju^ 

by h S2i“Sat'4?d P^ysi^stic language if one means no m4e 
persons nn th<a' h inferences about physical events in other 

on^s^^ concerning organic changes in 

on.s own tody. Wnat is involved here, as in so many other cieT 

?oielatif the usual attempt at estabhshiag 

S S “ regard to ^y 

ot th.se .vents leaves, to be sure, much to be desired One would 

come very- close to the actual state of agairs if one were to say that 
±e moral sciences are, above aU, the sciences in which correlatbns 

for inadequately described and 

names are available. 

oathv” concepts of “understanding” and “em- 

everything in them that is usable in a physical- 

4en7s' Thrill .st^ten^ent about order, exactly as in aU 
..ien..s. The alleged distinction between “natural sci4ices” and 

■ Sv" ST’’ “ T“ '« coLmSSseS 

non-^xisMnt. **“ >>“"■ "i* understaneiing as well, is 

formulations are encountered 
Aey are subjected to systematic formulation, physicalistic statements 

tnatnio- ^ matter of mdiference for the position here 

maintamea wnether certain individual theses of Watson’s Pavlov’s 
or others are upheld or rejected. What is essenS °s 'tirody 


md Fhysicaiism [ 299 ] 

physiccdisticaiiy formulated correlations be employed in the descrip- 
tion of living things, whatever may be observed in these things. 

It woxjld be misleading to express this by saying that the distinc- 
tion of “psychical” and “corporeal” no longer existed, but had been 
feplaced by “something neutral.” It is not at all a question of a 
"something,” but simply of correlations of a physicaiistic character. 
Only insufficient analysis can lead anyone to say something like: 
"It cannot yet be .ascertained whether the whole sphere of the 
‘psychical’ really admits of physicaiistic expression. It is, after all, 
possible that here and there another type of formulation is required, 
ie., concepts not physicaiisticaiiy definable.” This is the last remnant 
of belief in a “soul” as a separate form of being. When people have 
observed a running clock and then see it stop, they can easily make 
use of the capacity of language for creating nouns, and pose the 
problem, "‘Where has the 'movement’ gone to?” And after it is 
explained to them that all that can be known about the clock is to 
be discovered through analysis of the relations between its parts 
and the surroundings, a sceptic may still object that, although he 
understands that speculation about the “movement” is pure meta- 
physics, he is stiU doubtful whether, for the solution of certain com- 
plicated problems relating to the operations of clocks, physicaiism 
entirely suffices. 

Without meaning to say that every sociologist must be trained 
in behaviorism, w^e can still demand of him that, if he wishes to 
avoid errors, he must be careful to formulate all his descriptions of 
human behavior in a wholly straightforward physicaiistic fashion. 
Let him not speak of the “spirit of the age” if it is not completely 
clear that he means by it certain verbal combinations, forms of 
worship, modes of architecture, fashions, styles of painting, etc. That 
he undertakes to predict the behavior of men of other ages on the 
basis of his knowledge of his own behavior is wholly legitimate, even 
if sometimes misleading. But “empathy” may not be credited with 
any peculiar magical power transcending ordinary induction. 

With inductions in this or that field, it is always a question of a 
decision. This decision may be characteristic of certain human groups 
or of whole ages, but is not itself logically deducible. Yet induction 
always leads, within the physicaiistic sphere, to meaningful state- 
ments. It must not, for this reason, be confused with the interpolation 
of metaphysical constructions. There are many who concede that 
they formulate metaphysical constructions, i.e., that they insert 
meaningless verbal combinations, but nevertheless will not fully 
appreciate the damage caused by such a procedure. The elimination 



, OTTO NEURATH 

J ote Py'Mosy. as well as to 

of the trances essences. People often expect from the priest 

SSr® """'■‘"“a 'SSfZ“er.t 

statements to the r“aim of rormulated observation- 

S!:nz:“ - 

mundaboat wa ““e° S“ .aZZ'T?””', “i’)' 

given data. This is clear from ^ ^ ' J '' 

follows from X. and Z fohows from y' 5°f '^‘^""^tion: if Y 

from X Even if Y»r,u j ^ ^ ^ follows immediately 

conceptions I arril^ afthe^f 

tions Lverthel^s- <iV,°t ^ Pianetari- orbits, this world of concep- 

Js3is?2£S£5f”" - 

stoSf s^L^Ve^v.^^^^ tf 

possible to take into account hnth™t investigated. It is 

by “external” stimuli and those caSS'S- “ 

“within” Iivin<j things (<- a th» .rh-^v, ° r ^“^^^omous changes 

fi^n toves..ia.e-S disto.Sor„rSil! ZSZ’ S 

6- Otto Neurath, Empirische Souologie, p. 57 . 


- -Sodology and Fhysicalism [ 301 ] 

iiiEtteaced by anything external, as well as the decomposition of a 
chemical compound through the addition of oxygen. Whether analo- 
gies to the disintegration of radium play a role within the human body 
need not be discussed here. 

Sociology does not investigate purely statistical variations in 
animal or, above all, human groups; it is concerned with the connec- 
tions among stimuli occurring between particular individuals. Some- 
times, without analyzing these connections in detail, it can determine 
under certain conditions- the total behavior of groups united by 
common stimuli, and make predictions by means of the laws ob- 
tained. How is “social behaviorism,” unimpeded by metaphysics, 
to be pursued? Just as every other actual science is pursued. Naturally, 
in investigating human beings certain correlations result which are 
not encountered in the study of stars or machines. Social behaviorism 
attains to laws of a definite type peculiar to itself. 

To pursue physicalistic sociology is not to transfer the laws of 
physics to living things and the groups they form, as some have 
considered feasible. It is passible to discover comprehensive socio- 
logical laws, as well as laws for narrower social areas, without 
having recourse to micro-structure, and thus being able to base these 
sociological laws on physical ones. Whatever sociological layvs are 
discovered without the aid of physical laws in the narrower sense are 
not necessarily altered by the addition of a subsequently discovered 
physical substructure. The sociologist is completely imimpeoed in 
his search for laws. The only stipulation is that he must always 
speak, in his predictions, of structures which are given in space 
and time. 

V. Sociological Correlations 

It is as little possible in sociology as in other sciences to state 
at the outset on the basis of purely theoretical considerations what 
correlations can be employed with a prospect of success. But it is 
demonstrable that certain traditional endeavors meet with consistent 
failure, while other methods, adapted to discovering correlations, 
are not at present sufficiently cultivated. 

Of what type, then, are sociological correlations? How does one 
arrive, with a certain degree of reliability, at sociological predictions? 
In order to be able to predict the behavior of a group in a certain 
respect, it is often necessary to be acquainted with the total life of 
the group. Variations in the particular modes of behavior distinguish- 
abie in the totality of events, the construction of machines, the 



t" 

n 


i 


^ - 


m 


li 




I 


[ 302 ] OTTO NEUXATH 

erection of temples, the forms of marriage, are not “autonomously” 
calculabie. They must be regarded as parts of the whole that is 
investigated at any given time. In order to know how the construction 
of temples will change in the future, one must be familiar with the 
methods of production, the form of social organization, and the 
modes of religious behavior in the period which is taken as the 
starting point; one must know the transformation to which all of 
these together are subject. 

Not all events prove equally resistant to being employed in such 
predictions. Given certain conditions, from the mode of production 
of a historical period one can often roughly infer the next phases 
in the development of the mode of production and the form of social 
organization. Then one is in a position to attempt with some success 
to make further predictions about religious l^havior and similar 
matters with the aid of such previous predictions. Experience shows 
that the reverse procedure, on the other hand, meets with failure, 
i.e., it does not seem possible to derive predictions about the mode 
of production from predictions about religious behavior alone. 

But, whether we direct our attention to the methods of production, 
to religious behavior, to the construction of buildings, or to music, 
we are always confronted with events which can be physicalistically 
described. 

Many of the social institutions of an age can be properly accounted 
for only if their distant past is known, w^hile others might, so to 
speak, be devised at any time given the appropriate stimuli. There 
is a certain sense in which the presence of camions acts as a stimulus, 
producing armed turrets b}^ way of reaction. The dress coats of our 
day, on the other hand, do not represent a reaction to dancing, and 
it is only with difficulty that they would be newly devised. But it is 
comprehensible to us that at some time in the past, a man dressed 
in a long-skirted coat became the inventor of the dress coat when 
the skirts of his coat flapped up while he was riding. The coherence 
between established customs is different in the two cases. 

Just as one must be informed about the type of coherence in 
order to be able to make predictions, so one must know whether 
the detachment of a certain institution or segment from a social 
complex is easy or difficult, and whether, in the case of loss, it can 
be replaced. The state, for example, is a highly stable complex whose 
operations are, to a considerable extent, independent of the change- 
over of personnel: even if many judges and soldiers w’^ere to die, 
there would be new ones to take their place. A machine, on the 



F^ysicdism [ 303 ] 

& ■ does not generally replace wheels which have been re- 
:iiioved from it. 

is a wholly physicalistic question to what extent the existence 
-'“of 'specially conditioned individuals, deviating from the norm, assnres 
tie stability of the state structure. The related question of the degree 
to which such significant individuals are replaceable must be treated 
separately. The queen bee assumes a special position in the hive, 
but when a queen bee gets lost, there is the possibility that a new 
om will emerge. There are always, so to speak, latent queens. How 
is this in the case of human society? 

The extent to which predictions about social complexes can be 
made without taking into consideration the fate of certain particularly 
pronainent individuals is entirely a concrete sociological question. 
It is possible to maintain, with good reason, that the creation of 
bourgeois Europe, once the machine system had imparted to the 
modem capitalistic transformation its characteristic hue, w^as pre- 
dictable at the end of the eighteenth century. On the other hand, one 
could hardly have predicted Napoleon’s Russian campaign and the 
burning of Moscow. But it would, perhaps, be valid to say that if 
Napoleon had defeated Russia, the transformation of the social 
order would have proceeded in the same way as it did in fact pro- 
ceed. Even a victorious Napoleon would have had to countenance 
the old feudalism of Central Europe to a certain degree and for a 
certain time, just as, on another occasion, he re-established the 
Catholic Church. 

The extent to which prediction is possible, or relates to particular 
individuals, in no way affects the essence of social behaviorism. The 
movements of a leaf of paper in the wind are equally unpredictable, 
and yet kinematics, climatology and meteoroiog>^ are all highly 
developed sciences. It is no part of the essence of a developed 
science to be capable of predicting every individual event. That the 
fate of a single leaf of paper, say, a breeze-blown thousand dollar 
bill, may especially interest us, is of little concern to scientific investi- 
gation. We need not discuss here whether a chronicle of the “acci- 
dental” paths of leaves in the wind could eventually lead to a theory 
of the paths of leaves. Many of the views associated with Rickert 
and allied thinkers yield no scientific laws even where they can be 
physicalistically interpreted. 

. Sociolo^, like every science, tracks down correlations which 
can be utilized for predictions. It seeks to lay down its basic con- 
oeptions as unambiguously and clearly as possible. One may attempt, 


[ ] OTTO NEURaTH 

for instance, to define groups tlirough ''commercium'' and ‘'con- 
nubtum/^ One ascertains who trades with whom, or who marries 
whom. There may emerge clearly distinguishable areas of concentra- 
tion, together with poorly occupied border areas. And then one 
could investigate the conditions under which such concentrations 
vary or even disappear. To discover the correlation of such areas 
of concentration with the processes of production obtaining at their 
respective periods is obviously a legitimate sociological task, which 
might be of importance for the tfaeoiy of “classes.” 

One can investigate, for instance, under what conditions matri- 
archy, ancestor worship, agriculture and similar institutions arise, 
at what point the founding of cities begins, or what correlations 
exist between systematic theology and other human activities. One 
can also ask how the administration of justice is determined 
by ^ social conditions, although it is questionable whether such 
limited divisions will exhibit sufficient law-like regularities. It 
may well be, for instance, that certain events occurring outside the 
field of law must be added to those involved in the administration 
of justice, if relations statable as laws are to be found. 

one group recognizes as law^, another may regard as outside 
the legal order. Thus, only correlations among men’s statements 
concerning the “law,” or between their behavior and their statements 
can be established. But it is not possible, without special preliminary 
work, to contrast “legal events” as such with other events. 

It IS doubtful whether simple sociological correlations can be 
- :■ determined between the allowed interest rate, on the one hand, and 

i standard of living of a period, on the other: whether simpler 

relations do not appear when the “allowed interest rate” and ‘*pro- 
^^t>ited usury” are taken together. Thus, the modes of behavior on 


w 

■Mk 


ill!' ' 

It 


which unfavorable “legal” and “ethical” judgments are passed could 
be incorporated into sociology, and the judgments themselves could 
be included. These disciplines are in every sense branches of sociolog}’, 
but they are quite different from the “ethics” and “jurispmdence” 
which are commonly cultivated. The latter yield few or no socioiogicai 
correlations. They are predominantly metaphysical, or, where free 
of metaphysics, their methodology and arrangement of statements 
can only be explained as residues of theology. In part, they yield 
purely logical deductions, the extraction of certain injunctions from 
others, or of certain conclusions from given legal assumptions. But 
all this lies outside the sphere of ordered correlations. 





VL Ethics and Jurisprudence as 
Remnants of Metaphysics 

la its origiii, etMcs is the discipline which seeks to determine the 
of divine injunctions. It attempts to find out, by means of a 
togicai combination of commandments and prohibitions of a universal 
kind, whether a given individual act is commanded, permitted or 
forbidden. The “casuistry” of Catholic moral theologians has ex- 
elaborated this type of deduction. It is quite obvious that 
the indeterminateness of divine injunctions and the ambiguity of 
their meaning preclude any genuine scientific method. The great 
expenditure on logical deductions was, so to speak, squandered on 
a worthless object, even though, historically, it prepared the way 
for the coming logicizing period of science. If the God who issues 
the commands, as well as events in heaven and hell (which was 
located by many theologians at the center of the earth) are pfaysicai- 
istically defined, then one is dealing with a non-metaphysical dis- 
cipline, to be sure, but a highly uncritical one. 

But how is a discipline of “ethics” to be defined once God 
is eliminated? Is it possible to pass meaningfully to a “command- 
in-itself,” to the “categorical imperative”? One might just as well 
talk of a “neighbor-in-himself without any neighbors,” or of a 
“son-in-himself, who never had a father or mother.” 

How is one to distinguish certain injunctions or modes of be- 
havior in order to make possible “a new ethics within the context of 
physicalism”? It seems to be impossible. Men can form joint resolu- 
tions and conduct themselves in certain ways, and it is possible to 
study the consequences of such actions. But what modes of behavior, 
what directives is one to distinguish as “ethical,” so that correlations 
may then be set up? 

The retention of an old name is based on the view that there is 
something abiding to be discovered, which is common to the old 
theological or metaphysical and the new empiricist disciplines. When 
all metaphysical elements, as well as whatever physicaiistic theological 
elements it may contain, have been eliminated from ethics, there 
remain only statements about certain modes of human behavior or 
the injunctions directed by some men to others. 

One could, however, also conceive of a discipline pursuing its 
investigations in a wholly behavioristic fashion as part of unified 
science. Such a discipline would seek to determine the reactions 
produced by the stimulus of a certain way of living, and whether such 


and Pkysicalism 


[ 305 ] 



^ 1 OTTO NEUBATH 

ways of living make men more or less happy. It is easy to 
a aoroughly empirical “felicitology” (Felicitologie) , on a behavior- 
istic foundation, which could take the place of traditional ethics. 

But a non-metaphysical ethics usually seeks to analyze, in one 
way or another, men’s “motivations,” as if this provided a suitable 
^oundwork for relations statable as laws. What men assert about 
the ‘reasons” for their conduct, however, is essentially more de- 
pCTdent on contingencies than the general run of their behavior. 
When the general social conditions of a given period are known, the 
behavior of whole ^oups can be far more readhy predicted than the 
rabonale which individuals wiU adduce for their conduct. The modes 
of conduct will be defended in very different fashions, and very few 

moreover, wiU note the correlation between the social situation and 
average conduct. 

These “conflicts of motivations,” for the most part metaphysically 
ormulated, are avoided by an empirical sociology, which is" intent 
upon xruitful work. This is the case with Marxism, the most pro- 
aucbve semiology of the present day. It endeavors to establish mr- 
relations between the social situation and the behavior of entire 
Classes, so that it can then account for the frequently changing verbal 
sequences w^ch ^ supposed to “explain the motivation” of the 
scientifically law-afaidmg actions which are conditioned in this vray. 

Ma^m, m its aescriptions of relations expressible as laws, 
makes as hdle use as possible of what men assert about themselves, 

« consciousness,” their “ideoio©-,” it is related 
to those schools of psychologj^” which accord to the “unconscious” 
prominent role. Thus it is that psychoanalysis 
and indiMdual psychology, by virtue of the fact that they confute and 
f motivational psychology of consciousness (today quite 
oee), prepare the way for modem empirical sociolosi', which 
s^ics, m the spmt of unified science, to discover correlations'between 
actions and the factors that condition them. 

And even if psychoanalysis and individual psychology in their 

fhfr metaphysical expressions, never- 

tii,.less, through their emphasis on the relation between behavior and 
Its unconscious preconditions, they are precursors of the behavior- 
istic^ay of thmkmg ^d of sociological methodology. 

■ ^ permissible to ask whether a certain manner of livin*’ 

happiness, since “happiness” can be described 
whoUy behavionstically; it is valid to ask on what depend the de- 
mands which masses of men make of one another, what new demands 
are set, what modes of behavior will emerge in such a situation. 




and Fhysicalism [ 307 ] 

?'fC3ain^ modes of behavior in this regard are often fimdamentafly 
'"^"divetgCEt) A1 these are legitimate sociological formulations of 
^problems* Whether it is advisable to characterize them as “ethical” 
• ‘i^cd cot be decided here. 

'■ The case of “jurisprudence” is a similar one, when it is iiader- 
' "^ 0 od as something odier than the sociology of certain social phe- 
Domeiia* But when it takes up the task of establishing whether a 
^tem of claims is logically consistent, whether certam conclusions 
of the statute books can be harmonized with certain observation- 
statements about legal practice, we are concerned with purely logical 
investigations. When we determine that the rules of a chemist are 
logically compatibie, we have not yet entered the sphere of the 
science of chemistry. In order to pursue chemistry, we must establish 
correlations between certam chemical events and certain tempera- 
tures, and other such things. The fact that, despite their essentially 
metaphysical preliminary formulations, the representatives of cer- 
tain schools of jurisprudence can produce something logically and 
scientifically significant does not prevent our rejecting these formu- 
lations, as, for example, the following: 


The thinking of mathematical or logical laws is a psychical act, but 
the object of mathematics — that which is thought of — is not something 
psychical, neither a mathematical nor a logical ‘"soul,” but a specific 
intellectual reality. For mathematics and logic abstract from the psy- 
chological fact of the thinking of such an object. In the same way the 
state, as the object of a special mode of thought to be distinguished 
from psychology, is a distinctive reality, but is not the fact of the thinking 
and willing of such an object. It is an ideal order, a specific system of 
norms. It resides not in the realm of nature — the realm of physical- 
psychical relations — but in the realm of spirit. The state as obligating 
authority is a value or — so far as the proposiiional expression of value 
is established — a norm, or system of norms. As such, it is essentially 
difierent from the specifically real fact of the conceiving or wOling of 
the norm, which is characterized by indifi*erence to value.'^ 

Formulations of this type are connected with similar ones on 
“ethics” and related disciplines, without any attempt having been 
made to discover how the term “objective goals” is to be fitted into 
miified science, and without indicating any observation-statements 
through which “objective goals” as such might be determined. Again: 

K the “general theory of the state” asks what the state is and how it is, 
1* e., what its possible basic forms and chief components are, politics 


7. Kelsen, Allgemeine Staaislehre, pp. 14 ff. 



^ OTTO NEUitATH 

“substocture” to another group as “superstructure” (“historica] 
materialism” ^ a social physicalistic theory), it proceeds throush- 
out its operations 'within the confines of social beha'viorism. What k 
mvolved here is no opposition of the “material” to the “spiritual ” 
1. e., of essences” with “different types of causality.” * 

TOe coming decades may be concerned in growing measure with 
the discovery of such correlations. Max Weber’s prodigious attemot 
to demonstrate the emergence of capitaUsm from Calvinism clearly 
shows to how great an extent concrete investigation is obstructed 
by metaphysical fonnulations. To a proponent of social behaviorism 

It seems^ at once quite natural that certain verbal sequences ^the 

formulation of cert^ divine commands— should be recognized as 
dependent on certain modes of production and power situations. 
But It does not seem very plausible that the way of life of vast 
numbers of human beings occupied with trade, industiy and other 
matters, should be determined by verbal sequences of individual 
th^logians, or by the deity'’s injunctions, always very vaguely worded 
which the theologians transmit. And yet Max Weber was committed 
to tlus point of view. He sought to show that from the “spirit of 

Calyimsm was bom the “spirit of capitalism” and with it the 
capitalist order. 

^ A Catholic theologian, Klraus, has pointed out that such an over- 
estimation of the influence of theological formulations can only be 
explained by the fact that he ascribed to spirit a 'Sort of “magical” 
effect. In the work of Weber and other thinkers, “spirit” is regarded 
as very closely bound up with words and formulae. Thus we under- 
assiduous quest for crucial theological formulations 
of individual Calvinists, in which the origins of crucial capitalist 
formulations might be sought. The “rationalism” of one sphere is 
to spnng from that of the other. That theological discourses and 
wnhngs possess such enormous powers is a supposition which would 
be formally possible within a physicalistic system. But experience 
proves otherwise. In company with the Marxists, the Catholic the- 
ologian mentioned above points out the fact that theological subtle- 
ties exercise little influence on human behavior, indeed, that they 
are scanty known to the average merchant or professional man. It 
would be much more plausible to suppose that in England, for 
example, merchants opposed to the royal monopoly, and usurers 
desirmg to take interest at a higher rate than the Church of En g lan d 
peimtted, readily gave their support to a doctrine and a part\^ 
wtech turned against the Church and the crown allied with the 
Church. First the behavior of these men was, to a considerable ex- 



i &^dology ^ Physicalism [ 311 ] 

capitalistically oriented — Ihm they became Calvinists. We should 
expect to find, in accordance with all our experience of theological 
diKlrines at other times, that these doctrines were subsequently re- 
and adapted to the system of production and commerce. And, 
Kraus further shows, in opposition to Weber, that those theological 
formulatioiis which are “compatible” with capitalism did not appear 
; until later, while Calvinism in its ori^al form was related rather 
; to the dogmas of the anti-capitalist Middle Ages. Webers metaphysi'^ 

, cal starting’-point impeded his scientific work, and determined un-- 
■ favorably his selection of observation-statements. But without a 
suitable selection of observation-statements there can be no fruitful 
sdentific work. 

Let us analyze a concrete case in somewhat greater detail. With 
what is the decline of siaveiy^ in the ancient w^orid connected? 

Many have been inciined to the \iew that Christian doctrine and 
the Christian way of life eSected the disappearance of slavery, after 
the Stoic philosophers had impaired the conception of slaver>^ as an 
eternal institution. 

If such an assertion is meant to express a correlation, it is 
natural to consider, in the first place, whether or not Christianity 
and slavery are found together. It is then seen that the most oppressive 
forms of slavery appear at the begiiming of the modem era, at a 
time when Christian states are eveiywhere expanding their power, 
when the Christian Churches are vigorous above ail in the colonies. 
Because of the intervention of Catholic theologians motivated by 
humanitarian considerations, the preser%^ation of the perishing Indian 
slaves of America was undertaken through the importation of sturdier 
Negro slaves brought to that continent in shiploads. 

It would really be necessar}^ to define in advance with a greater 
degree of precision v»^hat is meant, on the one hand, by “Christian,” 
and, on the other, by “slaver\'.” If the attempt is made to formulate 
the correlation between them with greater clariiy, it must be said 
that statements of a cenain type, religious behavior, etc., never 
appear in conjunction with the large-scale ownership of slaves. But 
in this connection, it would be necessary^ to lay down a definite mode 
of application. For a man can be a “slave” from the “juristic” stand- 
point, and, simultaneously, a “master” from the “sociological” point 
of view. Sociological concepts, how^ever, may be linked only with 
other sociological concepts, 

“Christian dogma” is an extraordinarily mdeterminate concept. 
Many theologians have believed it possible to demonstrate, from 
the Bible, that God has condemned the Negroes to siaveiyr: when 



{ ] OTTO NEURATH 

Ham treated his drunken father Noah irreverently, Noah cursed him 
and declared that he and his descendants were to be subject to his 
brothers Shem and Japheth and their descendants. Still other theo- 
logians have sought to discover in Christian doctrine arguments 
against slavery. 

It is evident that the sociologist advances much further when 
he delimits a certain system of men, religious acts, dogmas, etc., 
and then notes whether it comes into being in conjunction with cer- 
tain modes of social behavior. This is, of course, a very rough pro- 
cedure. The attempt must be made to discover not only such simple 
correlations, but also correlations of greater complexity. Laws must 
be combined with one another, in order for it to be possible to 
produce certain predictions. 

Some sociological “laws” are valid only for limited periods, just 
as, in biology, there are laws about ants and about lions in addi- 
tion to more general laws. That is to say, we are not yet in a position 
to state precisely on what certain correlations depend: the phrase 
“historical period” refers to a complicated set of conditions which 
has not been analyzed. Much confusion is due to the opinion of 
some analytical sociologists that the laws which they had discovered 
had to possess the same character as chemical laws, i.e,, that they 
had to hold true under all conceivable earthly condiiions. But sociol- 
og}^ is concerned for the most part w^itb correlations^ valid for limited 
periods of time. Marx was justified in asserting that it is senseless 
to speak of a universal iaw^ of population, as Malthas did. But it is 
possible to state which law of population holds for any given socio- 
logical period. 

When, for the purpose of clarifying the question, “How does the 
decline of slavery come about?” one analyzes the confiici between 
the Northern and Southern States over the freeing of the slaves, 
one is confronted by a conflict between industrial and plantation 
states. The emancipation inflicts serious injury on the plantation 
states. Shouldn’t we expect a connection between the freeing of the 
slaves and the processes of production? How^ is such a notion to be 
made plausible? 

One attempts to determine the conditions under which slavery 
offers the slave-owner advantages, and the conditions under w^hich 
the contrary is the case. If those masters w^ho free their slaves are 
asked why they do so, only a few will say that they oppose slavery 
because it does not yield sufficient advantages. Many will inform 
us, without hypocrisy,, that they have been deeply impressed by 
reading a philosopher who championed the slaves. Others will de- 


ond Physicalism [ 313 ] 

in detail their conflicting motives, v41i perhaps explain that 
slavery would really be more advantageous to them, but that the 
" ‘-•'‘■desire to sacrifice, to renounce property, has led them, after a long 
%7*iliiier* conflict, to the difficult step of freeing their slaves. Anyone 
• ^ ‘ aa:nsto^^^ to operate in the spirit of social behaviorism will, above 
‘ ■ all^ fceep in mind the very complicated ‘'stimulus” of the way of 
" "• - life based on slave-owning, and then proceed to investigate the 
^reaction” — retention or freeing of the slaves. He will employ the 
■-results of this inquiry to determine how far theological doctrines 
concerning the emancipation of slaves are to be recognized as “stim- 
ulus,” how far as “reaction.” 

; ' ' If it is shown that relatively simple correlations can be estab- 

lished between the effects of slaveiy^ on the masters’ tenor of life 
and the behavior of the master toward the liberation of slaves, and 
that, as against this, no simple correlaiions can be laid down between 
the doctrines of the time and the behavior of the slave-owners, 
then preference will be given to the former mode of investigation. 

Thus there wall be examined under various conditions the rela- 
tionship betv/een hunting and slaver}% agricuiiure and slaver\\ manu- 
facture and slavery. It wffil be found, for example, that the possession 
of slaves generally offers no advantage where there are sufficiently 
numerous free workers who eagerly seek employment in order to 
avoid start^ation. Columella, a Roman agrarian writer of the later 
period, bluntly says, for example, that the employment of slaves is 
disadvantageous to anyone who drains fever sw’amps in the Cam- 
pagna: the sickness of a slave means loss of interest, while his 
death results in loss of capital He goes on to say that it is possible, 
on the other hand, to obtain free workers on the market at any 
. time, and that the employer is in no way burdened by their sick- 
ness or death. 

When serious fluctuations in the business situation occur, entre- 
preneurs find it desirable to be in a position to drop free workers; 
slaves, like horses, must continue to be fed. When one reads in 
Strabo, therefore, that in antiquity pap\Tus shrubs in Egypt were 
already being cut dowm in order to maintain the monopoly price, 
one understands that the universal employment of free labor could 
not be far away. 

t-U.y ' - Tho conditions which led to the fluctuating tendencies of early 
k ' economic institutions can likewise be investigated. Cor- 

relation is added to correlation. It is seen that “free labor” and “the 
■r -destruction of commodities” seem to be correlated under certain 
. . conditions. This is equally true of “plantation slavery” and “a con- 



[ 314 ] OTTO neukatb 

slant iii,arket.” One can view the Civil War as a conflict between the 
indestrial North, which was not interested in slaver}^ and the cotton- 
produdng agrarian South, and thereby be able to make extensive 
predictions. 

This does not mean that the religious and ethical opponents 
of slavery were lying when they said that they directly rejoiced in the 
emancipation of the slaves, but not in the increase of industrial 
profits which ensued in the North. That such a desire for the free- 
ing of the slaves could develop at this time and find so rich a satis- 
faction is something which the empirical sociologist could deduce, 
in broad outline, from the total economic situation. 

The methods used in the elaboration of a theory of agricultural 
economics have also been applied by several writers (theologians 
among them) in the construction of a wholly empiiicsd theory of 
the "‘employment of natives,’’ yielding all types of correlations.^ In 
combination with other relations expressible as laws one can make 
all sorts of predictions concerning the fate of slaver}’ in particular 
countries and territories. 

The distribution of grain to freemen but not to slaves, during 
the later history of Rome, offered slave-owners an additional motive 
for freeing their slaves. The former master could then re-employ the 
freedman at a lower cost, and also use his support at elections. It 
is likewise easy to understand how, during the decline of Rome, the 
system of the ‘'coloni” and serfdom emerge through the regression 
of early capitalistic institutions. In order to undertake an enterprise 
with slave labor, one had to have at one’s disposal extensive financial 
resources, since both workers and implements of production had 
to be purchased. Under a regime of free labor, the purchase of 
tools was sufficient. The system of the “coloni” required no invest- 
ment at all from the owner, who was assured of dues of all kinds. 
The “free” workers w^ere forced by the whole social order to labor 
— the death penalty was imposed for idleness — ^while each slave had 
to be disciplined by his own master. The master had to protect the 
health and life of his slave, to care for him just as he had to care 
for a horse or a bullock, even when it was unruly. 

We see how, by means of such analyses, correlations are estab- 
lished between general social conditions and certain modes of be- 
havior of limited human groups. The “statements” which these 
groups make about their own behavior are not essential to these 
correlations; they can often be added with the help of additional 

9. Cl Otto Neurath, “Probleme der Kriegswinschaftslehre,” Zeitschrift fur die 
gesamten Staatswissenschaften, 1914, p. 474. 


: Sociology and Physicdism [ 315 ] 

'^^mflations. It is above aU in MaEtism that empirical sociology is 
pursued in this way.“ 

A system of empirical sociology in the spirit of social behavior- 
'issis as it has been developed above all in the United States and the 
0.S.S.R-, would have to direct its inquiries primarily to the typical 
^reacdons^’ of whole groups. But significant historical movements 
axe also often measured or evaluated without such analysis. And it 
may further be shown that through the development of certain in- 
stitutions, through the increase in a certain magnitude, a reversal is 
produced which causes further changes to take a whoEy different 
direction. The primitive “idea of progress,” that every magnitude in- 
creases indefinitely, is untenable. One must consider the whole sys- 
tem of sociological magnitudes in all its complexity, and then note 
what changes are predictable. One cannot infer from the growth of 
large cities up to the present time that the process will continue 
approximately the same. Rapid growth is especially apt to release 
stimuli leading to a sudden cessation of growth and perhaps to the 
reconstitution of many small centers. The expansion of capitalist 
large-scale industry and the emergence of the proletarian masses 
dependent on those industries can lead to a situation where the whole 
capitalist mechanism moves through a series of economic crises 
towards its ultimate dissolution. 

\1II. Possibilities of Prediction 

It is possible to state the extent to which predictions can be 
successfully made within the sphere of social behaviorism. It is evi- 
dent that its various ''predictions i.e., its scientific theories, are 
sociological events essentially dependent on the social and economic 
order. It is only after this is understood that it becomes cie ar, for 
example, that under certain conditions certain prediciions either do 
not emerge at all, or cannot be elaborated. Even when an individual 
believes that he divines the direction of further successful investiga- 
tion, he can be prevented from finding the collaboration required 
for sociological research by the indifference, or even the opposition, 
of other men. 

The approach of social changes is difficult to notice. In order 
to be able to make predictions about events of a new' type, one must 
usually possess a certain amount of new experiences. It is often the 
changes in the historical process that first give the scientist the 

example, Etiore Ciccotti, Der Untergang der Sklaverei in Altertum 
(German translation by Oda Oiberg), Berlin, 1^10. 


*■ ■* OTTO NEURaTH 

necessa^ data for further investigations. But since sociological in- 
TCStigatioi^ ako play a certain role as stimuli and instruments in 
the organization of living, the development of sociology is very 
closely bound up with social conflicts. Only established schools of 
sociology, requirmg social support, can master, by means of coUective 
labor, the masses of material which must be adapted to a stricter 
formulation of correlations. This presupposes that the powers which 
fmance such work are favorably inclined towards social behaviorism 
This IS in general not the case today. Indeed, there exists in the 
nilmg classes an aversion to social, as well as to individual, behavior- 
ism which is much more than a matter of a scientific doubt, which 
would be comprehensible in view of the imperfections of this doc- 
tnne. The opposition of the ruling circles, which usuaUy find support 
in the umversities of the capitalist countries, is explained sociologi- 
cally, above aU, by the fact that empirical sociology, through its 
non-metaphysical attitude, reveals the meaninglessness of such ex- 
pressions as “categorical imperative,” “divine injunction,” “moral 
Idea, superpersonal state,” etc. In doing this it undermines imnor- 
d^nnes which are useful in the maintenance of the prevailino 
order. The proponents of “unified science” do not defend one worldt 
view arnong other world-views. Hence the question of tolerance 
cannot be raised. They declare transcendental theology to be not 
taise, out meaningless. Without disputing the fact that powerful in- 
spiration and cheering and depressing effects, can be associated with 
meamngiess doctnnes, they can in practice “let seven be a holv 
numter, smce they do not harass the supporters of these doctrines, 
ut they^camot ^ow that these claims have any meaning at all, 
owever i den, i.e., that they can confirm or confute scientific 

emen s. Even if such reasoning by the pure scientist leaves meta- 
physics and theology undisturbed, it doubtlessly shakes the reverence 
lor txiem whicii is frequently demanded. 

i^l the metaphysical entities whose injunctions men endeavored 
to obey, and whose “holy” powers they venerated, disappear. In 
toeir place there stands as an empirical substitute, confined within 
the bounds of purely scientific formulations, the actual behavior of 

operate as empirical forces on individual 
men. That groups of men lend strength to individual men pursuing 
certain modes of action and obstruct others pursuing different modes'^ 
beha^^orism^°^ which is wholly meaningful in the 'context of social 

tehaviorist, too, makes commands, requests and 
reproaches, but he does not suppose that these utterances, when 



- Sociology md Fhysicalism [317] 

-'connected with propositions, can yield a system. Words can be 
employed Eke whistles, caresses and whiplashes; but when used 
' la this w^ay, they can neither agree with nor contradict propositions. 

' An injunction can never be deduced from a system of propositions! 

■ '7 ' This is no “limitation” of the scientific method: it is simply the 
result of logical analysis. That injunctions and predictions are so 
frequently linked follows from the fact that both are directed to 
the future. An injunction is an event which it is assumed wEl evoke 
certain changes in the future: A prediction is a statement which it 
is assumed will agree with a future statement. 

The proponents of “unified science” seek, with the help of laws, 
to formulate predictions in the “unified language of physicaEsm.” 
This takes place in the sphere of empirical sociology through the 
development of “social behaviorism,” In order to attain to more 
useful predictions, one can immediately enminate meaningless verbal 
sequences by the use of logic. But this is not sufficient. There must 
follow the elimination of all false formulations. The representatives 
of modern science, even after they have effected the elimination of 
metaphysical formulations, must stiff dispose of false doctrines, for 
example, astrolog}^ magic, etc. In order to liberate someone from 
such ideas, the universal acknowledgment accorded to the rules of logic 
does not, as with the elimination of meaningless statements, suffice. 
One must, if one wishes to see one’s own theoiw prevail, create the 
groundwork v/hich will lead people to recognize the inadequacy of 
these theories, which, while ''also physicalistic/' are uncritical. 

The fruitfulness of social behaviorism is demonstrated by the 




establishment of new correlations and by the successful predictions 
made on the basis of them. Young people educated in the spirit of 
physicalism and its unified language will be spared many of the 
hindrances to scientific work to v/hich we are still at present sub- 
jected. A single individual cannot create and employ this successful 
language, for it is the product of the labor of a generation. Thus, 
even in the form of social behaviorism, sociolog}- will be able to 
formulate vaUd predictions on a large scale only when a generation 
trained in physicalism sets to work in all departments of science. 
Despite the fact that we can observe metaphysics on the increase, 
there is much to show that non-metaphysical doctrines are also 
spreading and constantly gaining ground as the new “superstructure” 
erected on the changing economic “substructure” of our age.^^ 


11. Cf. Otto Neurath, 
onist, October 1931. 


‘Physicalism, the Philosophy of the Vienna Circle,*’ The 


V j 



Analytical Philosophy 








15 




^ ^-.; 


Philosophy 


BY FRANK P. RAMSEY 


Philosophy must be of some use and we must take it seriously; it 
must clear our thoughts and so our actions. Or else it is a disposition 
we have to check, and an inquiry to see that this is so; i.e. the chief 
proposition of philosophy is that philosophy is nonsense. And again 
we must then take seriously that it is nonsense, and not pretend, 
as Wittgenstein does, that it is important nonsense! 

In philosophy we take the propositions we make in science and 
e^-eiyday life, and try to exhibit them in a logical system with primi- 
tive terms and definitions, etc. Essentially a philosophy is a system 
of definitions or, only too often, a system of descriptions of how 
definitions might be given. 

I do not think it is necessary to say with Moore that the defi- 
nitions explain what we have hitherto meant by our propositions, 
but rather that they show how we intend to use them in future. 
Moore would say they were the same, that philosophy does not 
change what anyone meant by “This is a table.” It seems to me 
that it might; for meaning is mainly potential, and a change might 
therefore only be manifested on rare and critical occasions. Also 
sometimes philosophy should clarify and distinguish notions previ- 
ously vague and confused, and clearly this is meant to fix our future 
meaning oniy.^ But this is clear, that the definitions are to give at 
least our future meaning, and not merely to give any pretty way of 
obtaining a certain structure. 

I used to worry myself about the nature of philosophy through 
excessive scholasticism. I could not see how we could understand 

This extract is taken from Ramsey’s The Foundations of Mathematics, copy- 
1931 by Routiedge and Kegan Paul, London, with whose permission it is here 
rtiainted. 

!• But in so far as our past meaning was not utterly confused, philosophy will 
natur^y give that, too. E.g. that paradigm of philosophy, Russell’s theory of 
descriptions. 




V- -i 




2 


[ 322 ]. FRANK P. RAMSEY 

a word and not be able to recognize wiietiier a proposed definition 
of it was or was not correct. I did not realize tbe vagiieness of the 
whole idea of understanding, the reference it involves to a multitude 
of performances any of which may faM and require to be restored. 
Logic issues in tautoio^es, mathematics in identities, philosophy in 
definitions; all trivial but all part of the vital work of clarifying and 
organmng our thought. 

If we regard philosophy as a system of definitions (and elucida- 
tions of the use of words which cannot be nominaliy defined), the 
things that seem to me problems about it are these: 

( 1 ) What definitions do we feel it up to philosophy to provide, 
and what do we leave to the sciences or feel it unnecessary to give 
at an? 

(2) WTaen and how can we be content v^ithout a definition but 
merely with a description of how a definition might be given? 
[This point is mentioned above.] 

(3) How can pMlosopMcal inquir}* be conducted Vrithout a per- 
petual petitio principii? 

(1) Philosophy is not concerned with special problems of defi- 
nition but only with general ones: it does not propose to define 
particular terms of art or science, but to settle e.g. problems which 
arise in the definition of any such term or in the relation of any 
term in the physical world to the terms of experience/ 

Terms of art and science, however, must be denned, but not 
necessarily nominally; e.g. we define mass by explaining how^ to 
measure it, but this is not a nominal definition; it merely gives the 
term “mass” in a theoretical structure a clear relation to certain ex- 
perimental facts. The terms we do not need to define are those 
which we know we could define if need arose, like “chair,” or those 
which like “clubs” (the suit of cards) we can translate easily into 
visual or some other language, but cannot conveniently expand in 
words. 

(2) The solution to what we called in (1) a “general problem 
of definition” is naturally a description of definitions, from which 
we learn how to form the actual definition in any particular case. 
That we so often seem to get no actual denniiions, is because the 
solution of the problem is often that nominal definition is inappro- 
priate, and that what is wanted is an explanation of the use of the 
symbol. 

But this does not touch what mav be supposed to be the real 


msophy'- [ 323 ] 

ilBcMiy iHider tMs head (2); for what we have said applies only 
^ mrtks case in which the word to be defined being merely described 
tmated as one of a class), its definition or explanation is 
of course, merely described, but described .in such a way that 
the actual word is given its actual definition can be derived, 
~ But 'there are other cases in which the word to be defined being 
-even, we are given in return no definition of it but a statement that 
its meaning involves entities of such-and-such sorts in such-and- 
ways, i.e. a statement which, would give us a definition if we had 
names for these entities. 

As to the use of this, it is plainly to fit the term in connection 
with variables, to put it as a value of the right complex variable; 
and it presupposes that we can have variables without names for all 
their values. Difficult questions arise as to whether we must always 
be able to name all the values, and if so what kind of ability this 
means, but clearly the phenomenon is in some way possible in con- 
nection with sensations for which our language is so fragmentary. 
For instance, “Jane’s voice” is a description of a characteristic of 
sensations for which we have no name. We could perhaps name it, 
but can we identify and name the different inflections of which it 
consists? 

An objection often made to these descriptions of definitions of 
sensory characteristics is that they express what we should find on 
analysis, but that this kind of analysis changes the sensation ana- 
lyi&d by developing the complexity which it pretends merely to dis- 
cover. That attention can change our experience is indubitable, but 
it seems to me possible that sometimes it reveals a pre-existing com- 
plexity (i.e. enables us to symbolize this adequately), for this is 
compatible with any change in incidental facts, anything even except 
a creation of the complexity. 

Another difficulty with regard to descriptions of definitions is 
that if we content ourselves with them we may get simply nonsense 
by introducing nonsensical variables, e.g. described variables such 

“particular” or theoretical ideas such as “point.” W^e might for 
glance say that by “patch” we mean an infinite class of points; 
if so we should be giving up philosophy for theoretical psychology. 
For in philosophy we analyze our thought, in which patch could not 
be replaced by infinite class of points: we could not determine a 
particular infinite class extensionaily; “This patch is red” is not 
short for “a is red and b is red etc. . , where n, b, etc., are points. 
(Pow would it be if just a were not red?) Infinite classes of points 



[ 324 ] FRANK P. RAMSEY 

could only come in when we look at the mind from outside and 
construct a theory of it, in which its sensor}^ field consists of classes 
of colored points about which it thinks. 

Now if we made this theory about our own mind we should have 
to regard it as accounting for certain facts, e.g. that this patch is red; 
but when we are thinking of other people’s minds we have no facts, 
but are altogether in the realm of theoiy^ and can persuade ourselves 
that these theoretical constructions exhaust the field. We then turn 
back on our own minds, and say that what are really happening 
there are simply these theoretical processes. The clearest instance of 
this is, of course, materialism. But many other philosophies, e.g. 
Carnap’s, make just the same mistake. 

(3) Our third question was how we could avoid pernio principii, 
the danger of which arises somewhat as follows: 

In order to clarify my thought the proper method seems tc be 
simply to think out with myself “¥/hat do I mean by that?” ‘‘What 
are the separate notions invoived in this term?” “Does this really 
follow from that?” etc., and to test identic of meaning of a pro- 
posed definiens and the definiendum by real and hypothetical ex- 
amples. This we can often do without thinldng about the nature of 
meaning itself; w^e can tell whether w^e mean the same or difierent 
things by “horse” and “pig” without thinking at all about meaning 
in general. But in order to settle more complicated questions of the 
sort w^e obviously need a logical structure, a system of logic, into 
which to bring them. These we may hope to obtain by a relatively 
easy previous application of the same methods; for instance, it 
should not be difficult to see that for either not-p or not-^^ to be true 
is just the same thing as for not both p and q to be true. In this 
case we construct a logic, and do all our philosophical analysis en- 
tirely unselfconsciously , thinking all the time of the facts and not 
about our thinking about them, deciding what we mean without any 
reference to the nature of meanings. [Of course we could also think 
about the nature of meaning in an unseliconscious way; i.e. think 
of a case of meaning before us without reference to our meaning 
it.} This is one method and it may be the right one: but I think it 
is wrong and leads to an impasse, and I part company from it in 
the following w^ay. 

It seems to me that in the process of clarifying our thought we 
come to terms and sentences which we cannot elucidate in the ob\i- 
ous manner by defining their meaning. For instance, variable hTOO- 
theticals and theoretical terms we cannot define, but we can explain 
the way in which they are used, and in this explanation we are forced 


*1 








not only at the objects which we are talking about, but at 
mental states. As Johnson would say, in this part of logic 
'cannot neglect the epistemic or subjective side. 

; -Now this means that we cannot get clear about these terms and 
without getting clear about meaning, and we seem to get 
situation that we cannot understand e.g. what we say about 
time and the external world without first understanding meaning 
and yet we cannot understand meaning without first understanding 
certainly probably the external world which are involved 

in it So we cannot make our philosophy into an ordered progress to 
- a goal, but have to take our problems as a whole and jump to a 
simultaneous solution; which will have something of the nature of 
z hypothesis, for we shall accept it not as the consequence of direct 
ar^iment, but as the only one we can think of which satisfies our 
several requirements. 

Of course, we should not strictly speak of argument, but there 
is in philosophy a process analogous to “linear inference” in which 
things become successively clear; and since, for the above reason, 
we cannot carry this through to the end, we are in the ordinary posi- 
lion of scientists of having to be content with piecemeal improve- 
ments: we can make several things clearer, but we cannot make 
anything clear. 

I find this self-consciousness inevitable in philosophy except in 
a very^ limited field. We are driven to philosophize because we do 
not know clearly what we mean; the question is always “What do 
I mean by jc?” And only ver\^ occasionaiiy can we settle this with- 
out reflecting on meaning. But it is not only an obstacle, this necessity 
of dealing with meaning; it is doubtless an essential clue to the truth. 
If we neglect it I feel we may get into the absurd position of the 
child in the following dialogue: “Say breakfast.” “Can’t.” “W’'hat 
can’t you say?” “Can’t say breakfast.” 

But the necessity of self-consciousness must not be used as a 
Justification for nonsensical hypotheses; we are doing philosophy not 
theoretical psychology, and our analyses of our statements, whether 
about meaning or anything else, must be such as we can understand. 

The chief danger to our philosophy, apart from laziness and 
woolliness, is scholasticism, the essence of which is treating what is 
vague as if it w^ere precise and trying to fit it into an exact logical 
' ' P^tfigory^ A typical piece of scholasticism is Wittgenstein’s view that 
. ^ our everyday propositions’ are completely in order and that it is 
impossible to think illogically. (This last is like saying that it is im- 
possible to break the rules of bridge because if you break them 



[ 326 ] FRANK P. RAMSEY 

you are not playing bridge but, as Mrs. C. says, not-bridge.) An- 
other is the argumentation about acquaintance with before leading 
to the conclusion that we perceive the past. A simple consideration 
of the automatic telephone shows that we could react differently to 
AB and BA without perceiving the past, so that the argument is 
substantially unsound. It turns on a play with “acquaintance” which 
means, first, capacity to symbolize and, secondly, sensory percep- 
tion. Wittgenstein seems to equivocate in just the same way with 
his notion of “given.” 


16 







fc' ' , y"'-' y 


Philosophical Arguments 


BY GILBERT RYLE 


Robin Gec«ge Collingwood held this Waynflete Chair for a 

lamentably brief time. Yet his literary productivity during this short 
: . period was immense. The time is not yet ripe for me to attempt to 
offer a critical evaluation of these contributions to philosophy, nor, 
even were I competent, should I on this occasion offer an apprecia- 
tion of Ms originality as an historian. He would himself, I think, 
have desired recognition chiefly for his thoughts on the philosophy 
of history. About these thoughts, therefore, I submit, with humility 
and diffidence, a few reflections. 

There are many branches of methodical inquiry into the different 
departments of the world. There are the mathematical sciences, the 
several natural sciences, and there are the humane or human studies 
of anthropolog}^, jurisprudence, philosophy, the linguistic and lit- 
erary studies, and iiistor}^ which last embraces in one way or an- 
other most of the others. There are also many disciplines which 
teach not truths but arts and skills, such as agriculture, tactics, 
music, architecture, painting, games, navigation, inference, and sci- 
entific method. All theories apply their own several principles and 
canons of inquir}’' and all disciplines apply their own several prin- 
ciples and canons of practice. These princ'iples were called by Pro- 
fessor Coilingw'ood their “presuppositions.” In other words, all em- 
ploy their own standards or criteria by which their particular exercises 
are judged successful or unsuccessful. 

— Now it is one thing mtelligently to apply principles; it is quite 
pother thing to step back to consider them. A scientist who ceases 
or a moment to try to solve his questions in order to inquire instead 
why he poses them or whether they are the right questions to pose 
^^ssesT^the time to be a scientist and becomes a philosopher. This 

, Inaugurai lecture at Oxford, copyright 1946 by the Clareodon 

uxtord, it is reprinted here with the kind pennission of the author and pub- 











[ 328 ] GILBERT RYLE 

duality of interests may, as histoiy shows, make him both a good 
philosopher and a better scientist. The best philosophical theories of 
mathematics have come from mathematicians who have been forced 
to try to resolve internal puzzles about the principles of their study, 
a philosophical exercise which has sometimes led to the origination 
of new mathematical methods and has often led to the origination 
of illuminating philosophical views. Ever\^ genius is the inventor of 
new methods and he must therefore be some sort of a critic of 
principles of method. 

Professor Collingwood was an historian who was puzzled about 
the canons of historical research. He wanted not only to explain 
certain historical processes and events but also to elucidate what 
sort of a thing a good historical explanation would be. Nor was this 
a purely domestic or technological interest. For to see what is an 
historical explanation, is, among other things, to see how it diners 
from a chemical, mechanical, biological, anthropological, or psycho- 
logical theoiy^ The philosopher may, perhaps, begin by wondering 
about the categories constituting the framework of a single theoiy^ 
or discipline, but he cannot stop there. He must tiy^ to co-ordinate 
the categories of ail theories and disciplines. The problem of “Man's 
place in Nature” is, roughly, the problem of co-ordinating the ques- 
tions which govern laboratoiy researches with the questions gov- 
erning the researches prosecuted in libraries. And this xo-ordination 
is done neither in libraries nor in laboratories but in the philosophers 
head. 

Professor Collingwood saw more clearly, I think, than did his 
most eminent predecessors in the philosophy of history that the ap- 
pearance of a feud or antithesis between Nature and Spirit, that is 
to say, between the objectives of the natural sciences and those of 
the human studies, is an illusion. These branches of inquiiy are not 
giving rival answers to the same questions about the same world; 
nor are they giving separate answers to the same questions about 
rival worlds; they are giving their own answers to different questions 
about the same world. Just as physics is neither the foe nor the 
handmaid of geometr\% so history, jurisprudence and literary studies 
are neither hostile nor ancillary to the labor ator}' sciences. Their 
categories, that is, their questions, methods and canons are different. 
In my predecessor's word, they work with different presuppositions. 
To establish this point it is necessary to chart these differences. This 
task Professor Collingwood died too soon to complete but not too 
soon to begin. He had already made that great philosophic advance 
of reducing a puzzle to a problem. 








TJ^opMced Arguments [329 ] 

Professor CoUingwood kept himself aloof from the sparring 

the shadow-boxing by which academic philosophers ordinarily 
''sti^cgtheii their muscles and discharge their humors. What we lost 
this abstention was compensated by the world’s gain. For he 
less for the eyes of his professional associates than for those 
■ ||jg intelligent citizens of the entire republic of letters. In conse- 
' queoce he achieved a style of philosophical writing and, I believe, 
diction, which at its frequent best is on a level with the higher ranges 
of English philosophic prose. • 


The Problem 

.. PMlosophers have in recent years given much consideration to 
the nature, objectives and methods of their owm inquiry. This in- 
terest has been due partly to a certain professional hypochondria, 
since the conspicuous progress made by other studies has induced 
in philosophers some nervousness about the scale of their own suc- 
cesses. P^y, also, it has been due to the application of modem 
logical theor}' to the processes of the mathematical and the inductive 
sciences, which has automatically led to its application to philosophy. 
The exposition of the logical credentials of different sorts of scientific 
conclusions has posed in a bright if painful light the corresponding 
question about the foundations of philosophical doctrines. 

My object is to exhibit the logical structure of a t3me of argu- 
ments which are proper to philosophical thinking. It makes no dif- 
ference whether these arguments are used polemically in controversies 
between philosophers or peaceably in privaie philosophical reflection. 
For arguments are effective as weapons only if they are logically 
cogent, and if they are so they reveal connections, the disclosure of 
which is not the less necessar}' to the discover}^ of truth for being 
also handy in the discomfiture of opponents. The love of truth is not 
incongruous with a passion for correcting the erring. 

Philosophical arguments are not inductions. Both the premises 
and the conclusions of inductions can be doubted or denied without 
absurdity. Observed facts and plausible hypotheses have no more 
illustrative force in philosophy than is possessed by fictions or guesses. 
Nor have either facts or fancies any evidential force in the resolution 
of philosophical problems. The evidential force of matters of fact 
is only to increase or decrease the probability of general or particular 
hypotheses and it is absurd to describe philosophical propositions as 
relatively probable or improbable. 

On the other hand philosophical arguments are not demonstra- 



>edient to distinguish the strong reductio ad absurdum 
■eductio. The latter form is used in some of Euclid’s 
He demonstrates the truth of a theorem by deducing 
Victory consequences which conflict with the axioms 
' with consequences drawn from them. It should be 
^argument proves only either that the required the- 
the axioms are true or that both are false, that is, 
ctoiy' of the required theorem is not compatible with 
strong reduction consists in deducing from a propo- 
)lex of propositions consequences \^ch are incon- 
other or with the original proposition. It shows (to 
ishion which will have to be amended later) that a 
Jgitimate because it has logically absurd corollaries, 
under investigation is shown to be not merely false 


arguments of this type belong to philosophy it is 
i that It would be proper for a dissentient philos- 
imolish this or any other philosophical assertion 
radictions latent in it. I am not trying to prov'e 
! of argument are proper to pIiilosophyT 
leration it wiH seem that arguments of the t 3 me 
um can have only a destructive effect. They may 
Qolishing silly theories and thus possess, besides 
ty of defeating opponents, the useful one of clear- 
bsequent constructive theory. But it will be felt 
5 can result in the erection of a new dwelling. I 
^ such objection by showing that (to use anoSier 
> ad absurdum arguments are neither more nor 
e threshmg operations. Or, to change the picture 
wm be maintained that philosophical arguments 
3 have something in common with the destruction- 
leers discover the strength of materials. Certainly 


gilbert RYLE 

uclidean type, namely deductions of theorems from 
;ulates. For philosophy has no axioms and it is de- 
king its start from postulates. Otherwise there could 
ihilosophical doctrines as there are alternative geom- 

f argument which is proper and even proprietary' to 
he reductio ad absurdum. This argument moves by 
•aihctions or lo^cal paradoxes from its material. It 
this discussion to show how this is possible and why 





Arguments 


f331] 


stretch, twist, compress, and batter bits of metal until they 
it is just by such tests that they determine the strains 
^ttft&Ji'the metal ^ withstand. In somewhat the same way, philo- 
^phical arguments bring out the logical powers of the ideas under 
"iaftstigation, by JBxing the precise forms of logical mishandling under 
K - 1 - which they refuse to work. 

s Logical Powers of Propositioss 

i^ery proposition has what will here be called certain “logical 
- ‘ powers”; that is to say, it is related to other propositions in various dis- 
lo^cal relationships. It follow^s from some as a consequence 
and it implies others. It is incompatible with some and merely com- 
patible with others. It is e\idence strengthening or weakening the prob- 
ability of ulterior h}qx>theses. Further, for any logical powers pos- 
sessed by a given proposition it is always possible to find or invent 
an inde^te range of other propositions w'hich can be classed with 
it as having analogous logics powers or. as it is commonly put, as 
of the same logical form. 

For the rules of logic are general. \'’alid arguments exhibit pat- 
terns which can be manifested equally %vell by collocations of any 
other propositions of the same logical family. Formal logicians learn 
to extract the logical skeletons of propositions in virtue of which 
these and any other propositions embodying the same skeletons can 
function as premises or conclusions of parallel valid arguments. 

Now when people are using or considering a given proposition 
they cannot then and there be attending to all its logical powers. 

cannot in one moment be considering it and all the valid argu- 
ments into which it might enter and an lUc fallacious arguments 
into which it might be improperly coerced. At best their grasp is 
adequate for them to be able to thinl: out some of these logical 
powers if they have occasion to do so. Many of the logical powers 
3f a proposition are not noticed at all in the routines of workaday 
thinking and of these a proportion balSes discovery’ even when the 
thinker is concentrating his whole ioteliectual strength upon the search 
for them. Thus people can correctly be said to have only a partial 
grasp of most of the propositions that they consider. They could 
be taken by surprise by certain of the remoter logical con- 
of their most ordinary propositions. 

None the less, though people’s understanding of the proposidoiis 
that they use is in this sense imperfect, there is another sense in which 
their understanding of some of them may be nearly or quite complete. 





GILBERT RYLE^ 

For they may have learned from practice or instruction all their 
logical powers which govern the limited uses to which those proDosi. 
tons are ordinarily put. A boy leams quickly how to use such proDoI 
sitions as3 X3 = 9or London is due north of Brighton without ever 
makmg the arithmetical or geographical mistakes which would be 
evidence of an imperfect grasp of such propositions. He does not 
know the rules governing the logical behavior of these propositions 
but he knows by wont their logical course down a limited set of 
familiar tracks. ^ 

The fact that people, however intelligent, never achieve a com- 
p ete appreciation of all the logical powers of the propositions that 

important consequences 
It should be noticed that even mastery of the techniques and the 
theory' of formal logic does not in principle modify- this situation. The 
extraction of the logical skeletons of propositions does not reveal 
the logical powers of those propositions by some trick which absolves 
the lopcian from thinking them out. At best it is merely a summary 
formulation of what ms thinking has discovered. 

_ When several different propositions are noticed having something 
in common (and wnen this common feature or factor is^not itself a 
constituent proposition) it is convenient and idiomatic, though haz- 
ardous, to abstract this common factor and call it (with excentions) 

Thus men learn to fasten on the idea of 
i.a I y or me concept of price as that which is common to a rapoe 
of propositions in which persons are affirmed or denied to be mortal 

T said to cost so much or to be exchan'-'c- 

able at such and such rates. Later they learn to isolate in the same 
rnanner more abstract ideas like those of existence, impiicatioh. dutv. 
species, mind, and science. ^ ^ 

In the early days of logical speculation these ideas or conc^nks 
were construea as being proper parts or substantia! bits, an assemblage 
Oi two or more of which was supposed to constitute a proposition. 

W i styled “terms.- This erroneous theoiw 

has been the source or a multitude of damaging confusions. The truth 
K ihat what we label “ideas” or “concepts” are abstractions from the 
tnSc'% propositions of which they are common factors or fea- 
nf n™ summarily of the family 

fector Tt t rosembling each other in respect of this common 

t ctor. Statements about ideas are general statements about familie-: 

OI propositions. 

A natural but disastrous corollary drawn from the erroneous 
doctrme of tenns was the assumption that the rules of logic govern the 







■ '^^^pkicd Arguments { J 

^oas "between propositions but have little or no bearing upon 
factors. It was, indeed, early discerned that there are logically 
differences of type or category^ betvv^een different classes of 
■{rl' ^ ^Ideas,” or “concepts,” but the original and traditional classi- 
"'ftaffon of a few of these types lent nothing to and borrowed nothing 
the study of the rules of inference. (True, certain rules of in- 
. iatMCC were :seeii to be interlocked with the concepts all, some, and 
But no 'niche was found even for these ideas in the table of 
'■•'categories ofxoncepts.) 

fact the distinction between the logical types of ideas is iden- 
. ; ^ tical with the discrimmation between the logical forms of the propo- 

’ sirions from which the ideas are abstractions. If one proposition has 
factors of different types from those of another proposition, those 
propositions are of different logical forms and have different sorts of 
logical powers. The rules governing the conjunctions of propositions 
' is valid arguments reflect the logical consiinitions of their various 
abstractible factors and features. There are as many upes of terms 
as there are forms of propositions, just as there are as many uphill 
as downhill slopes. 

It is therefore both proper and necessaiy to speak not only (at 
one level of abstraction) of the logical powers of propositions, but 
also (at a higher level of abstraction) of the logical pov/ers of ideas 
or concepts. Of course, a description of the logical powers of a given 
idea is neither more nor less than a description of certain of the logical 
powders of all propositions similar to one another in having that idea 
as an abstractible common factor. 

As people’s understanding of the proposiiicns that they use is 
always imperfect, in the sense that they never have realized and 
never could realize ah the logical powers of those propositions, so 
their grasp of ideas or concepts is necessarily incomplete. The risk 
always exists that confusion or paradox will arise in the course of 
any hitherto untried operations with those ideas. 


; The Sources of Logical Paradoxes 

j . Concepts and propositions cany^ with them no signal to indicate 
^ ^ logical types to which they belong. Expressions of the same gram- 

y . ' ^srical patterns are used to express thoughts of multifarious logical 

I ■ , Men naturally, therefore, tend to be blind to the fact that dif- 

ideas have different logical powers or at least they tend to 
& -j ' varieties of logical types as being few in number. Even 

ii, P^^^pbers have assumed for over two thousand vears that Aris- 






[ 334 ] GILBERT RYLE 

totle’s inventory of ten such t5rpes was exhaustive if not over- 
elaborate. 

What happens when a person assumes an idea to be of one 
logical type when it really belongs to another? — ^when, for example^ 
he assumes that the ideas large or three have logical powers similar 
to those of green or merr/l The inevitable consequence is that naive 
Intellectual operations with those ideas lead directly to logicaEy m- 
tolerable results. Concepts of different types cannot be coerced into 
similar logical conduct. Some sort of contradiction arises from the 
attempt and this, in fortunate cases, compels the thinker to turn 
back in his tracks and try to change his treatment of the outraged 
concept. 


The Diagnosis and Core of Paradoxes 

Here there begins a new sort of inquiiy^ the deliberate attempt 
to discover the real (as distinct from the naively anticipated) logical 
powers of ideas. The logical absurdities which betray the origirial 
type-confusions give an intellectual shock and set a theoretical prob- 
lem, the problem of determining with method and with definitive 
checks the rules governing the correct manipulation of concepts. 

This task can be metaphorically described as the charting of 
the logical powers of ideas. The metaphor is helpful in a number 
of ways. People often know their way about a loc^ty w^hiie quite 
unable to describe the distances or directions between different parts 
of it or between it and other familiar localities. They may knov; a 
district and still be perplexed when approaching it by an unaccus- 
tomed route or in a strange light. Again they may know the district 
and still give descriptions of it which entail that two different build- 
ings are in one place or that one building lies in two different direc- 
tions from a given object. 

Our workaday knowledge of the geography of our ideas is in 
similar case — even of those ideas with which we can operate eE- 
cientiy in the daily tasks in which w^e have been drilled. This worka- 
day knowledge is knowledge but it is knowledge without system and 
yf'ithout checks. It is knowledge by wont and not knowledge by rules. 

There is another respect in which the metaphor of maps is use- 
ful. Surveyors do not map single objects like the village church. 
They put together in one map all the salient features of the area: 
the church, the bridge, the railway, the parish boundar}^, and per- 
haps the contours. Further, they indicate how this map joins the 
maps of the neighboring areas, and how^ all are co-ordinated with 


[335 ] 

Phihsophicd Arguments . , . ] 1 

of tbe compass, the lines of latitude and longitude and 
^S^of measuremLt. Any error in surveying results m a carto- 

^^Tre^°ution of type-puzzles about the logical powers of ideas 
A mauds an analogous procedure. Here too the problem is not to 
^Sit separately^ the locus of this or that single idea but to deter- 
mine the cross-bearings of all of a galaxy of ideas belongmg to ^ 

or contiguous fields. The problem, that is, is not to anatomize 
S^^litary cS:ept, say, of liberty but to extract its lopcal poweK 
as these bear on those of law, obedience, responsibihty, loyalty, go - 
emment and the rest. Like a geographical survey a philosop^c^ 
sSSy is necessarily synoptic. Philosophical problems cannot be 

fwipfii or soivs(i ipi6Csrtio2.i. , 

^^°^TOs description of the inquiry into the logical powers of ideas 
as bein<' analogous in some respects to a geographical survey is, ot 
course, "of iUustrative utility only within narrow limits. In one m- 
portant respect among many others the analog' breaks down. The 
TOrrectness of a geographical survey is established by two major 
sorts of checks; the presence of a cartographical contradiction proves 
that the survey is erroneous but visual observations are positive evi 
deuce of its veracity. In the extraction of the lo^cal powers of ideas 
there is no process directly corresponding to visual observation. 
Hence the primacy in philosophical reasoning or the reauctio ad 
absurdum argument. The object to which this phiiosopmcai destmc- 
tion-test is applied is the practice of operating with an laea as n it 
belonged to a certain category, that is as if it had powers correspon - 
ing to those of an accepted model. InitiaUy this practice is naive and 
unoremeditated. Sometimes it is deliberately recommended and 
adopted. In this case the destruction-test is being apphed to a 

philosopher’s theor}'. . 

The earliest philosophical problems are set by contrauictions m- 
advertently encountered in the course of non-phiiosophical thinking. 
As every new theory^ begins certain new concepts coine aHlO -.nr 
rency, concepts which are cardinal not merely to its conclubions Dut 
even to its questions. Being new their logical powers are still un 
explored, and being new^ they are unthinkingly credited with 
powers similar to those of ideas the discipline of which is familiar. 
Paradoxical consequences flowing from conventional operations upon 
them reveal that they have characters of their own. So must hoi^es 
Have startled their first masters by their non-bovine shape and be- 
havior. 

When the deliberate attempt is made to find the harness which 



[ 336 ] GILBERT RTX.E 

wiil fit refractory concepts, the method is adopted of consciously 
looking for further logical paradoxes and contradictions. The rules 
governing the logical conduct of an idea are imperfectly grasped so 
long as there remain unexamined chances that it is still being mis- 
handled. Absurdities are the original goad to philosophical thinking’ 
they continue to be its scalpel. 

This process can without injustice to the genealogy of the word 
be called “dialectical,” though there seems no reason to constrict 
the process within the symmetrical confines of the hallowed double- 
entry method often associated with its employment. It is also the 
procedure followed, though not explicitly prescribed, by those who 
prefer to describe philosophy as being the clarification of ideas, the 
analysis of concepts, the study of universals and even the search for 
definitions. 


An Objection 

At this point it is necessary to face and resolve a difficulty — in- 
deed a contradiction — ^which threatens to make nonsense of every- 
thing that I have said. Its emergence and its resolution may serve 
as an illustration of my general position. 

It has been said that philosophical problems arise from a tend- 
ency of propositions (as we inadvertently handle them) to generate 
absurd consequences. But if the consequences of a proposiiion are 
absurd that proposition is absurd and then there can be no such 
proposiiion. It is absurd to say that there are absurd propositions. 
It is logically impossible for there to be a proposition of such a 
type that there could be no propositions of that type. It seems to 
follow that the reductio ad absurdum can never be applied, though 
the argument establishing this point itself exemplifies that pattern. 

The solution is that expressions and only expressions can be 
absurd. Only of a given expression such as a sentence, therefore, 
can it be said that it cannot be construed as expressing a proposition 
of a certain logical constitution or, perhaps, a proposition of any 
logical constitution. This is what the reductio ad absurdum does. It 
discloses that a given expression cannot be expressing a proposition 
of such and such a content with such and such a logical skeleton, 
since a proposition with certain of these properties would conflict 
with one with certain of the others. The operation by which this is 
established is in a certain fashion experimental or hypothetical. If 
the expression is expressing a proposition at all, it cannot be express- 
ing one analogous in these respects to certain familiar propositions 






^J^^phkd Arguments [ 337 ] 

In |||0se respects to others, since the corollaries of part of the 
' ^^thcsis are at variance with those of another part. It is an hypo- 
argument of the pattern known as ponendo tollem. In ex- 
famine cases it may establish that the expression cannot be expressing 
; •- pj^position of any pattern; in milder cases it proves only that it 
^nhot be expressing a proposition of certain specified patterns. 

■ For examples, take the two statements ‘‘Numbers are etemaf’ 
^ ^‘Time began a million years ago.” Both are linguistically regular 
sfatements but the latter sentence expresses no proposition. It tries 
to say what cannot be significantly said, viz. that there was a mo- 
ihent before which there w^as no possibility of anything being before 
^ything else, which contains a patent contradiction. The former 
.sentence is nonsensical if construed as expressing a proposition of 
one type but not if construed in another way. If it is construed as a 
terse way of saying that numbers are not temporal things or events 
or, better, that numerical expressions cannot enter into significant 
expressions as subjects to verbs with tenses, then what it says is 
true and important. But if it is construed, as childlike people have 
construed it, as saying that numbers, like tortoises, live a very long 
time — and in fact however old they get, they cannot die — then it 
could be shown to be absurd. It is nonsense when construed as an 
item of biology but true wben interpreted as an application of the 
theory of logical types to arithmetical ideas. , 

Reductio ad absurdum arguments, therefore, apply to the em- 
ployment and misemplo3TOent of expressions. So it is necessar}^ to 
recast what was said earlier. Statements about the misreading of 
the logical powders of propositions and ideas should be reformulated 
somewhat as follows. 

Certain classes of expressions when functioning in certain classes 
of contexts either have or are unthinkingly supposed to have a cer- 
tain logical force. And when I speak of an expression as having or 
teing credited with a certain logical force I mean no more than that 
it expresses or is assumed to express an idea or proposition with 
certain logical powers, in the sense adumbrated above. It is there- 
fore always possible to inquire w'hat consequential propositions would 
be true if the expression under investigation expressed or helped to 
express a proposition the logical powers of which were analogous 
to those of a known model. It is always initially possible that this 
, logical experiment will reveal that some of the consequences of the 
-assumption conflict with some of its other consequences and thus 
leyeal that the attribution of this logical force to this expression in 
&is use was a false one. The genuine logical force of the expression 







Tptf. Function of the “Reductio ad Absurdum” 

The discovery of the logical type to which a puzzle-generating 
idea belongs is the discovery of the rales governing the valid argu- 
ments in which propositions embodying that idea (or any other idea 
of the same type) can enter as premises or conclusions. It is also 
the discovery of the general reasons why specific fallacies result 
from mis attributions of it to specific types. In general the former 
discovery is only approached through the several stages of the latter. 
The idea is (deliberately or blindly) hypothetically treated as homo- 
geneous with one familiar model after another and its own logical 
structure emerges from the consecutive elimination of supposed logi- 
cal properties by the absurdities resulting from the supposals. 

This program appears vexatiousiy circuitous and one is tempted 
to dream of some direct way of fixing the logical powers of pu zz le- 
generating ideas, w^hich shall share with the method of progressive 
reductio the merit of being rigorous while improving on it by dis- 
pensing with trial and error. But, whatever other methods of search 
may be used, there remains this important fact about its object, that 
to find or understand a rule it is necessar}^ to appreciate not only 
what it enforces but also what it permits and what it forbids. People 
are not fully seized of a logical rule if they have not considered the 
absurdities against which it prescribes. The boundaries* of a right of 
way are also boundaries of forbidden ground. So no method of dis- 
covering the legitimate employments of a concept can dispense with 
the method of forecasting the logical disasters consequent upon 
illegitimate operations with it. Before the argument comes to its 
close, it is necessar}^ to clear up three subsidiary points. 

Systematic Ambiguity 

It is commonly supposed that a particular concept is precisely 
indicated by reference to a particular expression, as if for example 
the idea of equality were unmistakably identified by being described 
as that for which the word “equality” stands. 

There are, of course, in all languages some words w^hich happen 
to have twu or more different meanings. That is how puns are pos- 
sible. But these ambiguities are of no theoretical interest. They are 


[ 338 ] gilbert RYLE 

(if it has a force at all) , must therefom be such that the propositions 
which it helps to express have coi^titutions which are insured against 
these and other contradictions. 


^ ,, ■■■ [339 I 

Arguments L J 

LilS in ieir occurrence, they can be c™vented by simple 
nr naraphrases and the different ideas expressed by a 
^^m^on P P connection with one another that 

^ ihich the word is used normally suffices to specify 
Si.??Sis intended to be conveyed. But there is another sort of 

of signification which characterizes the use not of a few 
most or of ail expressions and which is such that the para- 
Erases and translations of an expression with a certain elasticity of 
will normally have a precisely similar elastiaty. This 
i^^^biguity is systematic in further respects. The vanous ideas 
■^^Lssed by an expression in its different uses are intimately con- 
with each other. They are in one way or another different in- 
flections of the same root. 

'A dven word wUl, in different sorts of context, express ideas ot 

an indSnite range of differing logical types and, therefore, with dif- 
feient logical powers. xAnd what is true of single words is also true 
of complex expressions and of grammatical constructions. 

Consider the adjective ‘^punctual.’' It can be used to characterize 
a person’s arrival at a place, the person who arrives there, his char- 
acter, and even the average character of a class of persons. It would 
be absurd to compare the punctuality of a man on a particular occa- 
sion with that of his arrival on that occasion; it would be absurd to 
compare the punctuality of his character with that of his arrival on 
a particular occasion; and it would be absurd to compare the punc- 
tuality of Naval officers as a class with that of a particular Na\al 
officer. These and similar absurdities show that the word punctual 
undergoes inflections of significance when applied to different types 
of subjects. There would be the same inflections of significance in 
French or German and parallel inflections with other words of the 
same sort, like “tidy” and ‘'‘industrious.’ So, where precision is 
wanted, it is wrong to speak of “toe idea’ of punctuality,^ although 
the word “punctual” does not become a pun-word by having a dif- 
-ferent logical force for each different ty^pe of context in which it is 
. used. 

A philosophically more interesting example is afforded by the 
verb to ‘‘exist.” It may be true that there exists a cathedral in Ox- 
ford, a three-engined bomber, and a square number between 9 and 
^25, But the naive passage to the conclusion that there are three 
;cxistents, a building, a brand of aircraft and a number soon leads 
;? to trouble. The senses of “exists” in which the three subjects are said 
exist are different and their logical behaviors are different. The 
*-**-=^' of different logical inflections in the forces of expressions 






[ 340 ] GILBERT RYLE 

is made by the impact upon us of the absurdities resulting from 
ignoring them; the determination of those difierences is done by 
pressing the search for further such absurdities. Unnoticed systematic 
ambiguities are a common source of type-confusions and philosophic, 
problems. Philosophers are sometimes found lamenting this readiness 
of languages to give to one expression the power of expressing an 
indefinite variety of ideas; some of them even recommend reforms 
of usage which will pin single meanings to single expressions. But, 
in fact, the capacity of familiar dictions to acquire new^ inflections 
of logical forces is one of the chief factors making original thought 
possible. A new^ thought cannot find a new vehicle ready made for 
it, nor can the discrimmation of the logical powers of new ideas 
precede the birth of the knowledge (by w'ont) of how^ to think with 
them. As some spanners are designed to be adjustable, so as to fit 
bolts of the same shape but differeni sizes, so. though undesigned, 
those linguistic instruments of thought are found to be most handy 
which are the most readily adjustable. The suggestion that men 
should coin a different diction to correspond with ever}' difference 
in the logical powers of ideas assumes, absurdly, that they could be 
aware of these differences before being taken aback by the para- 
doxes arising from their naively attributed similarities. It is like sug- 
gesting that Grill should precede the formation of habits or that chil- 
dren should be tauahi the rules of gra m mar before learning to talk. 


Abstractions 

I have been spealdng so far as if ah ideas alike generate philo- 
sophical puzzles. But this needs correction. To put it roughly, con- 
crete ideas do not generate such puzzles, abstract ideas do. But this 
disiinction between concrete and abstract as well as that between 
lower and higher abstractions requires a clarification, of which no 
more than a sketch can be given here. By a "concrete idea” is 
meant one the original use of w^hich is to serve as an element in 
propositions about what exists or occurs in the real world. It could 
be introduced or explained to an inquirer by confronting him with 
one or several specimens from the real world, or else by presenting 
him with physical models, pictures or mental images of specimens. 
Propositions containing such ideas can be called first-order propo- 
sitions. Questions about their truth and falsehood can in favorable 
cases be settled by observ'ation or sets of observations. 

Ideas like spaniel, dog, ache, thunder in their originai use are 
instances of concrete concepts. In this use they generate no philo- 



Arguments 


[341] 

ouzzles, since one learns from the routines of dahy^exf^n- 
P pe and the limits of their application. Their logical 
.^^^ prShv’Ms taught by one’s daily walks. Such concepts are formed 

- „nticin<^ similarities in the real world. , , t. . * 

different from these are what are often called abstract 
is a negative mark of these that a person cannot be mtro- 
S to such concepts by being presented with correspondmg reali- 
' ' ri^Nothing in the world exemphfies the economic man the 

S'tMs idea occurs e.g. in the Spaniel is a descendant of the Wolf), 

■ : ^ or 2 (as this occurs e.g. in 2 is a prime number). It is a positive 

• mark of some abstract ideas that they can be expressed by abstract 
nouns like “justice,” “circularity” and “wickedness”; but this is the 

• exception rather than the rule. The proposition the economic man 
' \ huvs in the cheapest and sells in the dearest market is an abstract 

oroposition, though nothing in the vocabular}^ of the sentence indi- 
cates that the proposition is of a different logical type Irom the ola 
man buys his tobacco in the neighboring tobacconisfs shop. 

Abstract propositions do not directly describe the real wond 
but nor do they directly describe any other world. They apply mdi- 
‘ - rectly to the real world, though there are various types of such indirect 
; appHcation. Arithmetic is not about inventories, but inventones 
satisfy arithmetical propositions; geometr\' does not describe Asia, 
but the geography of Asia is an application of geometiy% and so on. 
To form abstract ideas it is necessary to notice not similarities be- 
tween things in nature but similarities between propositions about 
tilings in nature or, later on, between propositions about propositions 
about things in nature. . . . But this conclusion nas an air of mys- 
tery, deriving from the fact that propositions are themselves abstrac- 
tions. The world does not contain propositions. It contains people 
believing, supposing and arguing propositions. This amounts (nearly 
enough) to saying that the world contains linguistic and other ex- 
pressions, used or usable by no-niatter-whom, which expressions, 
when used, express truths or falsehoods. To talk about a given prop- 
- osition is therefore to talk about what is expressed by any e?:pression 

- (of no matter what linguistic structure) having the same logical 

: ’ . force as some given expression, as such expressions are or might be 

I h;;' intelligently used by persons (no matter whom). 

^ , This doctrine that to speak of a specified proposition is to speak 

of persons (no matter who) using expressions (no matter of what 
% ' - sorts) having the same logical force as that of a given expression 
can be proved. In any particular instance, it is always significant to 
there is no such proposition, since the given sentence is 






[ ] GILBERT RYLE 

absurd, having, perhaps, parts which have correct uses in other con- 
texts but cannot be combined in this way to form a sentence with an 
integral logical force. 

With these safeguards it is correct to say that some propositions 
are about other propositions and are therefore second- or hinher- 
order propositions. Some higher-order propositions, which form 
perhaps, the most numerous class, are only about other propositions 
in the special sense that they are about partial similarities between 
otherwise different propositions. For any given proposition there 
may be found a range of different propositions sharing with it and 
with each other some one common factor. “Socrates is wise” ex- 
presses a proposition having something in common with what is 
expressed by “Plato sapiens est.’" This co mm on factor can be ex- 
pressed by a skeleton sentence of the pattern “so and so is wise” 
(where “so and so” announces the gap in the skeleton sentence). 
Similarly the skeleton sentence “if p then expresses what is com- 
mon to a range of hypothetical propositions. 

Propositions about such factors of propositions, with certain 
exceptions, are ordinarily said to be propositions about abstractions 
or abstract ideas. They are higher-order propositions about isoiable 
features of ranges of lower-order propositions and describe the loa- 
cal force of skeleton sentences equipollent with a given skeleton 
sentence. Thus, a proposition about wisdom does" not mention 
Socrates or Plato; facts about Socrates and Plato are irrelevant to 
its truth. Yet the general fact that there are or might be subjects 
oi whom it could be true that they w’ere wise is not irrelevant to 
the logical force of the word “wisdom” and it is consequently rele- 
vant to the truth of propositions about wisdom. This illustrates the 
sense in which it has been said that abstract propositions do not 
describe the world, or zny other world, but do indirectly anoiv 
to the world. It is always possible to accuse a submitted abstract 
idea of absurdity or rather to accuse an, expression purporting to 
express an abstract idea of being an absurd e.xpression. Naturally 
enough language does not provide many nonsemical single word's 
but there frequently occur absurd complex e.xpressions, purporting 
to express complex concepts, when such a complex is illegitimated 
The fact that such accusations are always significant proves that 
abstract propositions always embody overt or covert inverted com- 
mas. (Indeed any abstract proposition if expressed with maximum 
logical candor would be seen to be describing a tenuous morsel of 
the real world, namely an expression in inverted commas. But of 
course it only mentions such an expression as a means of specif>'ing 


Arguments [ 343 ] 

or proix>sitioii wMctt is the logical force of that and any 

■fboiripolcnt expression.) . j > ^ a a r 

liere is, of course, an unliimted vanety of types and orders of 
ideas, but all alike can generate philosophical puzzles, just 
experience of the real world gives us no drill in their cor- 
bel use. Mistaken views about abstractions are not rebutted by a 
broised shin or a parched throat. Nor does the language used to 
'express abstract ideas vary with their different varieties. The chart- 
ing of their logical powers consists therefore in the checking of their 
logical behavior against logical rules, which is the operation described 
in tins lecture, i.e. the eiimmation by reductio ad absurdum of logical 
powers incorrectly ascribed or ascribable to them. 

Another general point can now be established. For any abstract 
proposition there must be a range of propositions of a lower level, 
since the abstract proposition describes factors common to them. 
This implies that corresponding to any abstraction there is at a lower 
proposition-level an idea being actually used (and not described). 
There must bt at this lower level knowledge by wont of some 
powers of this idea before there can begin the higher-level research 
into the rules governing those powers. We must know in practice 
how to decide whether Socrates is wise or clever before we can de- 
bate the abstract question of the relations between wisdom and 
cleverness. (Hence philosophy is sometimes said to tell us only 
what we knew before. This is as true as the corresponding statement 
about Mr. Jourdain’s knowledge of prose before his introduction to 
grammar.) 

This indicates what was missing in my prefatory account of the 
method and effects of philosophical reasoning. This w’as likened to 
' threshing, which separates the grain from the chaff, discards the 
chaff and collects the grain. Philosophical reasoning separates the 
genuine from the erroneously assumed logical powers of abstract 
ideas by using the reductio ad absurdum argument as its fiail and 
winnowing fan, but knowledge by wont of the use of concreter ideas 
is also necessary as its floor. 


Crucial and Cardinal Ideas 

' Though all abstract ideas alike are liable to generate phiiosophi- 
puzzles, some demand priority in philosophical examination. Of 
. these one class consists largely of the new^ theory-shaping ideas which 
“ are struck out from time to time in the fields of science, criticism, 
- statesmanship, and philosophy by men of genius. Genius shows itself 


[ ] GILBERT RYLE 

not so much in the discovery of new answers as in the discovery of 
new questions. It influences its age not by solving its problems "but 
by opening its eyes to previously unconsidered problems. So the 
new ideas released by genius are those which give a new direction 
to inquiry, often amounting to a new method of thinking. 

Such crucial ideas, being new, are at the start unco-ordinated with 
the old.^ Their potency is quickly recognized but their logical powers 
have still to be determined, as, correspondingly have those logical 
powers of the old ideas w^hich have yet to be correlated with the 
new. The task of assimilating the new crucial ideas into the un- 
fevered blood-stream of workaday thought is rendered both more 
urgent and more difiicult by the fact that these ideas necessarily besin 
by being exciting. They shock the settled who execrate them as 
superstition, and they spell-bind the young who consecrate them 
into m3;th. That cloud and this rainbow are not dispelled until philos- 
ophers settle the true logical perspectives of the ideas. 

Quite distinct from these, though often integral to them, are what 
may be described as philosophically cardinal ideas, those, namely, 
the logical unravelling of which leads directly to the unravelling of 
some^ complex tangle of interconnected ideas. Once these key-ideas 
are charted, the geography of a whole region is, at least in outline, 
nxed. No general clue can be given for predicting which ideas will 
turn out to have this catalytic power. To discern this is the privilege 
01 philosophic genius. ^ 




17 

How I See Philosophy 

BY FRIEDRICH WAISMANN 


/ W3BAT PHILOSOPHY is?^ I don’t know, nor have I a set formula to 
offer. Immediately I sit down to contemplate the question I am 
ftooded with so many ideas, tumbling over one another, that I can- 
not do justice to ail of them. I can merely make an attempt, a ver}^ 
inadequate one, to sketch with a few' strokes what the lie of the land 
seems to me to be, tracing some lines of thought without entering 
upon a close-knit argument. 

It is, perhaps, easier to say w^hat philosophy is not than what it 
is. The first thing, then, I should like to say is that philosophy, as it 
is practised today, is unlike science; and this in three respects: 
in philosophy there are no proofs; there are no theorems; and there 
are no questions which can be decided, Yes or No. In saying that 
there are no proofs I do not mean to say that there are no arguments. 
Arguments certainly there are, and first-rate philosophers are recog- 
nized by the originality of their arguments; only these do not work 
in the sort of w'ay they do in mathematics or in the sciences. 

^ There are many things beyond proof: the existence of material 
objects, of other minds, indeed of the external world, the validity of 
induction, and so on. Gone are the days when philosophers w'ere 
trying to prove all sorts of things: that the soul is immortal, that this 
. is the best of all possible worlds and the rest, or to refute, by “irre- 
' futable” argument and with relish, materialism, positivism and what 

Proof, refutation — these are dying words in philosophy (though 
-'G. E. Moore stiU ‘‘proved” to a puzzled world that it exists. What 

cs^y is r)|-_ Waismann’s contribution to Contemporary British Philosophy, 

' dnn H. D. Lewis), copjo-ight 1956 by George Allen and Unwin Ltd,, Lon- 

. . Witn whose kind permission it is here reprinted. 

“ ^ ™ reply to a question put to me by the Editor (of Contemporary 



[ 345 ] 








[ 346 ] FRIEDRICH WAISMAI^ 

can one say to this — save, perhaps, that he is a great prover before 
the Lord?). 

But can it be proved that there are no proofs in philosophy? No; 
for one thing, such a proof, if it were possible, would by its very 
existence establish what it was meant to confute. But why suppose 
the philosopher to have an I.Q. so low as to be unable to learn from 
the past? Just as the constant failure of attempts at constructing a 
perpetual motion has in the end led to something positive in physics, 
so the efforts to construct a philosophical “system,” going on for 
centuries and going out of fashion fairly recently, tell their tale. 
This, I think, is part of the reason why philosophers today are get- 
ing weaned from casting their ideas into deductive moulds, in the 
grand style of Spinoza. 

\%at I want to show' in this article is that it is quite wrong to 
look at philosophy as though it had for its aim to provide theorems 
but had lamentably failed to do so. The w^hole conception changes 
when one comes to realize that w'hat philosophers are concerned 
with is something difierent — neither discovering new propositions nor 
refuting false ones nor checking and re-checking them as scientists 
do. For one thing, proofs require premisses. Whenever such prem- 
isses have been set up in the past, even tentatively, the discussion at 
once challenged them and shifted to a deeper level. Where there are 
no proofs there are no theorems either. (To write down lists of 
propositions “proved” by Plato or Kant: a pastime strong!}- to be 
recommended.) Yet the failure to establish a sort of Euclidean 
system of philosophy based on some suitable “axioms” is, I submit, 
neither a mere accident nor a scandal but deeply founded in the 
nature of philosophy. 

Yet there are questions; (and arguments). Indeed, a philosopher 
is a man who senses as it were hidden crevices in the build of our 
concepts where others only see the smooth path of conimonplaceness 
before them. 

Questions but no answers? Decidedly odd. The oddness may 
lessen when w^e take a look at them at closer range. Consider two 
famous examples: Achilles and the tortoise, and the astonishment of 
St. Augustine when confronted with the fact of memoiy^ He is 
amazed, not at some striking feat of memory, but at there being 
such a thing as memory at all. A sense-impression, say a smell or a 
taste, floats before us and disappears. One moment it is here and 
the next it is gone. But in the galleries of the memoiy^ pale copies 
of it are stored up after its death. From there I can drag them out 
when and as often as I wish, like, and yet strangely unlike, the 


j 


See Fhilosophy [ 347 ] 

in that they are not perishable like the momentary 
what was transitory has been arrested and has achieved 
' But who can say how this change comes about? 
v.- 4 :v*-^'^^Herc^the veiy fact of memory feels mystifying in a way in which 
asMng for information do not; and of course it 
is' mt a factual question. What is it? 

: -From Plato to Schopenhauer philosophers are agreed that the 
-■• 'mmcQ-ol their philosophizing is wonder, ’^hiat gives rise to it is 
recondite and rare but precisely those things which stare us 
memory, motion, generi ideas. (Plato: What does 
*‘horse’* mean? A single particular horse? No, for it may refer to 
my horse; all the horses, the total class? No, for we may speak of 
this or that horse. But if it means neither a single horse nor all horses, 
what does it mean?) The idealist is shaken in just the same way 
when he comes to reflect that he has, in Schopenhauer’s words, ‘"no 
knowledge of the sun but only of an eye that sees a sun, and no 
knowledge of the earth but only of a hand that feels an earth.” Can 
it be, then, that nothing whatever is knowm to us except our own 
consciousness? 

In looking at such questions, it seems as if the mind’s eye were 
growing dim and as if everything, even that which ought to be abso- 
lutely clear, was becoming oddly puzzling and unlike its usual self. 
To bring out what seems to be peculiar to these questions one might 
say that they are not so much questions as tokens of a profound 
uneasiness of mind. Tr\^ for a moment to put yourself into the frame 
of mind of which Augusdne was possessed when he asked: How is 
it possible to measure time? Time consists of past, present and future. 
The past can’t be measured, it is gone; the future can’t be measured, 
it is not yet here; and the present can’t be measured, it has no ex- 
tension. Augustine kIlev^■ of course how time is measured and this 
was not his concern, \\hat puzzled him was how it is possible to 
measure time, seeing that the past hour cannot be lifted out and 
placed alongside the present hour for comparison. Or look at it this 
way: what is measured is in the past, the measuring in the present: 
how can that be? 

The philosopher as he ponders over some such problem has the 
..appearance of a man who is deeply disquieted. He seems to be strain- 
nig to grasp something which is beyond his powers. The words in 
. such a question presents itself do not quite bring out into the 
...open the real point — ^which may, perhaps more aptly, be described 
the recoil from the incomprehensible. If, on a straight railway 
. 'journey, you suddenly come in sight of the very station you have 



' 






'rrm 





[ 348 ] FBIEDRICH WAISMANK 

just left behind, there will be terror, accompanied perhaps by slight 
giddiness. That is exactly how the philosopher feels when he says to 
himself, “Of course time can be measured; but how can it?” It is as 
though, up to now, he had been passing heedlessly over the diffi- 
culties, and now, all of a sudden, he notices them and asks himself 
in alarm, “But how can that be?” That is a sort of question which 
we only ask when it is the very facts themselves which confound us, 
when something about them strikes us as preposterous. 

Kant, I fancy, must have felt something of the sort when he sud- 
denly found the existence of geometry a puzzle. Here we have prop- 
ositions as clear and transparent as one would wish, prior, it seems, 
to ail experience; at the same time they apply miraculously to the 
real world. How is that possible? Can the mind, unaided by experi- 
ence, in some dark manner actually fathom the properties of real 
things? Looked upon in this way, geometry takes on a disturbing air. 

We all have our moments when something quite ordinary^ sud- 
denly strikes us as queer — ^for instance, when time appears to us as 
a curious thing. Not that we are often in this frame of mind: but on 
some occasions, when we look at things in a certain way, unex- 
pectedly they seem to change as though by magic: they stare at us 
with a puzzling expression, and we begin to wonder whether they 
can possibly be the things we have known all our lives. 

“Time flows” we say — a natural and innocent expression, and 
yet one pregnant with danger. It flows “equably,” in J^ewton’s phrase, 
at an even rate. What can this mean? When something moves, it 
moves with a definite speed (and speed means: rate of change in 
time). To ask with what speed time moves, i.e. to ask how quickly 
time changes in time, is to ask the unaskable. It also flows, again 
in Newton’s phrase, “without relation to anything external.” How 
are we to figure that? Does time flow on irrespective of what happens 
in the world? Would it flow* on even if everything in heaven and on 
earth came to a sudden standstill as Schopenhauer believed? For if 
this w'ere not so, he said, time would have to stop with the stopping 
of the clock and move with the clock’s movement. How' odd: time 
flow^s at the same rate and yet without speed; and perhaps even with- 
out anything to occur in it? The expression is puzzling in another 
way. “I can never catch myself being in the past or in the future,” 
someone might say; “whenever I think or perceive or breathe the 
word ‘now,’ I am in the present; therefore I am always in the 
present.” In saying this, he may think of the present moment as a 
bridge as it were from which he is looking down at the “river of 
time.” Time is gliding along underneath the bridge, but the “now” 





FMlosophy 


[349 ] 


take part in the motion. What was future passes into the 
'Lj rrjr nt' fis just below the bridge) and then into the past, while the 


‘f tiie “self’ or the “I,” is always in the present. “Time flows 
the ‘now/ ” he may feel to be a quite expressive metaphor, 
it' sbuncis all right — until he suddenly comes to his senses and, 
a start, realizes, “But surely the moment files?” (Query: How 

,i,^ l 0 -$iicceed in wasting time? Answer: In this way, for instance — ^by 

'With eyes closed or staring vacantly in front of oneself, to 
the present moment as it is Sitting by.) He may come now to 
at matters in a different way. He sees himself advancing through 
*i towards the future, and with this goes a suggestion of being 
/ ' active^ Just as at other times he may see himself floating down the 
"fe'^eam whether he likes it or not. “'^ai exactly is it that is moving 
events in time or the present moment?” he may wonder. In 
' the first case, it looks to him as if time were mo\4ng while he stands 
; still; in the second case as if he were moving through time. “How 
exactly is it,” he may say in a dubious voice, “am I always in the 

■ present? Is the present always eluding me?” Both ring true in a way; 
tsut they contradict each other. Again, does ii make sense to ask, 

' ^At what time is the present moment?” Yes. no doubt; but how 
can it, if the “now” is but the fixed point from which the dating 
: of any event ultimately receives its sense? 

So he is pulled to and fro: “I am always in the present, yet it 
slips through my fingers; I am going for^'ard in time — no, I am 
carried down the stream.” He is using different pictures, each in its 
way quite appropriate to the accasion; yet when be tries to apply 
them jointly they clash. “Wffiat a queer thing time must be,” he may 
; say to himself with a puzzled look on his face, "’what after all is time?” 

■ — expecting, half-expecting perhaps, that the answer will reveal to 
him time’s hidden essence. Ranged beyond the inteliecmal are deeper 

-- levels of uneasiness — terror of the ineviiabilin’ of lime's passage, with 
- all the reflections upon life that this forces upon us. Now all these 
I anxious doubts release themselves in the question. “What is time?” 

, (En passant this is a hint that one answer will never do — will never 
remove all these doubts that break out afresh on different levels and 
y-"yet'are expressed in the same form of words.) 
r As we all know what time is and yet cannot say what it is it 
; : feels^ mystifying; and precisely because of its elusiveness it catches 
our imagination. The more we look at it the more we are puzzled: 
charged with paradoxes. “What is time? W^at is this being 
op of movement only without anything that is moving?” 

How funny to have it bottled up! “Tve got here 



It may be well at this point to remind ourselves that the words 
^'question” and '‘answer/’ “problem” and “solution” are not always 
used in their most trite sense. It is quite obvious that we often have 
to do something very^ different to find the way out of a difficulty. A 
problem of politics is solved by adopting a certain line of action, 
the problems of novelists perhaps by the invention of devices for 
presenting the inmost thoughts and feelings of their characters; there 
is the painter’s problem of how to suggest depth or movement on 
the canvas, the stylistic problem of expressing things not yet cur- 
rent, not yet turned into cliche; there are a thousand questions of 
technology which are answered, not by the discovery of some truth, 
but by a practical achievement; and there is of course the “social 


[ 350 ] FRIEDRICH WAISMAKH 

in my hand the most potent, the most enigmatic, the most fleeting 
of all essences — ^Time.” (Logan Pearsall Smith of an hour-glass.) 
For Shelley it is an “unfathomable sea! whose waves are years,” a 
“shoreless flood,” for Proust — ^weE, why not leave something to the 
reader? 

But isn’t the answer to this that what mystifies us lies in the 
noun form “the time”? Having a notion embodied in the form of a 
noun almost irresistibly makes us turn round to look for what it is 
“the name of.” We are trying to catch the shadows cast by the 
opacities of speech. A wrong analogy absorbed into the forms of 
our language produces mental discomfort; (and the feeling of dis- 
comfort, wffien it refers to language, is a profound one). “AH sounds, 
all colors . . . evoke indefinite and yet precise emotions, or, as I 
prefer to think, call down among us certain disembodied powers 
whose footsteps over our hearts we call emotions” (W. B. Yeats). 

Yet the answer is a prosaic one: don’t ask what time is but how 
the word “time” is being used. Easier said than done; for if the 
philosopher rectifies the use of language, ordinary^ language has “the 
advantage of being in possession of declensions,” to speak with 
Lichienberg, and thus renews its spell over him, luring him on into 
the shadow^ chase. It is perhaps only when we turn to languages of 
a widely different grammatical structure that the way towards such 
possibilities of interpretation is entirely barred- “It is^ highly probable 
that philosophers within the domain of the Ural-Altaic langcages 
(where the subject-concept is least developed) will look differently 
‘into the world’ and be found on paths of thought different from 
those of the Indo-Europeans or Mussulmans” (Nietzsche). 




1 See FMlosaphy [ 351 J 

In pMosophy, the real problem is not to find the answer 
question but to find a sense for it. 

.-' To ^ “solution’^ of such a “problem” consists let 

’ll ^ait' with Achilles who, according to Zeno, is to this day chasing 
f"-'''’" V"' tie" tortoise. Suppose that Achilles runs twice as fast as the tor- 
't^se. If the tortoise’s start is 1, Achilles will have to cover suc- 
c^ssively 1, . . . ; this series is endless: so he can never 

’ catch the tortoise. “Nonsense!” (a mathematician’s voice), “the 
ytm of the infinite series is finite, namely 2, and that settles it.” 
Though perfectly true, his remark is not to the point. It does not 
• ■ ■ remove tiie sting from the puzzle, the disconcerting idea, namely, 

that however far we go in the series there is always a next term, that 
the lead the tortoise has in the race, though naturally getting smaller 
and smaller, yet never ceases to be: there can be no moment when 
It is strictly zero. It is this feature of the case, I suggest, that we do 
not understand and which throws us into a state of confusion. 

I But look at it this way. Suppose that we apply the same sort of 
argument to a minute, then we shall have to argue in some such way 
as this. Before the minute can be over the first half of it must elapse, 
then one-quarter of it, then one-eighth of it, and so on ad infinitum. 
This being an endless process, the minute can never come to an end. 
Immediately we have the argument in this form, the blunder leaps 
to the eye: we have been confusing two senses of “never,” a temporal 
and a non-temporal one. While it is quite correct to say that the se- 
quence 1, ^4, Vs, . . . never ends, this sense of the word “never” 

has nothing whatever to do with time. .All it means is that there is 
no last term in the series, or (what comes to the same} that to any 
term, no matter how^ far out in the sequence, a successor can be 
constructed according to the simple rale “halve it”: that is meant 
here by “never”; whereas in saying, for instance, that man will never 
find out anything to avert death, “never” is meant in the sense “at 
no time.” It is clear that the mathematical assenion concerning the 
■ possibility of going on in the sequence by forming new terms according 
'• - . ^ the rule does not state anything about actual occurrences in time. 

... ^e mistake should really be obvious: in saying that, since the start 
r-r.- n getting progressively smaller and yet can never cease to be, 
Aclffles can never catch the tortoise, we jump from the mathe- 
wn-temporal to the temporal sense. Had there been two dif- 
words in our language to mark these senses the confusion could 
arisen, and the world would be poorer for one of its 
tr attractive paradoxes. But the same w^ord is as a matter of course 

lased with different meanings. Result: something like a conjuring 






I Philosophy , [ 353 } 

in fa¥or of a three-valiied logic with ‘‘possible” as a 
/ 'diird tmth-valiie alongside “true” and “false.”) 

f ■ " ^ The way out is clear enough. The asker of the question has fallen 

I • Mo the error of so many philosophers: of giving an answer before 
. stopping to consider the question. For is he clear what he is asking? 
I- ' He to suppose that a statement referring to an event in the 
I*' ' r „ future is at present undecided, neither true nor false, but that when 

I' ' the event happens the proposition enters into a sort of new state, 

f- ■ that of being true. But how are we to figure the change from “un- 

f ' / ■ dedded” to “true”? Is it sudden or gradual? At what moment does 
i - the statement “it will rain tomorrow” begin to be true? When the 

f , ’ first drop falls to the groimd? And supposing that it will not rain, 

%- when will the statement begin to be false? Just at the end of the day, 

1: a 12 p.m. sharp? Supposing that the event has happened, that the 

r statement is true, will it remain so for ever? If so, in what way? 

- Does it remain uninterruptedly true, at evory moment of day and 
night? Even if there were no one about to give it any thought? Or 
is it true only at the moments when it is being thought of? In that 

I case, how long does it remain true? For the duration of the thought? 

|v We wouldn’t know how to answer these questions; this is due not 

I to any particular ignorance or stupiditj^ on our part but to the fact 

that something has gone wrong with the way the words “true” and 
I “false” are applied here. 

I If I say, “It is true that I was in America,” I am saying that I 

was in America and no more. That in uttering the words “It is true 
Ir that — ” I take responsibility upon myself is a different matter that 

I does not concern the present argument. The point is that in making 

|: a statement prefaced by the words “It is true that” I do not add any- 

I thing to the factual information I give you. Saying that something 

f. is true is not making it true: cp. the criminal lying in court, yet every 

I time he is teUing a lie protesting, Ms hand on his heart, that he is 

] telling the truth. 

- What is characteristic of the use of the words “true” and “false” 

1i and what the pleader of logical determinism has failed to notice is 
this. “It is true” and “it is false,” while they certainly have the force 
■ ' of asserting and denying, are not descriptive. Suppose that someone 

says, “It is true that the sun will rise tomorrow” all it means is that 
. ’ ^ sun will rise tomorrow: he is not regaling us with an extra- 

C;;:. V of the tmeness of what he says. But supposing that he 

'L V. y- ^ instead, “It is true now that the sun win rise tomorrow,” 
would boil down to something like “The sun will rise tomorrow 


n 


[ 354 ] FRIEDRICH WMSMANN 

now”; which is nonsense. To ask, as the puzzle-poser does, “Is it 
true or false now that such-and-snch will happen in the future?’’ 
is not the sort of question to which an answer can be given: which 
is the answer. 

This sheds light on what has, rather solemnly, been termed the 
“timeiessness of truth.” It lies in this that the clause “it is true 
that — ” does not allow of inserting a date. To say of a proposition 
like “Diamond is pure carbon” that it is true on Christmas Eve 
would be just as poor a joke as to say that it is true in Paris and not 
in Timbuctoo. (This does not mean that we cannot say in certain 
circumstances, “Yes, it was true in those days” as this can clearly 
be paraphrased without using the word “true.”) 

Now it begins to look a bit less paradoxical to say that when a 
philosopher w'ants to dispose of a question the one thing he must 
not do is: to give an answer. A philosophic question is not solved: it 
<d/-ssolves. And in what does the “dissolving” consist? In making the 
meaning of the w^ords used in putting the question so clear to our- 
selves that we are released from the spell it casts on us. Confusion 
was removed by calling to mind the use of language or, so far as 
the use can be distilled into rules, the rules: it therefore a con- 
fusion about the use of language, or a confusion about rules. It is 
here that philosophy and grammar meet. 

There is one further point that needs elucidation. Wnen we say 
of a given assertion, e.g. “It is raining,” that it is true we can hardly 
escape the impression that we say something “about” the assertion, 
namely, that it has the property of trueness. To make such a state- 
ment seems, then, to say more than what was asserted origmaliy, 
namely, that it is raining and that this assertion is true. That, how- 
ever, leads to queer consequences. For in v/hich sense does it say 
more? Consider first under w'hich circumstances it would be appro- 
priate to say of tw^o given propositions that the one says “more” 
than the other. “This is red” says more than “this is colored” for 
the obvious reason that anyone can conclude from the first statement 
to the second but no one reversely; similarly “today is Tuesday” 
says more than “today is a weekday.” The criterion, then, suggests 
itself that, given two propositions p and q, p says more than q, ii 
^p. q is meaningful and p, ^q contradictory. The holder of the 
view that “p is true” says more than p {p standing e.g. for “It is 
raining”), may now be challenged to explain what he means by 
that. Is he using the word “more” in the sense just explained? If so, 
the curious consequence ensues that it must make sense to assert 



[ 355 ] 

that is in our case, “It is not true that it is 
it is raining.” Since this obviously is not what he had 
what does he mean? We are not contradicting him; we 
him of how these words have always been used by 
lion-philosophical contexts that is, and then point out that, 
stiQ wants to use them in this sense, to say what he wanted to 
lands him in an absurdity. All we do is to make Mm aware 
his own practice. We abstain from any assertion. It is for Mm to 
what he means. Not that he cannot do it. In ascribing truth 
a ^ven statement, he might say, he wants to express perhaps 
cither (i) that it is “in accordance with fact” or sometMng of the 
sort; or (ii) that he knows that it is true. In the first case he is faced 
the same dilemma, namely, that it must make sense to say, 
"It is not in accordance with the facts that it is raining and it is 
raining”; in the second fresh diMculties are breaking out. For one 
thing, the words “it is true that — v/hen uttered by different people, 
then mean different things; for another, and this is more fatal 
to the advocate of fatalism, in construing the words in this sense, 
he cuts the ground from under Ms own feet. No one would then be 
worried by the question whether, supposing that it is false now^ 
that he will write a certain letter tomorrow, it follows that it will 
really be impossible for him to write that letter, that this line of 
conduct is barred to him, logically barred. For since “it is false 
sow” means in the new^ sense “he doesn't know yet” nothing follows 
and the whole question evaporates. 

My reason for going into this tangle at some length is that the 
method applied in unravelling it presents some interesting features. 
First, we don’t jorce our interlocutor. We leave him free to choose, 
accept or reject any w^ay of using his words. He may depart from 
ordinaiy usage — language is not untouchable — if it is only in this 
way that he can explain himself. He may even use an expression 
one time in tMs, another time in that, way. The only thing we insist 
upon is that he should be aware of what he is doing. If w^e strictly 
adhere to tMs method — going over the argument, asidng him at each 
tep whether he is willing to use an expression in a certain w^ay, if 
offering Mm alternatives, but leaving the decisions to Mm and 
pointing out what their consequences are — no dispute can arise. 

arise only if certain steps in tMs procedure are omitted so 
t looks as if we had made an assertion, adding to the world’s 
a new apple of discord. This would be the true way of doing 
undogmatically. The diMculty of this method lies in 



[ 356 ] FMEDRICH WAISMANK 

presenting the subject in a manner which can easily be taken in 

in arranging the cases and the ways in which they are connected 
through intermediate links so that we can gain a clear synoptic view 
of the whole. 

Second, we do not use arguments in order to prove or disprove 
any “philosophic view.” As we have no views we can afford to look 
at things as they are. 

Next, we only describe; we do not “explain.” An explanation, 
in the sense of a deductive proof, cannot satisfy us because it pushes 
the question “Why just these rules and no other ones?” only one 
stage back. In following that method, we do not want to give rea- 
sons. AH we do is to describe a use or tabulate rules. In doing this, 
we are not making any discoveries: there is nothing to be discovered 
in grammar. Grammar is autonomous and not dictated by reality. Giv- 
ing reasons, bound as it is to come to an end and leading to something 
which cannot further be explained, ought not to satisfy us. In gram- 
mar we never ask the question “why?” 

But isn’t the result of this that philosophy itself “dissolves’’? 
Philosophy eliminates those questions which can be eliminated by 
such a treatment. Not all. of them, though: the metaphysician’s crav- 
ing that a ray of light may fall on the mystery of the existence of this 
w’orld, or on the incomprehensible fact that it is comprehensible, 
or on the “meaning of life” — even if such questions could be shown 
to lack a clear meaning or to be devoid of meaning altogether, they 
are not silenced. It does nothing to lessen the dismay they rouse in 
us. Tiiere is something cheap in “debunking” them. The heart’s 
unrest is not to be stilled by logic. Yet philosophy is not dissolved. 
It derives its weight, its grandeur, from the significance of the ques- 
tions it destroys. It overthrow's idols, and it is the importance of these 
idols which gives philosophy its importance. 

Now^ it can perhaps be seen why the search for answers fitting 
the moulds of the questions fails, is bound to fail. They are not real 
questions asking for information but “muddles felt as problems” 
(Wittgenstein) which wither aw^ay w^hen the ground is cleared. If 
philosophy advances, it is not by adding new propositions to its list, 
but rather by transforming the whole intellectual scene and, as a 
consequence of this, by reducing the number of questions w^hich 
befog and bedevil us. Philosophy so construed is one of the great 
liberating forces. Its task is, in the words of Frege, “to free the 
spirit from the tyranny of words by exposing the delusions which 
arise, almost inevitably, through the use of a word language.” 


m'-t'See Fhilosaphy 


[357 ] 




.-j* ’ ' ■ Wbat, only criticism and no meat? The philosopher a fog dispeller? 
^ lij^i all he was capable of I would be sorry for him and leave 
his devices. Fortunately, this is not so. For one thing, a 
^" 'pfiiosopMc question, if pursued far enough, may lead to something 
' ‘ ^^live— for instance, to a more profound understanding of language. 

. ^ke the sceptical doubts as to material objects, other minds, etc. 

tfe first reaction is perhaps to say: these doubts are idle. Ordinarily, 

~ when I doubt whether I shall ^sh this article, after a time my 
- ifoubt comes to an end. I cannot go on doubting for ever. It’s the 
destiny of doubt to die. But the doubts raised by the sceptic never 
cSe. Are they doubts? Are they pseudo-questions? They appear so 
onl}’' when judged by the twin standards of common sense and 
common speech. The real trouble lies deeper: it arises from the 
sceptic casting doubt on the very facts which underlie the use of 
language, those permanent features of experience which make con- 
cept formation possible, which in fact are precipitated in the use of 
om most common words. Suppose that you see an object in front 
of you quite clearly, say, a pipe, and when you are going to pick it 
up it melts into thin air, then you may feel, ‘‘Lord, I’m going mad” 
or something of the sort (unless the whole situation is such that you 
have reason to suspect that it was some clever trick). But w^hat, the 
sceptic may press now, if such experiences were quite frequent? 
Would you be prepared to df^olve the connection between different 
sense experiences which form the hard core of our idea of a solid 
object, to undo what language has done — ^to part with the category 
of thing-hood? And would you then be living in a phenomenalist’s 
paradise with color patches and the other paraphernalia of the sense- 
datum theory, in a disobjected, desubstantialized world? To say in 
such circumstances, “Lx)ok, it’s just tabling now” would be a joke 
(for even in the weakened verb forms “tabling,” “chairing” an 
element of the thing-category lingers on). That is why the sceptic 
... Struggles to express himself in a language which is not fit for this 
■ purpose. He expresses himself misleadingly when he says that he 
such-and-such facts: his doubts cut so deep that they affect the 
. fehnc of language itself. For what he doubts is already embodied in the 
speech, e,g. in what is condensed in the use of thing- 
J^ouient he tries to penetrate those deep-sunken layers, he 
/ ■ language in which he ventilates his qualms — ^with the 




ifeh 

Iff; : ■■ 






[ 358 ] FMEDHICH WAISMaNH 

result that he seems to be talking nonsense. He is not. But in order' 
to make his doubts fully expressible, language would first have to 
go into the melting-pot. (We can get a glimmering of what is needed 
from modem science where all the long-established categories—, 
tfainghood, causality, position — ^had to be revolutionized. This re- 
quired nothing less than the construction of some new language, not 
the expression of new facts with the old one.) 

If we look at the matter in this way the attitude of the sceptic 
is seen in a new light. He considers possibilities which lie far outside 
the domain of our current experience. If his doubts are taken seriously, 
they turn into observations which cast a new and searching light 
on the subsoil of language, showing what possibilities are open to 
our thought (though not to ordinan^ language), and what paths 
might have been pursued if the texture of our experience were 
different from w’hat it is. These problems are not spurious: they 
make us av/are of the vast background in which any current experi- 
ences are embedded, and to which language has adapted itself; thus 
they bring out the unmeasured sum of experience stored up in the 
use of our words and syntactical forms. 

For another thing, a question may decide to go in for another 
career than dissolving: it may pass into science. Frege, for instance, 
was prompted to his inquiries by philosophical motives, namely, 
to find a definite answer to the question about the nature of arith- 
metical truths — ^whether they are analnic or s>mthetic, a priori or 
a posteriori. Starting from this question and pursuing it with all 
possible rigor, he was led to unearth a whole mine of problems of a 
scientific nature; and proceeding along these lines, he came to fashion 
a new' instrument, a logic, which in delicacy and range and power 
far surpassed anything that went by this name before, a subject 
revealing to this day new and unexpected depths. True, the question 
from which Frege set out was not too clearly defined owing to the 
imprecise nature of the Kantian terms in which it was expressed. 

A w^hoie chapter might be written on the fate of questions, their 
curious adventures and transformations — how they change into 
others and in the process remain, and yet do not remain, the same. 
The original question may split and multiply almost like a character 
in a dream play. To mention just a few examples: can logic be 
characterized completely in a formal way, i.e. without bringing in 
any extraneous ideas such as the use of language and all that goes 
with it? Can arithmetic be characterized in any such way, entirely 
“from within”? Or will any interpretation include some Erdenrest 
of the empiric? These questions have given rise to extensive research 




Wgm ? Fhihsopky [ 359 ] 

mathematical interpretation of formal systems. The query how 
lo^ca! intuition is correct has got ramified into a bunch of ques- 
pertaining to the theory of logical types, the axiom of choice, 
“indeed to a far more fundamental issue, namely, whether 
i^dhiaiy logic itself is ‘"right” as contrasted with the system of 
fcfOTSces evolved by the intuitionists. Or again, are there undecid- 
'* questions in mathematics, not in the restricted sense of G5del, 

''-'lull imdecidable in an absolute sense? Are there natural limits to 
’ S'" generalization? It is interesting to watch how from a question of this 

not too precise, somewhat blurred, new and better defined 
>{; detach themselves, the parent question — ^in Frege’s case 

. S l^nlosophic par excellence — giving rise to a scientist’s progeny. 

- • ’ Now something else must be noted — ^how^ these questions become, 
not only precise, but clear (which is not the same thing). To illustrate, 
can the infinity represented by ail natural numbers be compared with 
the infinity represented by all points in space? That is, can the one 
be said to be less than, or equal to, the other? When it was first asked, 
the question had no clear sense — ^perhaps no sense at all. Yet it 
^ gmdfii G. Cantor in his ingenious search. Before set theory was 
discovered — or should I rather say “invented”? — ^the question acted 
as a sort of signpost pointing vaguely to some so far uncharted 
' - region of thought. It is perhaps best characterized by saying that it 

guides our imagination in a given direction, stimulates research 
along new lines. Such questions do not “dissolve” : they are solved, 
only not in the existing system of thought but rather by constructing 
a new conceptual system — such as set theory — ^where the intended 
and faintly anticipated sense finds its full realization. Tliey are there- 
• foie of the nature of incitements to the building of such systems, they 

point from the not-yet-meaningful to the meaningful. 

The question is the first groping step of the mind in its joumeyings 
. - : &at lead towards new horizons. The genius of the philosopher shows 
; . itself nowhere more strikingly than in the new kind of question he 

bmgs into the world. Wliat distinguishes him and gives him his 
- ; : place is the passion of questioning. That his questions are at times 

• , not so clear is perhaps of not so much moment as one makes of it. 

is nothing like clear thinking to protect one from making dis- 
It is ail very well to talk of clarity, but when it becomes an 
it is liable to nip the living thought in the bud. This, I am 
^ deplorable results of Logical Positivism, not 

^ founders, but only too striking in some of its followers. 
at these people, gripped by a clarity neurosis, haunted by fear, 
tongue-tied, asking themselves continually, “Oh dear, now does this 


1 









make perfectly good sense?” Imagine the pioneers of science, Kepler 
Newton, the discoverers of non-Enclidean geometry, of field physics* 
the unconscious, matter waves or heaven knows what imagine thein 
asking themselves this question at every step — ^this would have been 
the surest means of sapping any creative power. No great discoverer 
has acted in accordance with the motto, “Everything that can be said 
can be said clearly.” And some of the greatest discoveries have even 
emerged from a sort of primordial fog. (Something to be said for 
the fog. For my part, Tve always suspected that clarity is the last 
refuge of those who have nothing to say.) 

The great mind is the great questioner. An example in point is 
Kant’s problem “How is geometiy^ possible?” The way to its solution 
was only opened up through the rise of the “axiomatic method.” 
Seeing that the axioms of geometrv' are capable of an indefinite 
number of different interpretations and that the particular way they 
may be interpreted is irrelevant to deductive purposes, Hilbert 
separated what belongs to the logical fomi of the Axioms from what 
belongs to their intuitional (or other) content and turned the whole 
question by saying: a point, a straight line, etc., may be anything 
that satisfies the axioms. As the business of deduction hinges only 
on the relations in which the basic terms stand to each otfaer^and not 
on the “content” we associate with them, and as these relations are 
fully set out in the axioms, the axioms in their totality^ determine 
what a “point,” a “line,” etc., is so far as it is sufficient for deductive 
needs. TTirough the rise of this technique it became an parent that the 
word “geometry’,” as understood by Kant, covers, in fact, two totally 
different sciences, mathematical and physical geometry’. It was the 
failure to distinguish between them that produced KanVs perplexity. 
“So far as the laws of mathematics refer to reality’, they are not 
certain; and so far as they are certain, they do no: refer to reality” 
(Einstein). Kant’s credit lies in having seen that there is a problem, 
not in having solved it. 

But here a new problem presents itself; How do vve know what 
will satisfy a given question? More genei'ally: How does the answer 
St the question? Questions of the current sort (“What is the right 
time?”) show already by their form wffiat sort of aiis\ver to expect. 
They are, so to speak, cheques with a blank to be filled; yet not 
always so: Augustine’s question, “How is it possible to measure 
time?” or Kant’s question, “How is geometry possible?” do not trace 
out the form of the answer. There is no obvious hnk between ques- 
tion and answer, any more than there is in the case of asking “What 
is a point?” When Hilbert’s idea — ^that the axioms of geometiy 







f&^-fSee PMlosopny ^ l — j 

-^vide the “implicit definition” of the basic terms — ^was 
^Irowunded it came totally unexpected; no one had ever thou^t 
tefore; on the contrary, many people had an tmeasy feehng 
■ if this were a way of evading the issue rather than an answer, 
. ^longst them no less a man than Frege. He thought the problem 

^^^is^^ere anything one can do to make a man like Frep see 
that the axiomatic method provides the correct answer? Can it, for 
e^ple be proved to him? The point to which attention must now 
be dmvm, though it should really be obvious, is that such a proof 
taomot be' riven, and it cannot because he, the asker, has &st to be 
tnmed round to see the matter differently. What is required is a 
change of the entire way of thinking. Indeed, anyone who is pu2zled 
by this problem and yet refuses to accept Hilbert’s solution only 
betrays &at he has got stuck in the groove hollowed out by the form 
in which the question is put. “A point is — ” he begins and then stops. 
What is to be done to help him to get out of the groove or,^ better 
still, to make him shift for himself when he feels “cramped” in it, 
is a discussion, not a proof. 

Fre^e behaves not so very unlike a man mystified by the question, 
“What Is time?” We may suggest converting the latter into the 
question how the word “time” “is being used (which would bring 
him down to earth) . But aren’t we cheating him? We seem to be 
holding out the answ'er to one question, but not to that one which 
he was asking. He may suspect that we are tiy^ing to fob him oS with 
the second best we have in'store, his original question still remaining 
an enigma. Similarly Frege; he considered it a scandal thai. the 
questions “What is a point?” “What is a number?” were still un- 
answered. 

In either of these cases, the aim of a discussion, in the absence 
of a proof, can only be to change the asker’s attitude. We may, for 
instance, scrutinize similar, or partially similar, cases, point out that 
the form of the answer is not always that of the question; by going 
patiently over such cases, the vast background oi analogies against 
.which the question is seen wHl slowly change. The turning up oi a 

■ Wide field of language loosens the position of certain standards 
.'r’lriiich are so ingrained that we do not see them for what they are; 
.and if we do this in an effective manner, a mind like Frege s wili be 
released from the obsession of seeking strainingly for an answer to 

■ fit the mould. Arguments are used in such a discussion, not as proofs 
;;ti 30 ugh but rather as means to make him see things he had not 
jjsfoticed before; e.g. to dispel wrong analogies, to stress similarities 



[ ] FEIEDBJCH WAISMaNH 

with Other cases and in this way to bring about something like a 
shift of perspective. However, there is no way of proving him wrong 
or bullying him into mental acceptance of the proposal; when all is 
said and done the decision is Ms. 

But here more is at stake than loosening a cramped position-—. 
it is a question of escaping the domination of linguistic forms. How 
often are we merely following the channels carved out by numberless 
repetition of the same modes of expression — as when we say, un- 
suspectingly, “lime flows” and are, when confronted (say) with 
Augustine’s paradox, suddenly shocked out of complacency. Exist- 
ing language, by offering us only certain sterot}^d moulds of ex- 
pression, creates habits of thought wMch it is almost impossible to 
break. Such a mould is, e.g. the actor-action scheme of the Indo- 
European languages. How deep their influence is can perhaps be 
surmised from Descartes’ conclusion from thinking to the presence 
of an agent, an ego, different from the thinking, that does the think- 
ing — a conclusion so natural and convincing to us because it is 
supported by the whole weight of language. Frege's obsession with 
the question “What is a number?” is another case. As we can speak 
of *'the number five,” five, Frege argued, must be the proper name of 
an entity, a sort of Platonic crystal, indicated by means of the definite 
article. (A Chinese pupil of mine once informed me that Frege’s 
question is unaskable in Chinese, “five” being used there only as a 
numeral in contexts like “five friends,” five boats,” etc.). Again, 
when w^e say of a given statement that it is true, we seem to be saying 
sometMng “about” it — evidence of the power of the subject-predicate 
cliche. Indeed, so strong is the temptation to construe it in this w’ay, 
namely, as a statement about a statement, that the idea of a different 
interpretation scarcely occurs to us. It is imponant to notice that in 
doing so we assimilate the expression to analogical forms; but it is 
no less important to notice that none of these analogies needs to be 
present to our minds: it is enough if they make themselves felt in a 
dim, inarticuiated way. Such patterns have an effect on us lilte thou- 
sands of explicit analogies: they act upon us, one might say, like a 
field of force, a language field, that draws our mental gaze in a 
certain direction. And, I venture to add, it is precisely because of 
of the fleeting, half-formed, shadow-like nature of these analogies 
that it is almost impossible to escape their influence. If we are taken 
in by them, it is our fault. A philosopher, instead of preachina the 


f^^%m^fSeePi^sophy [ _ 1 

.;'_^ swimnier must be able to swim up-stream, so the philos^ 
master the imspeakabiy difficult art of thinking up-speech, 

another point. When we dissuade a man like Frep 

search, we seem to be hmderiiig him from reaching &e 
get out to reach. Does our discussion clash, then, with his 
®^eh? And, if so, in which way? First of all, in no clearly definable 
for he is not yet clearly aware what he is aiming at, and the 
“‘i -'Sssion brings him gradually to see things in a different light. How 
change brought about? WeU, he first saw the question m 
^om with other ones, and these analogies are, one by one, de- 
or rather, in the course of the discussion they are seen to 
' - L Reading. In proportion as the whole conceptual background 

^ changes he comes to see that something is wrong with the way he 
puts his question, that the attainment of his object is no longer 
^tisfying. It is not that he gives up because he has tried very hard, 
but in vain, and has now got tired: no, he gives up because he 
**sees” the question differently. And in what does this consist? Well 
ffl the fact that he is now well aware of the analogies which were 
’misleading him, that he sees the question against a different linguistic 
background (a ‘‘figure” sometimes changes when it is seen against 
a different “ground”), that a certain strain disappears and that he 
says, with a sigh of relief, “Yes, that’s it.” 

The philosopher contemplates things through the prism ot 
language and, misled (say) by some analogy, suddenly sees thing* 
In a new strange light. We can cope with these problems only by 
di^ng dovvm to the" soil from which they spring. What we do is to 
fight up the mental background from which the question has de- 
tached itself; in a clearer perception of some of the crucial concepts 
the question transforms itself into another one. Not that it has been 
answered in the current sense. Rather we have removed the factors 
that prompted the question by a more profound and penetrating 
analysis. The essence of this process is that it leads the questioner 
on to some new aspect — and leads him with his spontaneous consent. 

■ :Hb agrees to be thus led and therefore ends by abandoning his 
- search. We caimot constrain anyone who is unwilling to follow the 
' mvr direction of a question; we can only extend the field of vision 
of the asker, loosen his prejudices, guide his gaze in a new direction: 
c . ; / . . tet ail this can be achieved only with his consent. 

our critical analysis we try to counteract the influence of 
t ; ...the language field, or (what comes to the same) we may help the 


1 :.: 




[ 3^ ] FRIEDRICH WAlSUmn 

questioner to gain a deeper insight into the nature of what he is 
seeking first of all — ^make him see the build of the concepts and 
the moulds in which he expresses the question. VlTiat matters is 
more like changing his outlook than proving to him some theorem; 
or more like increasing his insight. Insight cannot be lodged in a 
theorem, and this is the deeper reason why the deductive method is 
doomed to fail; insight cannot be demonstrated by proof. 

What it comes to in the end is that the asker of the question, in 
the course of the discussion, has to make a number of decisions. 
And this makes the philosophical procedure so unlike a logical 
one. He compares, for instance, the case before him with analogous 
ones and has to judge how far these analogies hold. That is, it is for 
him to decide how far he is willing to accept these analogies: he has 
not, like a slave, to follow blindly in their track. 

Science is rich in questions of this type. They are not scientific 
questions properly and yet they exercise scientists, they are philo- 
sophic questions and yet they do not exercise philosophers. 

WTiat I have wanted to say in this section and have not said, 
or only half-said: 

(1) Philosophy is not only criticism of language: so construed, 
its aim is too na^^ow^ It is criticizing, dissolving and stepping over all 
prejudices, loosening all rigid and constricting^moulds of thought, 
no matter whether they have their origin in language or somewhere 
else. 

(2) What is essential in philosophy is the breaking through to a 
deeper insight — ^which is something positive — ^not merely the dis- 
sipation of fog and the exposure of spurious problems. 

(3) Insight cannot be lodged in a theorem, and it can therefore 
not be demonstrated. 

(4) Philosophic arguments are, none of them, logically com- 
pelling: they really screen what actually happens — the quiet and 
patient undermining of categories over the whole field of thought. 

(5) Their purpose is to open our eyes, to bring us to see things 
in a new way — ^from a wider standpoint unobstructed by misunder- 
standings. 

(6) The essential difference between philosophy and logic is that 
logic constrains us while philosophy leaves us free: in a philosophic 
discussion we are led, step by step, to change our angle of vision, 
e.g. to pass from one way of putting a question to another, and this 
with our spontaneous agreement — a thing profoundly different from 
deducing theorems from a given set of premises. Misquoting Cantor 
one might say: the essence of philosophy lies in its freedom.. 


5ec FhUosophy 


[365 ] 


■?- 




IV 


'^ere is a notion that philosophy is an exercise of the intellect 
&^"that philosophic questions can be settled by argument, and con- 
" ^ knew how to set about it. What seems to me 

however, is that I cannot find any really good hard argument; 
' l^iBore that, the example just discussed must make it doubt- 
'fid whether any compelling argument can be found. Out of this 
I incline to come to a new and somewhat shocking conclusion: 

- mat the thing cannot be done. No philosopher has ever proved any- 
The whole claim is spurious. What I have to say is simply 
Ihis. Philosophic arguments are not deductive; therefore they are 
Slot rigorous; and therefore they don’t prove anything. Yet they 
have force. 

Before going into the matter, I want to show, quite summarily 
first, how unpiausible the view is that rigorous arguments are applied 
in philosophy. A first alarming sign can perhaps already be seen in 
the notorious fact that the ablest minds disagree, that what is indis- 
putable to the one seems to have no force in the eyes of the other. 
In a clear system of thought such differences are impossible. That 
they exist in philosophy is Vr'eighty evidence that the arguments have 
none of the logical rigor they have in mathematics and the exact 
sciences. 

Next, arguments, in the way they are thought of, must contain 
inferences, and inferences must start somewhere. Now where is the 
philosopher to look for his premises? To science? Then he will ‘"do” 
science, not philosophy. To statements of everyday life? To particular 
ones? Then he will never be able to advance a single step beyond 
them. To general statements? If so, a number of questions raise 
their ugly heads. By what right does he pass from “some” to “all”? 
(“To Generalize is to be an Idiot,” W, Blake.} Can he be sure that 
his premises are stated with such clarity and precision that not 
a ghost of a doubt can creep in? Can he be sure that they contain 
aieat, are not anal3d;ic, vacuous, definitions in disguise and the like? 
Can he be sure that they are true? (How can he?) And even sup- 
posing, what is not the case, that all these requirements could be 
TOt, there is still another task looming before him when it comes 
-to /developing the consequences: can he be sure how to operate with 
^ terms? (How can he?) I am not letting out a secret when I say 
that the ordinary rules of logic often break down in natural speech — 
a fact usually hushed up by logic books. Indeed, the words of com- 


[ 366 ] FRIEDRICH WAISMANK 

mon language are so elastic that anyone can stretch their seme to fit 
Ms own whims; and with tMs their “logic” is queered. (Plenty of 
scope for a “natural logic”; we know that we are unhappy; so we 
are unhappy. We know that we are unhappy; so we are great, Pascal. 
“If she had perished, she had perished:” does this entail that she has 
not perished? If so, by what rule? “If I believed that I should be very 
silly indeed:” does this, or does tMs not, entail that I don’t believe 
it? Natural language holds logical problems of its own, lots of them.) 

This brings me to another point Ordinary language simply has 
not got the “hardness,” the logical hardness, to cut axioms in it. It 
needs something like a metallic substance to carve a deductive system 
out of it such as Euclid’s. But common speech? If you begin to draw 
inferences it soon begins to go “soft” and fluffs up somew^here. You 
may just as w^ell carve cameos on a cheese souffle. (My point is: 
language is plastic, yielding to the will to express, even at the price 
of some obscurity. Indeed, how' could it ever express anytMng that 
does not conform to the cliche? If logicians had their way, language 
would become as dear and transparent as glass, but also as brittle 
as glass: and what would be the good of making an axe of glass that 
breaks the moment you use it?) But language is not hard. And that 
is why it is dangerous in pMlosophy to hunt for premises instead of 
just going over the ground, standing back and saying: look. 

Most pbilosopmc arguments, to ignore constructions a la Spinoza, 
hinge on such points as what “can” and what “cannot” be said or 
what sort of question it is “proper” and what sort of question it 
would be “inappropriate” to ask. Much skill and ingenuity' has been 
spent in elucidating such questions as to whether a certain metaphor 
is “natural,” a certain diction “fitting.” It would not be right to 
burke the point that considerations such as these, w'hile apparently 
pertaining to matters of style, contribute in fact largely to the force- 
fulness of an argument, indeed play a very real and decisive part in 
the way they make us look at the subject. In going over, examining 
and comparing the various modes of expression that center around 
certain key notions, for instance, “imagination,” “memory,” “pleas- 
ure,” we catch the first glimpse of what is sometimes called the 
“logic” of these notions. Now can any of these things be proved? 
Can it be proved, for example, that a certain diction is “fitting”? 
(Remember, no such thing as a definition of a “well-formed form- 
ula.”) No philosopher has ever made so much as an attempt. Every- 
one uses words in this way and he leaves it at that; and rightly so. 
For what sort of reasons could he give anyway? Here already, at the 
very threshold, the idea of a philosopMc proof begins to ring hollow. 


See Fhilosophy [ 367 ] 

, bnt the ordinary use of language.” x4]l right; but even so, 

'4 "is i»t that one ‘‘cannot” use language differently. To illustrate: 

music” — does this “teff” you amthing? Perhaps not; yet a 
Whig hke ‘‘Architecture is frozen music” (Goethe) drives the point 
^Whe- To say “The arms are full of blunted memories” sounds odd, 
J iiatil you come upon it in Proust’s context. The “will to under- 
stand” does not even flinch before those bogies of the logician, 
contradictions: it transforms them, wresting a new sense from the 
' apparent nonsense. (“Dark with excess of light,” “the luminous 
'^oom of Plato” — ^just to remind the reader of two examples of 
0>hndgc.) There are about 303 reasons wby we sometimes express 
ourselves in a contradiction, and understandably so. 

Result; it cannot even be proved that a given expression is natural, 
a metaphor fitting, a question proper (or unaskable), a collocation 
of words expressive (or devoid of meaning). Nothing of the sort 
can be demonstrated. 

Two other points reinforce what has been said. What we some- 
times do in a philosophical discussion is not argue at all but simply 
raise lots of questions — a method brilliantly employed by Ryle. 
Indeed, a volley of perplexing questions can certainly not be de- 
scribed as an argument and a foriiori not as a logical one, yet it is 
no less effective in making one rum back in recoil to consider one’s 
views. Lastly, though on the surface the philosopher seems to be 
engaged in much the same thing as a logician is, for instance, in 
testing an argument for any loose links in it or in building up an 
argument, this should not mislead us. For if he were to construct 
rigorous proofs, where are the theorems established by them? What 
has he to show as the fruit of his labors? 

I have not raised any of these questions w^antonly; they force 
themselves on eveiy^one who tries to arrive at a clear and unbiased 
view of the matter. Should these difficulties not have their origin 
in the nature of philosophy itself? 


V 

I proceed now to consider philosophic arguments, especially 
those which are regarded as constituting a decisive advance, to see 
. whether they give us any reason for modiri’ing the view^ advocated 
here. There are only a few^ classical cases. One of them is Hume’s 
- p^i^hrated argument to show^ that the relation of cause and effect is 
ptnnsically different from that of ground and consequence. Now 
does this “proof’ consist? He reminds us of what we have 





[ 368 ] FRIEDRICH WAISMANK 

always known: that, while it is self-contradictow to assert the grotiacj 
and deny the consequence, no such contradiction arises in assuming 
that a certain event, the ‘‘cause,” may be followed not by its usual 
effect but by some other event. Ji it is asked “Is this a proof?” what 
is one to say? It certainly is not the sort of proof to be found hx 
a deductive system. Much the same applies to Berkeley’s argument 
when he tells us that, try as he might, he cannot call up in his mind 
an abstract idea of a triangle, of just a triangle with no particular 
shape, any more than he can conceive the idea of a man without 
qualities. Is this a proof? He points out the obvious. (Only it wants 
a genius to see it.) 

To take my own argument against logical fatalism, it is not strict 
The decisive step consists in follov/ing a certain analogy with other 
cases. It is analogical, not logical. Similarly the argument used 
against Zeno is not conclusive. (I have no space to enlarge upon that.) 

Now^ for tW'O more examples, one of the current sort of argument 
applied today by philosophers, the other taken from Aristotle. 

When we say of someone that he “sees” or “hears” an aeroplane, 
or “descries,” “detects” a lark in the sty, or again that he “tastes” 
or “smells” roast pork, w^e do not ascribe to him an activity. That 
“seeing” is not a sort of doing can be illustrated, e.g. by calling at- 
tention to the fact that we don’t use the continuous present tense. 
We say “I see the clock,” not “I am seeing the clock” (save G. E. 
Moore, who, oddly enough, regularly says that he “is seeing his right 
hand”), whereas it is perfectly correct to say “I am looking at the 
clock, listening to its ticking,” and so in the other cases. Again, 
while it is proper to say “I have forgotten to post the letter,” no 
one would say “I have forgotten to see the letter-box.” There is 
no sense in asking you, when you look at me, whether your seeing 
is easy or difficult, quick or slowish, careful or heedless, whether you 
see me deliberately and whether you have nov/ finished seeing me. 
So, it is argued, perceiving is not a doing (an argument used by 
myself in lectures). 

The point to be labored is that this argument is not conclusive. 
Odd as it sounds, “I have finished seeing you” may be said, though 
only in very special circumstances. A man with impaired eyesight 
who, unable to take in the shape as a whole, has perhaps to scan 
the face bit by bit in search of some characteristic marks might say, 
and understandably, “Now I have finished seeing you.” We too are 
occasionally in a not much better position, as when, in magnesium 
light, we look at some scene, and ^erwards complain, “Too quick, 
I couldn’t take it in.” It would seem then that there is no more 


• i See Philosophy *■ 

■ o difference in degree between this case and the normal ones. 
S L2f Srtainiy; bS what would you think of a mathematician 
.^^^rems cSapse when apphed to shghtly out-of-the-way 

^fr mv next example I choose pleasure. Aristotle, in critici^g 
Plato pointed out that if pleasure were a process gomg on m to 
f^d enjoy something swiftly or slowly— an ardent which is 
Almost a tombshen in its destructive power. Certainly,^ to speak in 
«:nch terms is very odd and sounds absurd. Yet, if I stram my imagi- 
TlTTcl perhaps bring myself to conceive of a set of cncum- 
under which it would not be entirely unnatural to say such 
^ T., Uctf-nino- tn muslc. for exampie, when I am foUowmg a 



to be dinereni irum wiiat x — ^ w * 

mncir Th** very quality of my eniovment seems to cnange as it 
SShiS’of S sL and geni or df the ndd. imoricating flow o 
rimsio had entered into it. If I say, in the one ease, tnat I was 
enjoying it leisurely like basking m the sun or sipping wine, in the 
other that I was suddenly carried away, breatnlessly loUowmg ite 
onrush and enjoying it like a storm at sea— ^oes tins sound hi^e sheer 
nonsense? So there does seem to be a time mctor m pleasure. 

Amongst the most pow^erful weapons in the philosopher s ry 
are reductio ad absurdum and inhnite regress arguments Before 
proceeding to an appraisal of these forms oi reasomng, it wiU be 
wen to consider how they work in their home iand_^mathema m . 

Let me choose as a typical case the proof that \' 2 is irration . 
If it were a rational number, we could nnd two integers m and n 
. such that 

t i j 

even, m must be even; hence 


m- = 2n- 


We may then argue as follow's. rt'.- is 
m = 2mi. Substitution yields 

I - 2m-r = n-. 

As is even, n must be even; hence n = 2ni. Substitution yields 
I mi" = 2ni-. 

K, then, two integers m and « exist which stand in the relation (1), 
■thev must have halves which stand in exactly the same relauon (, 

• W these must have halves which stand in the same relation ana 
:so on ad infinitum; which is plainly impossible, m and n bem|&mte. 
- ^erefore the tentative assumption (1) cannot hold, and V- 


[ 370 ] 


FRIEDRICH WAISMANN 




not be rational. Q.E.D. This is the prototype of a refutation by 
infinite regress. 

Arguments of this type have been applied outside mathematics. 
However, when I come to look at them a bit more closely I begin 
to hesitate. An example will illustrate my doubts. An argument pro- 
pounded against the use of mechanical models is this. If the elastic 
properties of matter can be explained as being due to electric 
forces with which the molecules act on each other, it surely is point* 
less to explain the action of the electric forces as being due to the 
elastic properties of a mechanical medium, the “ether.” To do this 
is to go round in a circle: elasticity is explained in terms of electric 
force, and electric force in terms of elasticity; while the attempt to 
break out of the circle by supposing that the elasticity of the ether 
is due to “electric forces” acting between the ether particles and 
these to the elastic properties of a second-order ether is to be pushed 
into an infinite series of reduction steps. Thus the mechanistic pro- 
gram is faced with a dilemma both horns of which are equally faial. 

A formidable argument — or is it? I can well imagine an un- 
daunted champion of the lost cause retort: “Not a bit of a regress. 
Yes, the ether is elastic, not, however, in the sense in which a spring 
is: while eiasticiU* of matter can be reduced to electric force, elasticity 
of the ether, being an ultimate postulate of the theor}% cannot be 
reduced any further.” And. with this the argument falls to the ground. 

But this is unconvincing, it will be said. 1 agree; I am not such 
an imbecile as to plead for retaining mechanical models and the 
rest. My point is only to see whether this “refutation” is compelRng. 
It isn't. The advocate of models is not forcibly dislodged from his 
position. There is, it would seem, always a way of getting out of 
the dilemma — of wriggling out if you like — which foils the argument. 
What is shown in it is merely that to cling ic models of this sort 
becomes, in the circumstances, vei}' unnatural. But to say that some- 
thing is unnatural is not to say that it is logically impossible: yet 
this is what the argument should establish. In the mathematical proof 
cited above no loophole was left for wriggling out. The whole de- 
duction was a “chain of adamant” — ^precisely the sort of thing the 
argument under review is not. 

Consider now a similar argument. There cannot be any such thing 
as volitions, it has been said. Volitions were called in by theorists 
to provide causes not only for what we (intentionally) do but also 
for mental processes or operations such as controlling an impulse, 
paying heed to something, and the like. As a consequence of this, 
acts of will were supposed to be the sort of thing the presence of 




Philosophy 


[ 371 ] 


makes an action “voluntary,” or wiiich — somehow, in some 

( ■''f lC'' way — “gets itself translated” into a bodily or mental 

' ' ' ' act In volitions were thought of as causes as well as effects of 
'■ii ':’ other, mental or physical, occurrences. Now the dilemma: if my 
[ •;.l . jjjjliing of the trigger were the result of a mental act of “willing to 

' pSiAe trigger,” what of this mental act itself? Was it willed or un- 
■ ' ^ed? If unwilled, it cannot be called voluntary and therefore not 
a volition; if willed, then we must suppose, according to the theory', 
that it results from a prior act, namely, “vvilling to will to pull the 
fi/'-' v:. trigger,” and that from another ad infinitum, leaving no possibility 
! ' . fot me ever to start. 

■' BrilEaiit as the argument is, the point to be brought up here is 
I?/ ’ -. v- -only whether it is logically fatal. Does it really prove that the as- 
sumption of acts of willing involves an innnite regress? A believer in 
such acts need not be cowed into submission. To ask of volitions 
whether they are themselves voiuntaiy’ or involuntaiy^ acts, he may 
' say, is plain nonsense. Only an aciion can be voluntan” or invol- 
untary, not an act of will. It is just the poin: that an act of will is 
• - an act of will and does not issue from any anterior act of will, any 
more than, in order to recall a thing I mus: first recall w^hat I warn: 
to recall, and before I can even do that I must recall that I want to 
recall w^hat I want to recall, and so on innnhum. Just as I can 

recall a thing without need to call in an act of recalling what I want 
to recall, so my pulling the trigger may be the direct result of an 
act of vail without the latter issuing from a parent act of will. Thus 
the whole argument apparently crumbles awa}'. 

This is meant not to belittle the argument or detract from its 
. force, but only to get clear as to what sor: of force it has. If it were 
conclusive, it would, with its destructive power, do away with a good 
many more acts and states of mind, no: only with volitions — with 
intending and desiring, for instance. Indeed, precisely similar argu- 
ments can be constructed ‘‘to deal wirh them.'’ Intention: though 
clearly not the sort of thing to be classed as a simple ''act.*’ ii yet 
: ^ somehow to “connect” with what goes on in us before we 

ij y: .• cany it into action — such as considering, planning, hesitating, choos- 
^ let US say, intend to find a naw in a given argument, 

i;,. and when I subsequently turn it over in my mind, this will be the 

I '7. ; • of my intention. Some mental operations, then, can arise from 

^ ^mtention, they are “intended.” So what of the intention itself? 

intended or unintended? If the intention is not intended, it is 
intention, and if it is intended it must be due to another in- 
f and this to yet another ad iniiniium. Similarly in the case 


n 





^ FRIEDRICH WAISMaKN 

of desire. Suppose that I feel a desire for a certain thing, is this 
desire itself desired or undesired? Either answer lands us in ab- 
surdities. 

If the strength of the argument were to lie in its structure it 
wo^d, with its devastating effect, apply after the exchange of some 
of Its terms for other ones, e.g. “volition” for “intention”— provided 
of course, that certain other circumstances essential to the reasoning 
are the same. Yet, whOe the first argument sounds, to say the least 
very plausible, no one will be duped by its caricatures. So if it has 
any force it cannot owe it to its structure and consequently cannot 
be of a logical sort. It is meant to refute the existence of a kind of 
mental thrust; but then w'e should remember that to prove the non- 
existence of something is alwaj/s a precarious business. “No one has 
ever proved the non-existence of Apollo or Aphrodite” it has 
observed; too much weight, then, need perhaps not be laid on this 
particular case. What is disturbing, hovrever, is the ease with which 
arguments can be cast into pseudo-deductive moulds. And it is 
this fact to which I wish to call attention by examining the argu- 
ment. As has been shown in the preceding discussion, it is not'^an 
isolated case. No philosophic argument ends with a Q.E.D. How- 
never forces. There is no bullying in philosophy, 
neither with the stick of logic nor with the stick of "language. 

VI 

In throwing such strong doubts on the power of arguments as 
used by philosophers I may seem to deny them any value what- 
ever. But such is not my intention. Even if they are lacking in logical 
iigOi this certai^y has not prevented an original thinker from using 
tnem successfully, or from bringing out something not seen before 
or not seen so clearly. So in the case I have discussed: something 
IS seen m_ that argument, something is made dear, though perhaps 
not quite m the sense intended by the arguer. If so, something very 
important has been left out from the picture. 

Perhaps our objections have been doing injustice to philosophic 
arguments. They were, quite mistakenly as I hope to have shown, 
supposed to be proofs and refutations in a strict sense. But what 
tte phfiosopher does is something else. He builds up a case. First, 
e makes you see all the weaknesses, disadvantages, shortcomings 
ot a position; he brings to light inconsistencies in it or points out 
how unnatural some of the ideas underlying the whole theorv' are 
y pushing them to their farthest consequences; and this he "does 


- I See Fhllosaphy [ ] 

^tii the stroBgest weapons in his arsenal, reduction to absurdity 
'-and infinite regress. On the other hand, he offers you a new way 
of looting at things not exposed to those objections. In other words, 
to submits to you, like a barrister, all the facts of his case, and 
you axe in the position of the judge. Yon look at them carefully, go 
Into the details, weigh the pros and cons and arrive at a verdict. 
But in arriving at a verdict you are not following a deductive high- 
way, any more than a judge in the High Court does. Coming to a 
decision, though a rational process, is very" unlike drawing conclu- 
sions from given premises, just as it is very unlike doing sums. A 
judge has to judge, we say, implying that he has to use discernment 
m contrast to applying, machine-like, a set of mechanical rules. 
There are no computing machines for doing the judge's work nor 
could there be an}' — a trivial yet significant fact. When the judge 
reaches a decision this may be, and in fact often is, a rational re- 
sult, yet not one obtained by deduction; it does not simply follow 
from such-and-such: what is required is insight, judgment. Now’ in 
arriving at a verdict, you are like a judge in this that you are not 
carrying out a number of formal logical steps: you have to use dis- 
cernment, e.g. to descr}^ the pivotal point. Considerations such as 
these make us see what is already apparent in the use of ‘Tational,” 
that this term has a wider range of application than what can be 
established deductively. To say that an argument can be rational 
and yet not deductive is not a sort of contradiction as it would in- 
evitably be in the opposite case, namely, of saying that a deductive 
argument need not be rational. 

This alters the whole picture. The point to be emphasized is that 
a philosopher may see an important truth and yet be unable to 
demonstrate it by formal proof. But the fact that his arguments are 
no! logical does nothing to detract from their rationally\ Tc return 
to our; previous example, the argument used against volition, though 
.it is not what it professes to be, logically destructive, nevertheless 
bss a force difficult to resist. Now’ to what is this due? It does not 
need much acumen to find the answer. It is the whole arrangement 
of so many felicitous examples, preceding the argument, and their 
masterly analysis, which breathes life into its bare bones; aided 
by the fact that the connection between a mental thrust and 
bocMy movement is allowed to remain a myster}^ The unsatis- 
^oriness of this position, together with the amassing of hosts of 
-Unanswerable questions and very striking examples — ^this makes the 
.^tgament so convincing. 

What do you find in reading Ryle or Wittgenstein? Lots of ex- 


f ^ . FRIEDRICH WAISMAHN 

amples with little or no logical bone in between. Why so manv e 
^ples? They speak for themselves; they usuaUy are more transpareS 
man the trouble maker; each one acts as an analog: too-ether tK« 
light up the whole linguistic background with the effect that th 
case before us is seen in the light they produce. Indeed, exampks 
aptly arranged are often more convincing and, above aU, of a moS 
^tmg efif^t than an argument which is anyhow spidery. Not that 
fee proofs proffered are valueless: a reductio ad absurdum alw^s 
pomts to a toot m thought, and so does an infinite resress But 
they point only. The real strength lies in the examples. AU {he proofs 
m a good book on philosophy, could be dispensed with, without 
losmg a whit of its convmcingness. To seek, in phUosophy, for rig- 
orous proofs IS to seek for the shadow of one’s voice. ^ ^ ^ 

In order to forestaU misinterpretations which wiU otherwise cer- 
aimy anse I have to concede one point: arguments on a small scale 
contaimng a few logical steps only, may be rigorous. The^Ss'l^ce 
of iny remarks IS that the conception of a whole phUosophical view 
-from Herachtus to Nietzsche or Bradley-is never a matter 
logical steps. A Weltanschauung like any of these or even a new ap- 
proach Idee that of Wittgenstein is never “arrived at,” in piScZ 

hv ^ ^“luted 

' logical reasomng: though arguments mav plav a patt in 

mal^g them acceptable. But some authors have disdained eve^fhaT 
itte one remainmg question to be asked is this- if the nhUos- 

aS -y p« how has h”™ 

leTd^f ^ road is 

in^. This leads to a new and deeper problem. 

VII 

H “ philosophy?” and to replv, “To 

dt • -oil, honoVkere 

^ due, i suppress what I was going to say; except perhaps this. 

^ u -li ®°methmg deeply exciting about philosophyf a fLt not 
mte^gible on such a negative account. It is not a mker of ‘-clanfy- 

S the^^LeZh^ i“g»rage” nor of any oth« 

them?, ^ Philosophy is many things and 

n ?ne ^ ^ ^ -^re asked to express 

essential feature I would^ un- 
na?e?^- pWiosophy worth the 

shape Wherr^r?*^ ^^^es its visible 

shape. When I say vision” I mean it: I do not want to romanticize. 


J Philosophy [ 375 ] 

is characteristic of philosophy is the piercing of that dead 
cciist of tradition and convention, the breaking of those fetters which 
bind ns to inherited preconceptions, so as to attain a new and broader 
looking at things. It has always been felt that philosophy 
slionid reveal to ns what is hidden. (I am not quite insensitive to 
Ibe ^ view.) Yet from Plato to Moore and Witt- 

genstein every great philosopher was led by a sense of vision: without 
1 so one could have given a new direction to human thought or 
opened windows into the not-yet-seen. Though he may be a good 
technician, he will not leave his marks on the histor}^ of ideas. What 
is decisive is a new way of seeing and, what goes with it, the will to 
transform the whole intellectual scene. This is the real thing and 
ever^^thing else is subservient to it. 

Suppose that a man revolts against accepted opinion, that he 
feels ‘'cramped” in its categories; a time may come when he believes, 
rightly or wrongly, that he has freed himself of these notions; when 
he has that sense of sudden growth in looking back at the prejudices 
which held him captive; or a time when he believes, rightiy or 
wrongly, that he has reached a vantage point from which things can 
be seen to be arranged in clear and orderly patterns while dijfficulties 
of long standing dissolve as though by magic. If he is of a philosophic 
cast of mind he w'ill argue this out with himself and then, perhaps, 
to impart what has dawned on him to others. The arguments he 
wiE offer, the attacks he will make, the suggestions he will advance 
are all devised for one end: to win other people over to his own 
way of looking at things, to change the whole climate of opinion. 
Though to an outsider he appears to advance all sorts of arguments, 
this is not the decisive point. What is decisive is that he has seen 
things from a new angle of vision. Compared to that everything else 
is secondary. Arguments come only afterwards to lend support to 
what he has seen. “Big words, not eveiy^ philosopher, etc.:” bui 
wbere should one get one’s bearings if not from the masters? And 
besides, once tradition has given way there is always ample scope 
for specialists to reduce some “pockets of resistance.” Unpalatable 
though it may be, behind the arguments so weli-planned, so neat and 
logical, something else is at work, a win to transform the entire way 
of thinking. In arguing for his viewy the philosopher will, almost 
against his will, have to undermine current categories and cliches of 
thinkmg by exposing the fallacies which underly the established 
Ttews he is attacking; and not only this, he may go so far as to 
^stion the canons of satisfactoriness themselves. In this sense, 
philosophy is the re-testing of the standards. In every philosopher 




t 1 FRIEDRICH WAISMANN 

lives something of the reformer. That is the reason why any advance 
in science when it touches the standards is felt to be of philosophic 
significance, from Galileo to Einstein and Heisenberg. 

If there is any truth in this, the relation of logic and philosophy 
appears in a new light. What is at issue is not a confiict between a 
formal and a less formal or informal logic, nor between the behavior 
of techmcal and eveiy'day concepts, but something radically differ- 
ent. It is the difference between drawing a conclusion and seeincr 
or making one see, a new aspect. 

To put the matter in a nutshell, a philosophic argument does 
more and does less than a logical one: less in that it never estab- 
lishes anything conclusively; more in that, if successful, it is not 
content to establish just one isolated point of truth, but effects a 
change in our whole mental outlook so that, as a result of that, 
myriads of such little points are brought into view or turned ou:' of 
sight, as the case may be. Are iOustrations necessary'? Once Hume 
had exposed the_ fallacies of his predecessors when dealing with the 
notion of causality he had made it impossible for anyone to think 
along the lines of Spinoza whose world looks to us sltrange as the 
moon. Suppose that you look at a picture-puzzle: at first you can 
see in it only a maze of lines; then, suddenly, you recognize a human 
met. Can you now, having discovered the face, see the lines as 
before? Clearly not. As with the maze of lines,, so with the muddle 
ciea.red up by^Kume: to recapture the mood of the past, tc travel 
back into the fog has become impossible — one of the big difficulties 
of understanding history-’ of philosophy. It is for the same reason that 
the nse of the linguistic technique in our day has put an end to the 
great speculative systems of the past. 

A philosophy is an attempt to unfreeze habits of thinking, to 
replace them by less stiff and restricting ones. Of course, these "may 
in time themselves harden, with the result that they effig progress': 
Kant, the Alleszermalmer to his contemporaries, yet proudly up- 
holding his table or categories — which appear to us unduly' narrow. 
The Uberaior of yesterday may turn into the tyrant of tomorrow. 

It can now be seen that the philosopher is not doing what the 
lo^cian does only less competently but doing something altogether 
aifferent. A philosophic argument is not an approximation of a logi- 
cal one nor is the latter the ideal the philosopher is striving for. Such 
^ account totaUy misdescribes what really takes place. Philosophy 
is not an exercise in formal logic, philosophic arguments are not 
chains of logical inference, only bungled ones, nor can they by any 
effort be recast into deductive moulds. What is being confused here 


Philosophy [ 377 ] 

scieBtist’s aim to find new truths and the philosopher’s aim 
■■'Ib insight. As the two things are so entirely out of scale it is 
wonder that the philosopher cannot move in the logician’s 
Not even if the logician himself is fighting the battle. The 
’-dash over the law of excluded middle in mathematics is a clash 
between two parties, each in possession of clear and precisely defined 
"'concepts. Yet there seems to be no way of settling the dispute fay 
cogcBt argument. If it were true that phiiosopfaical troubles arise 
fiom the loose nature of our everyday concepts, why should such 
conflicts break out in the exactest of the sciences? 

There have never been any absolutely cogent reasons for parting 
with the law of excluded middle, accepting Darwinism, giving up 
the Ptolemaic system or renouncing the principle of causality. If any 
of these things could be demonstrated how does it come that there 
are always partisans of the “lost causes”? Are they like the unluck}^ 

‘ drcie-squarers, v/asting their time in trying to do what has been 
shown to be logically impossible? The truth is that conflicts of this 
type cannot be resolved, not entirely, either by adducing factual evi- 
dence or by logical demonstration. Both sides, of course, bring up 
arguments in the combat but they are not decisive. These are battles 
never lost and never won irrevocably. It is a typical situation, a recur- 
rent theme in the histor}- of human thought. 

\^flienever science arrives at a crucial, stage w^here the funda- 
mental notions become imceriain and are held as it were in solution, 
disputes of an odd land are breaking out. The mere fact that lead- 
ing scientists, in spite of dinerences in temperament, outlook, etc., 
take part in them, feel bound to do so, should make us reflect. 
Now what the protagonists avowedly or unavowedly are trying to 
do is to win their fellow scientists over to their own way of think- 
ing; and to the degree to which their arguments are attempts at 
changing the whole intellectual attitude they take on a philosophical 
character. Is this coincidence? 


I have so far spoken of “seeing a new aspect” without making 
sn attempt to explain the term. I hope now^ to do so, though only 
. .perfunctorily, by giving one or two illustrations. There is a sort of 
connected with the idea of certain discoveries. Descartes, 
i.-fcrinstance, was the discoverer of analytic geometr}^ But could he 

looking for it sounds down- 
absurd. What we are inclined to say in such a case is: to seek 








J 378 ] FRIEDRICH WAISMANN 

for analytic geometiy is not possible — ^first because it was not seen 
and then because it was seen. But if he could not seek, how could 
he find? This leads us straight to the heart of the matter. 

Consider first an entirely imaginaiy case. In the propositional 
calculus, as it was built up by Frege, two primitive ideas occur, 
“not” and “or.” It was later discovered by Sheffer that the whole 
calculus can be based on one single idea (his “stroke” function). 
Of what kind was this discovery? Suppose that Frege, by a curious 
chance, had written aU his logical axioms in the form 

-( )v-( ) 

i.e. as a sum of two negations, but had none the less mistakenly 
believed that two symbols were required for expressing these laws, 
namely and “v.” Imagine nov/ that someone else looking at 
these formulae is struck by what, on our assumption, has escaped 
Frege, namely that they all have one and the same structure and 
require therefore only one symbol. In what exactly does his dis- 
covery consist? In his seeing the formulae in a new way, in his 
reading a new structure into them. What matters is his apprehension: 
so long as he does not see the structure of a new system in the old 
one he has not got it. Anyone may look at the formulae and yet not 
perceive what SheSer has perceived, the occurrence of an identical 
structure. This is the discovery’, not the introducing of a special 
symbol for a combination of the old ones. It w^ould have been quite 
enough, for instance, had Sheffer merely pointed out the constant 
recurrence of this structure in all the laws without providing his 
“stroke”; that is inessential. 

This example may illustrate what is meant by the “seeing of a 
new aspect.” Seeing such an aspect is often the core of a new dis- 
cover}’. If you look at the formulae, the moment you notice the new 
structure in them they suddenly seem to change — a phenomenon 
akin to seeing a figure, say, a drawm cube differently, now as solid 
and protruding, how as hollow and receding. The one pattern sud- 
denly “jumps” into the other. Similarly in our case, though there 
are also difierences; thus the new aspect, once it has dawned, can 
steadily be held in mind and has not that perceptual instability. The 
apprehension of a new^ pattern in the formulae seems to hold in it 
actually more of a visual experience, anyhow to be more closely 
akin to it than it might at first appear. Seeing and interpreting, 
looking and thinking seem as it were to fuse here. 

If it is now asked whether it is possible for anyone to seek for 


'-Bm I Fhihsophy [ 379 ] 

sew aspect, what is one to reply? Well, that something can be 
jjx a new way is seen only when it is seen in this way. That an 
g^pect is possible is seen only when the aspect has already flashed 
and not before: that’s why the finding cannot be anticipated, not 
ei?es by the greatest genius. It always comes unbidden and, as it 
would seem, in a sudden flash. 

To take another case, is the calculation 

(5 + 3)2::::, 52 ^2. 5. 3 + 32 

at the same time a proof that 

(2 + 3)-=:22+2.2.3~f-3^ ? 

Yes and no— depending on how you look at it. (Does it strike you 
that the 2 in the middle term is a ‘‘stracturar’ 2, deriving not from 
the special numbers but from the general form of the operation?) 
A man, while reckoning with special numbers only, may yet con- 
ceivably do algebra if he sees the special sums in a new way, as the 
expressions of a general iav\ (Discovery^ of algebra as the discovery 
of an aspect of numerical calculation.) 

What goes for these more or less trivial cases goes for Descartes 
and also for Einstein and Hilbert. They were unable to seek, Einstein 
for a conceptual gap in the idea of simultaneity, Hilbert for the 
axiomatic method. Though these discoveries are of a different order 
altogether, the principle underlying them is the same. None of them 
has ever “arrived” at his view because he was never travelling. They 
did not seek, they found (like Picasso). And tliat is so wrong with 
the whole way in which such discoveries are so often presented — as 
if they were ^e result of a “method” or “procedure,” as if the great 
men arrived at their solutions by drawing logical inferences. This 
leaves out the most essential thing — the flashing of a new aspect 
which is non-inferential. The moments of seeing cannot be foreseen, 
any more than they can be planned, forced, controlled, or sum- 
moned by will-power. 

Is there any truth in what I am saying? I shall not argue. In- 
stead, let me remind you of some observations which will be familiar 
■ to you. It is notorious that a philosophy is not made, it grows. You 
choose a puzzle, you are shocked into it. Whoever has pon- 
some time over some dark problem in philosophy will have 
;^ficed that the solution, when it comes, comes with a suddenness. 
It is not through working very hard tow^ards it that it is found. What 
' is rather that he suddenly sees things in a new light — as if 

^ veil had been lifted that screened his view, or as if the scales bad 



[ 380 ] FKIEDUICH WAISMANK 

faHen from Ms eyes, leaviog Mm surprised at Ms own stupidity not 
to have seen what was there quite plain before him all the tkne. It 
is less like finding out something and more like maturing, outgrow- 
ing preconceived notions. 

To give just one example of vision in philosophy: Wittgenstein 
saw through a big mistake of Ms time. It was then held by most 
philosophers that the nature of such things as hoping and fearing, 
or intending, meaning and understanding could be discovered throng 
introspection, while others, in particular psychologists, sought to 
arrive at an answ^er by experiment, having only obscure notions as 
to what their results meant. Wittgenstein changed the whole approach 
by saying: what these words mean shows itself in the way they are 
used — the nature of understanding reveals itself in grammar, not in 
experiment. This was at the time quite a revelation and came to 
him, so far as I remember, suddenly. 

The view advocated here is that at the living center of every philos- 
ophy is a vision and that it should be judged accordingly. The really 
important questions to be discussed in the Mstory^ of philosophy are 
not whether Leibniz or Kant were consistent in arguing as they did 
but rather wmat lies beMnd the systems they have built. And here I 
want to end with a few words on metaphysics. 

To say that metaphysics is nonsense is nonsense. It fails to 
acknowledge the enormous part played at Ieasf"in the past by those 
systems. Why this is so. why they should have such a hold over the 
human mind I shall not undertake here to discuss. Metaphysicians, 
like artists, are the antennae of their time: they have a flair for 
feeling which w^ay the spirit is moving. (There is a Rilke poem about 
it.) There is sometmng visionaiy about great metaphysicians as if 
they had the power to see beyond the horizons of their time. Take, 
for instance, Descartes' work. That it has given rise to endless meta- 
physical quibbles is certainly a thing to hold against it. Yet if we 
attend to the spirit rather than to the words I am greatly inclined 
to say that there is a certain grandeur in it, a prophetic aspect of the 
comprehensibility of nature, a bold anticipation of what has been 
achieved in science at a much later date. The true successors of 
Descartes were those who translated the spirit of this philosophy 
into deeds, not Spinoza or Malebranche but Newton and the mathe- 
matical description of nature. To go on with some hairsplitting as 
to what substance is and how it should be defined was to miss the 
message. It wus a colossal mistake. A philosophy is there to be 
lived out. WhdX goes into the word dies, what goes into the work lives. 




Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


1 


The range of this bibliography is rather wider than that of the 
{jook. It includes works which are either expository or critical not 
only of logical positivism, in the strict sense, but of every form of 
jxjodem analytical philosophy. It does not claim to be exhaustive even 
on the topic of logical positivism: but an effort has been made to 
list at any rate the most important books and articles that can rea- 
sonably be regarded as falling within this field. 

The bibliography is divided into three sections: anthologies and 
compilations; books and monographs; and articles, including contri- 
butions to symposia and critical notices of special interest. Contribu- 
tions by any one writer are listed in chronological order. The refer- 
ences to articles do not give the numbers of the periodicals or 
proceedings in which they appear, but the dates oi the volumes in 
which these numbers fall. This is in conformitv' with the practice fol- 
lowed by the other books in this series. 


ANTHOLOGIES 
A N D C O M P I L A T I 0 N S 

Ayer, A. J. el al. The Revolution in Philosophy, London: Macmillan, 1956 
BlacL M. (ed.). Philosophical Analysis, Ithaca: Cornel! Univ. Press, 1950 
Hdwards, P. and Pap, A. (eds.), A Slodern Introduction to Philosophy, Glen- 
coe: The Free Press; London: Allen and Umtin, 1957 
ISton, W, (ed.). Aesthetics and Language, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1954 
Feigl, H.-and Brodbeck, M. (eds.). Readings in the Philosophy of Science, 
New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953 , ,, , j 

' IBdgi, H. and Scriven, M. (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of 
' ■ Science; Vol. I, The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of 
L ' Psychology and Psychoanalysis, Minneapolis : Univ. oi Minnesota 

■ Press, 1956 







[ 3S2 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Feigl, H., Scriven, M. and Ma?well, G- (eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Phi. 

losophy of Science; Vol. II, Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body 
Problem, Minneapolis : Univ. of Minnesota Press, 1958 
Feigi, H. and Sellars, W. (eds.), Readings in Philosophical Analysis, New 
York: Appieton-Century-Crofts, 1949 

Flew, A. G. N. (ed.). Logic and Language (first series), Oxford: Blackwell 
1951 

Logic and Language (second series), Oxford: BiackweE, 1953 
Essays in Conceptual Analysis, London: Macmilian, 1956 
Flew, A, and MacIntyre, A. (eds.), New Essays in Philosophical Theology^ 
London: SCM Press; New York: Macinilian, 1955 
Gardiner, P. (ed.). Theories of History, Glencoe: The Free Press, 1959 
Henie, P., Kailen, H. M. and Langer, S. K. (eds.), Structure, Method and 
Meaning: Essays in honor of Henry M. Shefer, New York: Liberal 
Arts Press, 1951 

Hook, S. (ed.), American Philosophers a: Work, New York: Criterion Books 
1956 

Determinism and Freedom, New York: New" York Unrv'. Press, 1958 
International Encyclopedic of Unified Science, ed. 0. Nenrath and others: 

(combined ed.), vol. I in 2 parts. Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1955 
Lasiett, P. (ed.). The Physical Basis of Mind, Oxford: Blackwell, 1950 
Politics, Philosophy and Society, Oxford: Blackwell. 1956 
Lewis, H- D. (ed.). Contemporary British Philosophy (third series), London: 
Alien and Unwin, 1956 

Linsky, L. (ed.), Semantics and the Philosophy of Language, Urbana: Univ. 
of lilinois Press, 1952 

Macdonald, M. (ed.). Philosophy and Analysis, Oxford: Blackwell, 1954 
Mace, C- A. (ed.), British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, London: Allen 
and Unwin; New" York: Macmillan, 1957 v 
Mitchell, B. (ed.), Faith and Logic, London: Allen and Unwin, 1957 
Muirhead, 1. H. (ed.). Contemporary British Philosophy (first and second 
series), London: Alien and Unwin, 1924 and 1925 
Munitz, M. K. (ed.), A Modern Introduction to Ethics, Glencoe: The Free 
Press, 1958 

Nenrath, O., ei aL, Encyclopedia and Unified Science. Chicago: Univ. of 
Chic. Press (Int. Encyci. of Unified Science). 1958 
Pears, D. F. (ed.), The Nature of Metaphysics, London; \fa rrnil l an .. 1957 
Runes, D. (ed.), Twentieth Centura Phliosophy, New \'ork: Philosophical 
Libraiy’, 1943 

Schilpp, P. A. (ed.). The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, Evanston: Northwest- 
ern Univ., 1942; 2nd ed. 1*952 

The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell. Evanston: Northw’esiem Univ., 1944 
Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scieniis:, New York; Tudor Press, 1949 
Sellars, W. and Hospers, J. (eds.). Pleadings in Ethical Theory, New York: 
Appieton-Century-Crof ts, 1952 

Philosophical Studies, Essays in Memory of L. Susan Stebbing, London: 
Alien and Unwin, 1948 

Wiener, P. P. (ed.). Readings in PhilosoDh^ of Science, New York: Scribner’s, 
1953 

Philosophical Essays for A, N. Whitehead, London: Longman’s, 1936 



of Logical Positivism 


[ 383 ] 


BOOKS 


K-, Beiiriige zur Methodologie der deduktiven Wissenschaften, 
Lwow: Veriag der Polnischen PMIosophischen Geselischaft in Lem- 
berg, 1921 

Afiscombe, G- E. M., Intention, Oxford: Basil Blackweli, 1957 
Austin, J. L., Ifs and Cans, British Academy Armnai Philosophical Lecture, 
London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1956 

tycr, A. I., Language, Truth and Logic, London: Gollancz, 1936, 2nd ed. 1946 
The Foundations of Empirical Knowledge, London: Macmillan, 1940 
Thinking and Meaning, London: H. K. Lewis, 1947 
Philosophical Essays, London: Macmillan, 1954 

The Problem of Knowledge, London: Macmillan and Penguin Books, 1956 
Baier, K., The Moral Point of View, Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1958 
Barnes, W. H. F., The Philosophical Predicament, London: A. and C. Black, 
1950 

Bergmarm, G., The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism, London: Longmans, 
Green, 1954 

Philosophy of Science, Madison: Univ. of Wisconsin Press, 1957 
Black, M., The Nature of Mathematics, London: Kegan Paul; New York: 
Harcourt Brace, 1933 

Language and Philosophy, Ithaca: Cornell Univ. Press, 1949 
Critical Thinking, New York: Prentice Hall, 1952 
Problems of Analysis, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1954 
Bloomfield, L., Linguistic Aspects of Science, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 
(Int Encycl. of Unified Science), 1939 
Bochenski, I. M., Europdische Philosophie der Gegenwart, Bern: Francke, 
1947. Eng- transL by D. Nichoil and K. Aschenbrenner, Contem- 
porary European Philosophy, Berkeley: Univ. of California Press, 1956 
Precis de Logique Maihematique, Bussum: F. G. Klroonder, 1949 
Braithwaite, R. B., Scientific Explanation, Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. 
Press, 1953 

Bridgman, P. W., The Logic of Modern Physics, New York: Macmillan, 1927 
The Nature of Physical Theory, Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1936 
Reflections of a Physicist, New York: Philosophical Library', 1950 
Britton, K., Communication: A Philosophical Study of Language, London: 

Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1939 
Broad, C. D., Scientific Thought, London: Kegan Paul, 1923 

The Mind and Its Place in Nature, London: Kegan Paul, 1925 
R., Der Raum, Berlin: Erg. Heft 56 der Kantstudien, 1922 
Der logische Aufbau der Welt, Berlin: Weitkreis- Veriag, 1928 
Scheinprobleme in der Philosophie, das Fremdpsychische und der Real- 
ismusstreit, Berlin, 1928 
Abriss der Logistik, Vienna: Springer, 1929 

Logische Syntax der Sprache, Vienna: Springer, 1934. Eng. transL, Logi- 
cal Syntax of Language, London: Kegan Paul; New York: Harcourt 
Brace, 1937 



[ 384 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Carnap, R. {continued) 

Die Aufgabe der Wissenschaftslogik, Einheitmissenschcft, No. 3, Vienaa: 
Gerold, 1934. French transl. (together ^th that of “FornialwisstD- 
schaft imd Realwissenschaft,” see articles below), Le probieme de 
la logique de la science, science formelle et science du reel, Paris: 
Actuaiites Scientifiqnes 291, Herman, 1935 
Philosophy and Logical Syntax, London: Kegan Paul, 1935 
Foundations of Logic and Mathematics, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press 
(Int Encycl. of Unified Science), 1939 
Introduction to Semantics (Studies in Semantics, voL I), Cambridge; 
Harvard Univ. Press, 1942 

Formalization of Logic (Studies in Semantics, voL 11), Cambridge: Har- 
vard Univ. Press, 1943 

Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic, Chi- 
cago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1947 

Logical Foundations of Probability (Probability and Induction, voi. I), 
Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1950 
The Nature and Application of Inductive Logic (sk sections from Logical 
Foundations of Probability), Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1951 
The Continuum of Inductive Methods, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1952 
Einfuhrung in die symbolische Logik, mil besondersr Berucksickiigung 
ihrer Anwendungen, Vienna: Springer, 1954. Engl, transl. Introduc- 
tion to Symbolic Logic, New York: Dover, !95S 
Carnap, R. and Bar-Hillel, Y., An Outline of the Theory of Semantic Informa- 
tion, Cambridge: Res. Lab. of Electronics, hi. IT. Repon No. 247, 
1952 

Carnap, R.. Hahn, H. and Neurath, O., Wissenschaftliche V/ehaunassung: Der 
Wiener Kreis, Vienna: Wolf, 1929 

Chisholm, R. M., Perceiving: A Philosophical Study. Ithaca: Comeii Univ, 
Press, 1957 

Clauberg, K. W. and Dubislav, W., Systematisches Worterbuck der Philo^ 
sophie, Leipzig: Meiner, 1923 

Copleston, F., Contemporary Philosophy, London: Bums and Oates, 1956 
Comforth, M., Science versus Idealism, London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1946 
In Defence of Philosophy against Positivism arid PragrTmtism, London: 
Lawrence and Wishart, 1950 

Dray, Wl, Laws and Explarmtion in History, O.xiord: Oxford Univ. Press, 1957 
Dubislav, W., Vber die sog, analytischen und synmeiischen Vrieile, Berlin, 
1926 

Vber die Definition, Berlin, 1927 

Die Philosophic der Mathematik in der Gegenwari, Berlin: Dunker k 
Dunnhaupt, 1932 

Dubislav, W. and Clauberg, K. W., Systematisches Worterbuck der Philo- 
sophie, Leipzig: Meiner, 1923 

Edwards, P., The Logic of Moral Discourse, Glencoe: The Free Press, 1955 
Einstein, A., Geometrie und Erfahrung, Berlin: Springer, 1921 
Ewing, A. C., The Definition of Good, New Y^'ork: Macmillan, 1947 
Feigl, H., Theorie und Erfahrung in der Pkysik, Karisnihe: Braun, 1929 
Finiay-Freundiich, E., Cosmology, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (Ink Encycl 
of Unified Science), 1951 

Frank, P., Das Kausalgesetz und seine Grenzen, Yuemia: Springer, 1932 

Das Ende der mechanistischen Physik, Einkeitswissenschaft No. 5, Vienna: 
Gerold, 1935 


tv-}'.;. 

'v:.. % 
S.: 

k'i 


t 


^iUdgraphy of Logical Positivism [ 385 ] 

P* (continued) 

-^JMerpretations and Misinterpretations of Modern Physics, Pans: Her- 

... * - maas, 1938 

" - Between Physics and Philosophy, Cambridge: Har\'ard Univ. Press, 1941 
. ' Bamdations of Physics, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (Int. Encycl. of 
' Unified Science), 1946 

B.is Life and Times, New York: Knopf, 1947; London: Jona- 
W - f ban Cape, 1948 

" Modem Science and Its Philosophy, Csiiahndge: PlaTVBiTdXJniv, Press, 1949 

Melativity: A Richer Truth, Boston: Beacon Press, 1950; London: Cape, 
, 1951 

: : Philosophy of Science, Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1957 
%ardiner, P., The Nature of Historical Explanation, Oxford: Oxford Univ. 
Press, 1952 

^ ' Uoodman, N., The Structure of Appearance, Cambridge: Harvard Univ. 

Press, 1951 

Fact, Fiction and Forecast, London: Athione Press, 1954; Cambridge: 
Harvard Univ. Press, 1955 

Hahn, H., Vberfiiissige Wesenheiten, Vienna: Wolf, 1929 

Logik, Mathematik und Naturerkennen, Einheitswissenschaft No. 2, 
Vienna: Gerold, 1933. Eng. transl. in the present volume 
Hahn, H., Camap, R. and Neurath, O., Wissenschaftliche Wehauffassung: 
r Der Wiener Kreis, Vienna: Wolf, 1929 

' Hallden, S. L, The Logic of Nonsense, Uppsala: Bokhandeln A-B. Lunde- 
- ■ . . quistska, 1949 

Emotive Propositions, Stockholm: Almqvist & W^iksell, 1954 
Hare, R. M., The Language of Morals, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1952 
' Hart, H. L, A., Definition and Theory in Jurisprudence, Oxford: Clarendon 
Press, 1953 

Helmholtz, H. von, Schriften zur Erkenntnistheorie, ed. Scblick, M. and 
Hertz, P., Berlin: Springer, 1921 

^ Hempel, C. G., Fundamentals of Concept Formation in Empirical Science, 
Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (Int. Encycl. of Unified Science), 1952 
' ’■ * Hempel, C. G. and Oppenheim, Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen 
Logik, Leiden; Sijthoff, 1936 

Hill, T. E., Contemporary Ethical Theories, New York: Macmillan, 1950 
Holloway, I., Language and intelligence, London: Macmillan, 1951 
Hospers, J., Meaning and Truth in the Arts, Chapel Hill: Univ. of North Caro- 
lina Press, 1946 

A . . An Introduction to Philosophical Analysis, New York: Prentice-Hall, 1953 
; . Huttcn, E. H., The Language of Modern Physics, London: Alien and Unwin, 
15>.56 

C. E. M., A Critique of Logical Positivism, London: GoUancz; Chicago: 
Univ. of Chic, Press, 1950 

V .1;.- \^<ttdan, Z., On the Development of Mathematical Logic and of Logical Posi- 
in Poland, London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1946 
^ Treatise of Formal Logic, Copenhagen: Levin & Mimksgaard; 

. London: Humphrey Milford (Oxford Univ. Press), 1931 
Peykologi Paa Biologisk Grundlag (Psychology Based on Biology), Co- 
penhagen, 1941-45 

’Pke Development of Logical Empiricism, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press 


'i- 




(Int. Encycl. of Unified Science), 1951 




[ 386 ] Bibliography of Logicd Fositivism 

Kalia, E., Der Logistische Neupositivismus: Eine kritische Studie, Tnrkii: 
Tnnin Yiiopiston jnlkaisuja, 1930 

t)ber das System der Wirklichkeitsbegriffe, Helsinki: Acta PMosopMca 
Feimica, Fasc. 2, 1936 

tJber den physikalischen Reaiitdtsbegriff, Helsinki: Acta PMosopMca 
Fennica, 3Fasc. 4, 1941 

Terminal-Kausalitdt als die Grundlage eines unitarischen Naturbegriffs: 
eine naturphilosophische XJntersuchung, Helsinki: Acta PMlosophica 
Fennica, 1956 

Kanfmann, F., Das Unendliche in der Mathematik und seine Ausschaltung, 
Vienna: Deuticke, 1930 

Methodology of the Social Sciences, London: Oxford Univ. Press, 1944 

Kelsen, H., Vergeltung und Kausalitdt, The Hague: van Stockum, 1941. Eng. 

transl. Society and Nature, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1943; 
London: Kegan Paul, 1946 

Kneale, W., Probability and Induction, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1949 

Kotarbinski, T., Elementy teori poznania, logiki formalnej i metodolog: nauk 
(Elements of the theory of knowledge, formal logic and method- 
ology of science), Lwow, 1929 

ICraft, V., Die Grundlagen einer wissenschaftlichen Werilehre, Vienna: 
Springer, 1937 

Mathematik, Logik und Erfahrung, Vienna: Springer, 1947 
Einfuhrung in die Philosophie — Philosophie, Weltanschauung, 
schaft, Vienna: Springer, 1950 

Der Wiener Kreis, Der Ursprung des Neupositivismus, Vienna: Springer, 
1950. Eng. transL, The Vienna Circle, New York: Philosophical 
Library, 1953 ^ ‘ 

Lazerowitz. M., The Structure of Metaphysics, London: Routiedge and Kegan 
Paul, 1955 

Lean. M., Sense -Perception and Matter, London: Routiedge and Kenan 
Paul, 1953 . 

Lewis, C. I., Mind and the World Order, New York: Scribner, 1929 

An Analysis of Knowledge and Valuation, La Salle: Open Court. 1946 

Lukasiewicz, J., Die iogischen Grundlagen der Wahrscheinlichkehsrschnung, 
Cracow': Krakauer Akad. d. Wiss., 1913 
O nance (On Science), Lwow% 1934 

Mainx, F., Foundations of Biology, Chicago: Univ, of Chic. Press (ini. En* 
cyci, of Unified Science), 1955 

Malcolm, N., Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir, Oxford and New' York: Ox- 
ford Univ. Press, 1958 

Marc-Wogau, K., Die Theorie der Sinnesdaten, Uppsala: Universiieis Ars- 
skrift, 1945 

von Mises, R., Wahrscheinlichkeit, Statistik und Wahreii, Vienna: Springer, 
1936. Eng. transl.. Probability, Statistics and Truth, New' York: Mac- 
millan; London: William Hodge, 1939 
Ernst Mach und die empiristische Wissenschaftsauffassung, Einheitswis- 
senschaft No. 7, ’s Gravenhage: W. P. van Stockum, 1938 
Kleines Lehrbuck des Positivismus, The Hague: Van Stockum & Son, 
1939. Eng. transL, Positivism: A Study in Human Understanding, 
Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1951 

Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1903 
Ethics, London: Home University Library, 1912 




Positivism [ 387 ] 

p^^flv^rMoons, G. E. (continued) 

philosophical Studies, London: Kegan Paul, 1922 
7- ^ -p/w?# of an External World, British Academy: Animal PMasophical 

/■ Lecture, 1939 

'"■/‘'Jif ? ^^jne Main Problems of Philosophy, London: Allen and Unwin, 1953 

Moms, C- W., Logical Positivism, Pragmatism, and Scientific Empiricism, 
\ - “ Paris: Hermann, 1937 

J 'p; “ foundations of the Theory of Signs, Chicago: Unlv. of Chic. Press (Int. 

/ . r- BncycL of Unified Science), 1938 

r, * J S^ns, Language, and Behavior, New York: Prentice-Hail, 1946 
Naess, A-, Erkenntms und Wissenschaftliches Verhalten, Oslo: 1936 
’ ' ^ ' **Truth** as Conceived by Those Who Are Not Professional Philosophers, 

y . Oslo; 1938 

1'- Interpretation and Preciseness, Oslo: 1953 

~ Innforing, Logikk og Metodelaere, Oslo: Universitets Studentkontor, 1949 
I: Naess, A., Christophersen, J. A. and Kvalo, K., Democracy, Ideology and 

Objectivity: Studies in the Semantics and Cognitive Analysis of 
Ideologic^ Controversy, Oslo: Univ. Press; Oxford, Blackwell, 1956 
Nagel, £., On the Logic of Measurement, New York: Columbia Univ. Ph.D. 
Thesis, 1930 

Principles of the Theory of Probability, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press 
(Int Encycl. of Unified Science), 1939 
, . Sovereign Reason, Glencoe: The Free Press, 1954 

Logic Without Metaphysics, Glencoe: The Free Press, 1956 
Nagel, E, and Newman, J. R., GodeVs Proof, New' York: New' York Univ, 
Press, 1958 

Nearath, O., Antispengler, Munich: Cailwey, 1921 
Empirische Soziologie, Vienna: Springer, 1931 

Einheitswissenschaft und Psychologic, Einheitswissenschaft No. 1, Vienna: 
Springer, 1933 

Le developpement du Cercle de Vienne et Vavenir de Vempirisme logique, 
|.; Paris: Hermann, 1935 

' Was Bedeutet Rationale Wirtschaftsbetrachtung? , Einheitswissenschaft 

I No. 4 , Vienna: Gerold, 1935 

- Foundations of the Social Sciences, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (Int 

Encycl. of Unified Science), 1944 

Neurath, 0-, Brunswik, E., Hull, C. L., Mannour>', G. and Woodger, J. H., 
Zur Encyklopddie der Einheitswissenschafi, Vortrdge, Einheitswis- 
senschaft No. 6, ’s Gravenshage: W. J, von Stockum, 1938 
. - . Neurath, O., Carnap, R. and Hahn, H., Wissenschaftliche W eltauffassimg: 

- * Der Wiener Kreis, Vienna: Wolf, 1929 

J. R, and Nagel, E., GodeVs Proof, New York: New York Univ. 
-■’..■'4-'. ^ Press, 1958 

' l^cod,!.. Foundations of Geometry and Induction, London: Kegan Paul, 1930 

Noweii-Smith, P, H., Ethics, London: Penguin, 1954; Oxford: Blackwell, 1958 
:j C, K. and Richards, I. A., The Meaning of Meaning, London: Kegan 

* ^Paui, 1923 

^ " Qppenheim, P., Die Naturliche Ordnung der Wissenschaften. Grundgesetze 
' ' der vergleichenden Wissenschaftslehre, Jena: Gustav Fischer, 1926 

. I^%»enhemi, P. and Hempel, C. G., Der Typusbegriff im Lichte der neuen 
Logik, Leiden: Sijthoff, 1936 














[ 388 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Pap, A., The A Prion in Physical Theory, New York: King’s Crown Press, 
1946 

Elements of Analytic Philosophy, New York: Macmillan, 1949 
Analytische Erkenntnistheorie, Vienna: Springer-Verlag, 1955 
Semantics and Necessary Truth, New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1958 
Passmore, J., A Hundred Years of Philosophy, London: Duckworth, 1957 
Pereiman, C. and Olbrechts-Tyteca, L., Traite de 1’ Argumentation (La nouvelle 
rhetorique), Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1958 
Petzall, A., Her Logistische Neupositivismus, Annales Universitatis Aboeasis, 
Ser. B., Tom. XIH, 1930 

Logistischer Positivismus, Goteborgs Hogskolas Arsskrift XXXVII, Gote- 
borg: Wettergren k Kerbers, 1931 

Pole, D., The Later Philosophy of Wittgenstein, London: Athlone Press, 1958 
Popper, K. R., Logik der Forschung, Vienna: Springer, 1935. Eng. trans!., 
The Logic of Scientific Discovery, London: Hutchinson, 1958 
The Open Society and Its Enemies, London: Kegan Paul, 1945 
The Poverty of Historicism, London: Routiedge and Kegan Paul, 1957 
Price, H. H., Perception, London: Methuen, 1932 

Truth and Corrigibility, Inaugural Lecuire, London: Oxford Univ, Press, 
1936 

Hume's Theory of the External World, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1940 
Thinking and Representation, British Academy Lecture, 1946 
Thinking and Experience, London: Hutchinson, 1953 
Quine. W. V. O., From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge: Harvard Univ. 
Press, 1953 

Ramsey. F. P., The Foundations of Mathematics anil Other Logical Essays, 
London: Kegan Paul, 1931 

Reicbenbach, H-, Reiaiivitdtstheorie und Erkenntnis A priori, Berlin: Springer, 
1920 

Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum-Zeii-Lehre {Die Wissenschaft No. 
72), Braunschweig: Vieweg, 1924 

Philosophic der Raum-Zeit-Lehre, Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter, 
1928. Engl. transL, The Philosophy of Space and Time, New York; 
Dover, 1957 

Atom und Kosmos. Das physikalische V/eltbild der Gegenwart, Berlin: 
Deutsche Buch-Gemeinschaft, 1930. Eng. transl., Atom and Cosmos. 
The World of Modern Physics, London: Allen and Unwin, 1932; 
New York: Macmillan, 1933 

Ziele und Wege der keutigen Naturphilosophie, Leipzig: Meiner, 1931. 
Eng. transl- in Selected Essays, London: Routiedge and Kegan Paul, 
1959 

Wahrscheinlichkeitslehre. Bine Untersuchung ilber die logischen und 
mathemaiischen Grundlagen der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung, Lei- 
den: Sijthoff, 1935. Eng. transl.. The Theory of Probability. An 
Inquiry into the Logical and Mathematical Foundations of the Cal- 
culus of Probability, 2nd ed., Berkeley and Los Angeles: Univ. of 
California Press, 1949 

Experience and Prediction. An Analysis of the Foundations and the 
Structure of Knowledge, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press, 1938 
Philosophic Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Berkeley and Los An- 
geles: Univ. of California Press, 1944. Ger. transl., Basel: Birk- 
bauser, 1949 







'^"^ B^graphy of Logical Positivism [ 389 ] 

\ lijMiefibacIi, H. {continued) 

,, .; ^"^^Ismenis of Symbolic Logic, New York: Macmilian, 1947 

The Rfee of Scientific Philosophy, Berkeley and Los Angeles: Univ. of 
Califonila Press, 1951. Ger. transL, Berlin-Gninewald: Herbig, 1953 
Nomoiogical Statements and Admissible Operations, Ajnsterdam: N.“ 
Holland Pub. Co., 1954 

The Direction of Time (edL M. Reichenbach), Berkeley and Los Angeles: 
Univ. of California Press, 1956 

Richards L A., and Ogden, C. K., The Meaning of Meaning, London: Kegan 
’Paul, 1923 

Robiisson, R-, Definition, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1950 
Rougier, L., Les paralogismes du rationalisme, Paris: Alcan, 1920 
La structure des theories deductives, Paris: Alcan, 1921 
Traite de la connaissance, Paris: Gauthier- Villars, 1955 
Russell, B., A Critical Exposition of the Philosophy of Leibniz, Cambridge: 
Univ. Press, 1900, second ed., London: Allen and Unwin, 1937 
The Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1903; 2nd ed., 
London: Allen and Unwin, 1937; New York: Norton, 1938 
Philosophical Essays, London and New York: Longmans, 1910 
The Problems of Philosophy, Home University Library, 1912 
Our Knowledge of the External World, Chicago and London: Open 
Court Publishing Company, 1914. 2nd ed. London: Allen and Un- 
win, 1926. 

Mysticism and Logic, London: Longmans, 1918; now Allen and Unwin 
introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, London: Alien and Unwdn, 1919 
The Analysis of Mind, London: Allen and Unwin; New York: Macmillan, 
1921 

The Analysis of Matter, London: Kegan Paul, 1927 
An Outline of Philosophy, London: Allen and Unwin; New York: Norton, 
1927 

An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London: Alien and Unwin; New 
York: Norton, 1940 

A History of Western Philosophy, London: Allen and Unwin; New York: 
Simon and Schuster, 1946 

Human KnovAedge: Its Scope and Limits, London: Alien and Unwin; 

New York: Simon and Schuster, 1948 
Logic and Knowledge, Essays 1901-1950 (ed. R. C. Marsh), London: 
Alien and Unwin, 1956 

Russell, B. and Wbitehead, A. N., Principia Maihematica, Cambridge: Univ. 

Prep, Vol. I, 1910: VoL II, 1912; Vol. Ill, 1913, second ed., 1925-1927 
Ryle, G., Philosophical Arguments, Inaugural Lecture. London: Oxford Univ. 
Press, 1945. Reprinted in the present volume 
The Concept of Mind, London: Hutchinson, 1949 
Dilemmas, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1954 

G. de and Ziisel, E., The Development of Rationalism and Em- 
i ; piricism, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (Int. Encycl. of Unified 

■ " Science), 1941 

ocaachter, J., Prolegomena zii einer kritischen Grammatik, Vienna: Springer, 

, .. ‘^^chiick, M., ^um und 7ei: in der gegenwdrtigen Physik, Berlin: Springer, 

. . - 1917; 2nd ed. 1919. Eng. transL, Space and Time in Contemporary 

, . Physics, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1920 


n 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 390 ] 

ScMick, M. (continued) 

Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre, Berlin: Springer, 1918 
Vom Sinn des Lebens, Berlin: Weitkreis Verlag, 1927 
Fragen der Ethik, Vienna: Springer, 1930. Eng. transL, Problems of 
Ethics, New York: Prentice-Hall, 1939 
Gesammelte Aufsdtze 1926-36, Vienna: Gerold, 1938 
GesetZy Kausalitdt und Wahrscheinlichkeit, Vienna: Gerold, 1948 
Grundzuge der Natur philosophic, posthumous papers ed. W. Holitscher 
and J. Rauscher, Vienna: Gerold, 1948. Eng. transl., Philosophy of 
Nature, New York: Pbilosophicai Library, 1949 
Natur und Kultur, posthumous papers ed. J. Rauscher, Vienna: Hum- 
boidt Verlag, 1952 

Scbiick, M. and Hertz, P. (eds.), Helmholtz, H., Schriften zur Erkenntnis- 
theorie, Berlin: Springer, 1921 

Schuitzer, B,, Observation and Protocol Statement, London: Williams and 
Norgate, 1938 

Stabbing, L. S., Logical Positivism and Analysis, British Academy Annua! 
Philosophical Lecture, 1933 

Philosophy and the Physicists, London: Methuen, 1937 
Stevenson, C. L., Ethics and Language, New Haven: Yale Univ. Press, 1945 
Strawson, P. F., Introduction to Logical Theory, London: Methuen, 1952 
Stroll, A., The Emotive Theory of Ethics, Berkeley: Univ, of California 
Press, 1954 

Tarski, A.., Einjuhrung in die Mathematische Logik und die Methodologie 
der Mathematik, Vienna: Springer, 1937.^ Eng. iransL, Introduction 
to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Scietices, London: 
Oxford Univ. Press, 1941 

Logic, Semantics, Meta-Mathematics, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2956 
Toulmin, S. E., The Place of Reason in Ethics, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1950 
Philosophy of Science, London: Hutchinson, 1953 
The Uses of Argument, Cambridge: Univ. Press,- 1958 
Ullman, S., The Princiules of Semantics, Glasgow: Jackson, 1951; Oxford; 
Blackw'eii, 1958 

Urmson, J. O., Philosophical Analysis, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1956 
Waismann, F., Einfuhrung in das mathematische Denken, Vienna: Springer, 
1936. Eng. transl.. Introduction to Mathematical Thinking, London: 
Hafner, 1951 

Wamock, G. J., English Philosophv Since 1900, London: Oxford Univ. Press, 
1958 

Weinberg, J. K., An Examination of Logical Positivism, London: Kegan Paul; 

New' York: Harcourt Brace, 1936 
Weldon, T. D., The Vocabulary of Politics, London: Penguin, 1953 
Weyi, H., Philosophic der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft, Munich and 
Berlin, 1927. Eng. transl. (revised). Philosophy of Mathematics and 
Natural Science, Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press, 1949 
White, A. R., G. E. Moore. A Critical Exposition, Oxford: Blackwell, 1958 
White, M., Toward Reunion in Philosophy, Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 
1956 

Whitehead, A. N., An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowb 
edge, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1919 
The Concept of Nature, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1920 



.^mimraphy of Logical Positivism [^1] 

■- -* fc-o/? A_ N and Russell, B., Principia Mathematica, Cambndge: 

Vol i; 1910; vk H. 1912; VoL HI, 1913, second fd.. 1925-m7 

D The Ground of Induction, Cambridge: Harvard Univ. Press, 1947 
Interpretation and Analysis. Psyche Miniature, London: Kegan 

ProMe^^ of Mind and Matter, Cambridge: Univ. Press, 1934 
-v-v--- Min^, Ojfoid: Blackwell, 1952 

r- •“ c: - Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis, Oxford: Blackwell, 1953 ^ 

I . *.: I. O., Causation and the Foundations of Science, Pans: Hermann, 

• . The Metamorphosis of Philosophy, Cairo: Ai-Maaref Pres^ 

Foundations of Inference in Natural Science, London: Metnuen, 

M Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus {Uigisch-Philosophische Ab- 

- handlung), German version in Annalen der Naiurphilosophte, 1911; 

4 German and English, London: Kegan Paul, 1922 

Philosophical Investigations, Oxford: Blackwell; New York: Macimlian, 
1953 

Remarks on the F oundations of Maiheniancs, Oxford: Blackwell, 1956 
The Blue and Brown. Books, Oxford: Blackw'eil, 1958 
Woodger, J. H., Biological Principles, London: Kegan Paul, 1929 
T - The Axiomatic Method in Biology, London: Cam ondgeUmv. Pr^, 1937 

The Technique of Theory Construction, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press 
(Int Encycl. of Unified Science), 1939 
' Biology and Language, Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1952 

von Wrieht, G. H., The Logical Problem of Induction, Helsinki: Acta Philo- 
t: sophica Fennica, Fasc. 3, 1941; 2nd rev. ed., Oxford: Blackwell, 1957 

Den logiska Empirismen, Helsinki, 1943 

A Treatise on Induction and Probability', London; Pvoutiedge and Kegan 

Paul, 1951 ^ ..V 

Ziisel, E., Das Anwendungsproblemi. Ein pnilosophischer Vcrsuch uber das 
Gesetz der grossen Zahlen und die Induktion, Leipzig; Barth, 

Zilse!, E. and Santillana, G. de, The Development of Rationalism and Em- 
piricism, Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (int Encycl. of Unified Sd- 
. ence), 1941 

Zuurdeeg, W. F., A Research on the Consequences of the Vienna circle 

echt: Kemink en 21oon, N. U., 1946 


Philosophy for Ethics 


[ 392 ] 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 
ARTICLES 
The foUowing abbreviations are used in this list: 


A for Analysis 

AJ for Australasian Journal of Psychol- 
ogy and Philosophy 

Arch. F. Sy. Phil, for Archiv fur Sys- 
temadsche Philosophic 
ArSoc. for Proceedings of the Aristote- 
lian Society 

Ar.Soc.Sup. for Proceedings of the Aris- 
totelian Society, Supplementary 
Volumes 

BJPS for The British Journal for the 
Philosophy of Science 
E for Erkenntnis 
HI for Hibbert Journal 
JP for Journal of Philosophy 


JSL for Journal of Symbolic Logic 
JUS for Journal of Unified Science 
M for Mind 
P for Philosophy 

PPR for Philosophy and Phenomenologi- 
cal Research 

PQ for Philosophical Quarterly 
PR for Philosophical Review 
PS for Philosophy of Science 
PSt for Philosophical Studies 
Psych. Pc',', for Psychological Review 
Rev.Int.Pkil. for Revue Internationale de 
Piiilosophie 

RM for Reviev.- of Metaphysics 
T for Theoria 


Acton, H. B., “The Expletive Theon* of Morals,” A., 1936-37 
“Is Ethical Relativity Necessary?” Ar.Soc.Sup.. 193S 
“Moral Subjectivism,” A, 1948-49 

Adams, E. M., “A Critique of the Emotive Theory of Ethical Terms,” JF, 1949 
“Word-Magic and Logical Analysis in the Field of Efnics.” IP, 195G 
Aiken, K. D., “Emotive ‘Meanings’ and Ethical Terms,” JF, 1944 
“Stevenson’s Ethics and Language T JP, 1945 

“Evaluation and Obligation: Two Functions of judgments in the Lan- 
guage of Conduct,” JP, 1950. Reprinted in Sellars, H. and Hospers, 
J., Readings in Ethical Theory 
“The Authority of Moral Judgments,” PPR, 1951-52 
“Dennitions, Factual Premises and Ethical Conclusions.” PR, 1951 
“The Role of Conventions in Ethics,” JF, 1952 
Aidukiewicz, K.. “Zalozenia logiki tradycyjnej” (Assumptions of Traditional 
Logic), Frzegiad FUozoficzny, 1926-2? 

“Sprache und Sinn,” E, 1934 
“Das W'eltbild and die Begriffsapparatur,” E, 1934 
“Der iogistische Antiirationaiismus in Polen,” E, 1935-36 
“Die syntaktische Konnexitat,” Stadia Philosophica, 1935 
“W sprawie powszechnikow” (On Universals), Przeglad FUozoficzny, 1935 
“Die wissenschaftliche Weltperspektive,” E, 1935. Reprinted in English 
translation in Feigi, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical 
Analysis 

“Logic and Experience,” Synthese, 1950-51 
Aldrich, V. C., “Symbolization and Similarity,” Monist, 1932 

“A Note on the Empirical Meaning of ‘possible’,” A, 1936-37 
“Some Meanings of ‘Vague’,” A, 1936-37 

“Messrs. Schlick and Ayer on ImmonaJity,” PR, 1938. Reprinted in 
Feigi, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“The Spirit of the New Positivism,” JP, 1940 




The Philosophy 


.if?-&r ^rl 

jkbSography of Logical Positivism [ 393 ] 

' '' Aldrich, V. C. {continued) 

'■ '-.,-'^^«pictorial Meaning and Picture Thinking,** Kenyon Review, 1943. Re- 
■' printed in FeigI, H. and Seliars, W., Readings in Philosophical 

^ ’ Analysis 

' 4 " >. . ‘Xanguage, Experience and Pictorial Meaning/* /P, 1948 

*®The Informal Logic of the Employment of Expressions,” PR, 1954 
**TheLast Word on Being Red and Blue All Over,” PSt, 1954 
; / ‘The Origin of the AprioriT JPf 1954 
-“What Appears?,” PR, 1954 
Ts an After-Image a Sense-Datum?,” PPR, 1954-55 
“Mr^ Quine on Meaning, Naming, and Purporting to Name,” FSl, 1955 
“Expression by Enactment,” PPR, 1955-56 
. : Alexander, H. G., “Necessary Truth,” M, 1957 

' Alexander, P., “Other People’s Experiences,” Ar,Soc., 1950-51 
“Complementary Descriptions,” M, 1956 
AJston, W. P., “Are Positivists Metaphysicians?,” PR, 1954 
“Particulars — Bare and Qualified,” PPR, 1954-55 
“Pragmatism and the Verinability Tneory of Meaning,” PSt, 1955 
Tneffabiiity,” PP, 1956 

Ts a Sense-Datum Language Necessar>'?,” PS, 1957 
Ambrose, A., “Finitism in Mathematics, I and U,” M, 1935 

“Moore’s Proof of an External World,” in Schilnp. P. A-, The Philosophy 
of G. E, Moore, 1942 
“Self-contradictory Suppositions.” M. 1944 

“The Problem of Justifying Inductive Inference,” JP, 1947. Reprinted in 
Hook, S., American Philosophers a: IVork 
“Everett J. Nelson on The Relation of Logic to Metaphysics/” PR, 1949 
“Hie Problem of Linguistic Inadequacy/' in Black, M,. Philosophical 
Analysis, 1950 

“Linguistic Approaches to Philosophical Problems,” JP, 1952 
“Wittgenstein on Some Questions in the Foundations of Mathematics/’ 
JP, 1955 

“On Entailment and Logical Necessity,” Ar.Soc.. 1955-56 
Anderson, J., “The Meaning of Good,” AJ, 1942 
“Hypotheticals,” AJ, 1952 

Anscombe, G. E. M., “The Reality of the Pasi,” in Black. M.. Philosophical 
Analysis, 1950 

“The Principle of individuation/' Ar.SccSuv., 1955 
“Aristotle and the Sea Battle,” M, 1956 
“intention,” ArSoc., 1956-57 
' T “Pretending,” ArSocSup., 1958 

Armstrong, J. H., “Knowledge and Belief,” .4, 1952-53 
: Ashby, R. W., “Use and Verification,” ArSoc., 1955-56 

von Aster, E., “Kritischer Objekiivismus und Neopositivismus.” J, 1950 
“Physikaiistischer und Psychologistischer Positivismus/' T, 1950 
, Atkinson, R. F-, “ ‘Good’ and ‘Right* and ‘Probable’ in Language, Truth and 
■ *;/ ■ ^ LogicT M, 1955 

u Anstm, J. L., “Are There A Priori Concepts?,” Ar.SocSup., 1939 

“Other Minds,” Ar.SocSup., 1946. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic and 
. ’ Language (second serf's) 

: ArSocSup., 1950 

“How to Talk,” ArSoc., 1952-53 


in Black, hi.. Philosouhical 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 394 ] 

Atsstm, J. L. {continued) 

“A Plea for Excuses,” ArSoc., 1956-57 
“Pretending,” ArSocSup., 1958 
Ayer, A. J., “Atomic Propositions,” A, 1933-34 

“The Genesis of Metaphysics,” A, 1933-34. Reprinted in Macdonald, M. 
Philosophy and Analysis 

“On Particulars and Universals,” ArSoc., 1933-34 
“Demonstration of the Impossibility of Metaphysics,” M, 1934. Reprinted 
in Edwards, P. and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 
“Internal Relations,” ArSocSup,, 1935 

“The Criterion of Truth,” A, 1935-36. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., 
Philosophy and Analysis 
“The Principle of Verifiability,” M, 1936 

“Concerning the Negation of Empirical Propositions,” E, 1936-37 
“Truth by Convention,” A, 1936-'^! 

“Verification and Experience,” ArSoc,, 1936-37. Reprinted in the present 
volume 

“Does Philosophy Analyse Common Sense?,” Ar.Soc.Siip., 1937 
“On the Scope of Empirical Knowledge. A Rejoinder to Bertrand Russel! ” 
E, 1937-38 

“The Terminology' of Sense-Data,” M, 1945. Reprinted in Philosophical 
Essays 

“Jean-Paui Sartre,” Horizon, 1945 
“Albert Camus,” ibid. 

“Deistic Fallacies,” Polemic, 1945 

“Freedom and Necessity,” Polemic, 1946. Reprinted in Philosophical 
Essays 

‘The Claims of Philosophy,” Polemic, 1947. Reprinted in Reflections on 
Our Age: Unesco, 1948 

“Tne Principle of Utility,” in Keeton, G. W. and Schwarzenberger, G., 
Jeremy Bentham and the Law, London: Stevens, 1948. Reprinted in 
Philosophical Essays 

“Some Aspects of Existentialism,” Rationalist Annual, 1948 
“On the Analysis of Moral Judgements,” Horizon, 1949. Reprinted in 
Philosophical Essays and in Munitz, M. K., ^ Modern Introduction 
to Ethics 

“Basic Propositions,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 195C. Re- 
printed in Philosophical Essays 

^X)n What There is,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1951. Reprinted in Fkiiosopkical Essays 
“The Philosophy of Science,” in Heath, A. E., Scientific Thought in the 
Twentieth Century, London: Watts, 1951 
“Statements about the Past,” Ar.Soc., 1951-52. Reprinted in Philosophical 
Essays 

“Individuals,” M, 1952. Reprinted in Philosophical Essays 
“Negation,” JP, 1952. Reprinted in Philosophical Essays 
“Cogito Ergo Sum,” A, 1952-53 

“The Identity of Indiscemibles,” in Proceedings of the Xhh International 
Congress of Philosophy, 1953. Reprinted in Philosophical Essays 
“L’immutabilite du passe,” Etudes Philosophiques, 1953 
“One’s Knowledge of Other Minds,” T, 1953. Reprinted in Philosophical 
Essays 

“Truth,” RevJnt.PhiL, 1953 


• ^Uography oj Logical Positivism { 395 ] 

'kvts A. I- (continued) 

«Caii There Be a Private Language?,” ArSocSup.. 1954 

Is Communication?,” in Studies in Communication, London: Seeker 
and Warburg, 1955 

' **Phllosophy at Absolute Zero,” Encounter, 1955 
' ■ *What Is a Law of Nature?,” Rev.Int,PhiL, 1956 

"Philosoptiical Scepticism,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British Philos- 
ophy (third series), 1956 

: “Perception,” in Mace, C. A., British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, 1957 

^The Conception of Probability as a Logical Relation,” in Observation 
and Interpretation: Proceedings of the Ninth Symposium of the 
Colston Research Society, 1957 

“Meaning and Intentionality,” Proceedings of the Xlltk International 
Congress of Philosophy, Venice, 1958 
“Pbilosophie et iangage ordinaire,” Dialectica, 1958 
Ayer, A. I., and Copieston, F. C., “Logical Positirism — a Debate,” in Edwards, 
p! and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 
Bachmann, F. and Carnap, R., “Ober Extremalaxiome,” £, 1936-37 
Baier, K., “Objectivity in Ethics,” AJ, 1948 
“Decisions and Descriptions,” M, 1951 
“The Ordinary Use of Words,” ArSoc., 1951-51: 

“Good Reasons,” PSt, 1953 
“The Point of View of Morality,” AJ, 1954 
“Contradiction and Absurdity,” A, 1954-55 
Baler, K. and Touinain, S. E., “On Describing,” M, 1952 
Bar-Hiliei, Y., “Analysis of ‘Correct’ Language,” M. 1946 
“Comments on Logical Form,” PSt, 1951 
“Indexicai Expressions,” M, 1954 
“Logical Syntax and Semantics,” Language. 1954 
Barnes, W. H. F., “A Suggestion about Value.” .4, 1933-34. Reprinted m 
Sellars, W. and Hospers, J., Readings in Etnical Theory 
“Meaning and Verifiability,” P, 1939 
“The Myth of Sense Data,” Ar.Soc., 1944-45 
“Is Phiiosophy Possible? A Study of Logical Positivism." P, 1947 
“Ethics Without Propositions,” ArSoeSup.. 194^ 

“Talking about Sensations,” Ar.Soc., 1953-54 

“On Seeing and Hearing,” in Lewis, H. D., C onienivorary British Philos- 
ophy (third series), 1956 

Barrett, W., “Logical Empiricism and the Histor*’ o: Philosophy,” JF, 1939 
“On the Existence of an External World,” JF. 1939 
“The Present State of the Problem of induction,” J. i9-r0 
Barzin, M., “L’empirisme iogique,” Rev.Ini.PhiL, 1950 
Basson, A. H., “The Existence of Material Objects,” M, 1946 
“Logic and Fact,” A, 1947-48 
“The Problem of Substance,” ArSoc., 1948-49 
“The Immortality of the Soul,” M, 1950 
‘The Logical Status of Supposition,” ArSoc. Sup., 1951 
' ' . “Unsolvabie Problems,” Ar.Soc., 1956-57 
Basson, A. H. and O’Connor, D. J., “Language and Phiiosophy,” P, 1947 
Baylis, C. A., “Are Some Propositions Neither True Nor False?,” PS, 1936 
f r " “Critical Comments on the ‘Symposium on Meaning and Truth,’ ” PPR, 
1944-45 


1 




Bibliography of Logical Positivism 




I ^ 


i 

I 

I 

■ 








Bill®! 


' ‘ 






„ .'-r.t'M 




[ 396 ] 


PR, 1944 


Bayiis, C. A. (continued) 

“Facts, Propositions, Exemplification and Tnitli,” M, 194S 

“Universais, Communicable Knowledge, and Metaphysics,” /F, 1951 

**The Confirmation of Value Judgments,” PR, 1952 

“Intrinsic Goodness,” PPR, 1952-53 

“Logical Subjects and Physical Objects,” PPR, 1956-57 

Beardsley, E., “Imperative Sentences in Relation to Indicatives,” PR, 1944 

Beardsley, M., “Phenomenalism and Determinism,” IP, 1942 
“Categories,” RM, 1954 

Beck, L. W., “Remark on the Distinction between Analytic and Synthetic,” 
PPR, 1948-49 

“On the Meta-Semantics of the Problem of the Synthetic A priori/" M, 
1957 

Behman, J., “Sind die mathematischen Urteile analytisch oder synthetisch?,” 
E, 1934 

Benjamin, A. C., “Outlines of an Empirical Theory of Meaning,” PS, 1936 
“The Unholy Alliance of Positivism and Operationalism,” IP, 1942 
“On Defining Science,” Scientific Monthly, 1949 
“Operationalism — ^A Critical Evaluation,” JP, 1950 
“A Definition of ‘Empiricism,’ ” PPR, 1954-55 

Bennett, J., “Meaning and Implication,” M, 1954 

Bergmann, G-, “On Physicalistic Models of Non-physical Terms,” PS, 1940 
“On Some Methcxiological Problems of Psycholog>%” PS, 1940. Re- 
printed in Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philosophy of 
Science 

“The Subject Matter of Psychology,” PS, 1940 
“The Logic of Probabiiit>%” American Journal of Pl^ysics, 1941 
“An Empiricist Schema of the Psychophysical Problem,” PS, 1942 
“Remarks Concerning the Epistemology of Scientific Emniricism,” PS, 
1942 

“Outline of an Empirical Philosophy of Physics,” American Journal of 
Physics, 1943. Reprinted in Feigi, H. and Brodbeck,' M., Readings 
in the Philosophy of Science 

“An Empiricist’s System of the Sciences,” Scientific Monthly, 1944 
“Pure Semantics, ^ntences and Propositions,” M, 1944 
“Frequencies, Probabilities and Positivism,” PPR, 1945-46 
“Remarks on Realism,” PS, 1946. Reprinted in The Metaphysics of Logi- 
cal Positivism 

“Some Comments on Carnap’s Logic of Induction,” PS, 1946 
“Russell on Particulars,” PR, 1947. Reprinted in The Metaphysics of 
Logical Positivism 

“Sense Data, Linguistic Conventions and Existence,” PS, 1947. Reprinted 
in The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 
“Professor Ayer’s Analysis of Klnowing,” A, 1948-49. Reprinted in The 
Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 
“Two Criteria for an Ideal Language,” PS, 1949 

“On Non-perceptual Intuition,” PPR, 1949-50. Reprinted in The Meta- 
physics of Logical Positivism 

“Logical Positivism,” in Perm, V., A History of Philosophical Systems, 
1950. Reprinted ia The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 
“A Note on Ontology,” PSt, 1950. Reprinted in The Metaphysics of 
Logical Positivism 





:■ sibliography of Logical Positivism [ 397 ] 

Beremann, G. {continued) 

‘Two Cornerstones of Empiricism,” Synihese, 1950-51. Reprinted m The 
Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 

“Logical Atomism, Elementarism and the Analysis of Value,” PS, 1951. 

Reprinted m The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 
‘The Logic of Psychological Concepts,” PS, 1951 

“Two Types of Linguistic Philosophy,” RM, 1951-52. Reprinted in The 
Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 

“The Problem of Relations in Classical Psychology,” PQ, 1952. Reprinted 
in The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 
“The Identity of Indiscernibles and the Formalist Definition of ‘Iden- 
tity/ ” M, 1953. Reprinted in The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 
“Logical Positivism, Language, and the Reconstruction of Metaphysics,” 
in Rivisia Critica di Storia della Filosofia, 1953. Reprinted in The 
Metaphysics of Logical Positivism 

“The Revolt against Logical Atomism,” Parts I and 11, PQ, 1951 and 1958 
Berlin, I., “Induction and Hypothesis,” ArSocSup., 1937 
“Verification,” Ar.Soc,, 1938-39 
“Logical Translation,” Ar.Soc., 1949-50 

“Empirical Propositions and Hypothetical Statements,” M, 1950 
Black, M., “Philosophical Analysis,” Ar.Soc., 1932-33 
“A propos of ‘Facts,’ ” A, 1933-34 

“Is Analysis a Useful Method in Philosophy?,” ArSocSup., 1934 
“The Principle of Verifiability,” A, 1934-35 
‘Truth by Convention,” A, 1936-37 

“Vagueness,” PS, 1937. Reprinted in Language and Philosophy 
“Some Problems Connected with Language,” ArSoc., 1938-39. Reprinted 
as “Wittgenstein’s Tractatuf* in Language and Philosophy 
“Relations between Logical Positivism and the Cambridge School of 
Analysis,” JUS, 1939-40 

“Comments on a Recent Version of Phenomenalism,” A, 1939-40 
“Certainty and Empirical Statements,” M, 1942 

“Ogden and Richards’ Theory of Interpretation,” JP, 1942. Reprinted in 
Language and Philosophy 

“Schilpp’s The Philosophy of G. E. MooreP JP, 1943 
“The Analysis of a Simple Necessary' StatemenL” JP, 1943 
“The ‘Paradox of Analysis,’ ” M, 1944 

“Russell’s Philosophy of Language,” in Schilpp, P. A., The Philosophy 
of Bertrand Russell, 1944. Reprinted in Language and Philosophy 
“The ‘Paradox of Analysis’ Again: a Reply,” M, 1945 
“How Can Analysis Be informative?,” PPR, 1945-46 
“The Limitations of a Behavioristic Semiotic,” PR, 1947. Reprinted as 
“The Semiotic of Charles Morris,” in Language and Philosophy 
“The Semantic Definition of Truth,” A, 1947-48. Reprinted in Macdonald, 
M., Philosophy and Analysis, and in Language and Philosophy 
“Linguistic Method in Philosophy,” PPR, 1947-48. Reprinted in Lan- 
guage and Philosophy 

“Some Questions about Emotive Meaning,” PR, 1948. Reprinted in JLan- 
guage and Philosophy 

“Logic and Semantics,” in Philosophical Studies — Essays in Memory of 
. Susan St ebbing, 1948. Reprinted in Problems of Analysis as “Car- 

nap on Logic and Semantics” 



Bibliography of Logical Positivism 





[398 ] 

Black, M. {continued) 

‘^Carnap’s Semantics,” PR, 1949 
“The Definition of Scientific Method,” in Stauffer, R. C., Science and 
Civilization, 1949. Reprinted in Problems of Analysis 
“The Justification of Induction,” in Language and Philosophy, 1949 
“Dn Speaking with the Vulgar,” PR, 1949 

“AcMiies and the Tortoise,” A, 1950-51. Reprinted in Problems of Anal- 
ysis 

“Definition, Presupposition, and Assertion,” PR, 1952. Reprinted in Prob- 
lems of Analysis 

“Phenomenalism,” in Science, Language and Human Rights (Proceed- 
ings of American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division), 1952. 
Reprinted as “The Language of Sense-Data” in Problems of Analysis 
“The Identity of Indiscemibles,” M, 1952. Reprinted in Problems of 
Analysis 

‘^ying and Disbelieving,” A, 1952-53. Reprinted in Problems of Analysis, 
and in Macdonald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Metaphor,” ArSoc,, 1954-55 

“Why Cannot an Effect Precede its Cause?,” A, 1955-56 
Biaashard, B., “The New Subjectivism in Ethics,” PPR, 1948-49. Reprinted 
in Edwards, P. and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 
“Subjectivism in Ethics. A Criticism,” PQ, 1951 
Blumberg, A. £., “The Nature of Philosophic Analysis,” PS, 1935 
Bimnberg, A. E. and Boas, G., “Some Remarks in Defense of the Operational 
Theoiy' of Meaning,” JP, 1931 

Blumberg, A. E. and Feigl, H., “Logical Positivism, a New^ Movement in 
European Philosophy,” JP, 1931 

Boas, G. and Blumberg, A. E., “Some Remarks in Defense of the' Operational 
Theor>' of Meaning,” JP, 1931 

Bohneit, H. G., “The Semiotic Status of Commands,” PS, 1945 
“Lewis’ Attribution of Value to Objects,” PSt, 1950 
Bouwsma, O. K.. “Moore’s Theory of Sense-Data,” in Schiipp, P. A., The 
Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1942 
“Naturalism,” JP, 1948 

“Toe Expression Theory of Art,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 

1950- Reprinted in Eiton, W., Aesthetics and Language 
“The Mvsterv of Time (or. The Man Who Did Not Know What Time 
Is),” JP, 1954 

“Refiections on Moore’s Recent Book,” PR, 1955 j 

Braithw'aite, R. B-, “Universals and the 'Method of Analysis,’ ” Ar.SocSup., 

1926 

“Verbal Ambiguity and Philosophical Analysis,” ArSoc., 1927-28 
“The Nature of Believing,” ArSoc. , 1932-33 

“Imaginary Objects,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1933 ^ 

“Philosophy,” in Cambridge University Studies, Cambridge Univ. Press, : 

1933 i 

“Solipsism and ‘the Common Sense View of the World,’ ” A, 1933-34 H 

“Prepositions about Material Objects,” ArSoc., 1937-38 ^ 

‘The Relevance of Psychology' to Logic,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1938 -I 

“Two Ways of Definition by Verification,” E, 1937-38 d 

“The New' Physics and Metaphysical Materialism,” Ar.Soc., 1942-43 1 

“Belief and Action,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1946 



SihUography of Logical Positivism [ 399 ] 

gffWh waite. R. B. {continued) 

^ “Teleological Explanation,” ArSoc,, 1946-47 
“Redocibiilty,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1952 

^iDonmioii Action Towards Different Moral Ends,” Ar.Soc., 1952-53 
^Probability and Induction,” in Mace, C. A., British Philosophy in the 
Mid-Century, 1957 

Brandt, R., “An Emotional Theory of the Judgment of Moral Words,” Ethics, 
1941-42 

‘The Emotive Theory of Ethics,” PR, 1950 
“The Status of Empirical Assertion Theories in Ethics,” M, 1952 
“The Languages of Realism and Nominalism,” PPR, 1956-57 
Bridgman, P. W., “Operational Analysis,” PS, 1938 
“Science: Public or Private?,” PS, 1940 
“The Operational Aspect of Meaning,” Synthese, 1950-51 
“The Nature of Some of Our Physical Concepts, I and 11,” BJPS, 1950-52 
Britton, K., “Empirical Foundation for Logic,” A, 1934-35 
“Language: Public and Private,” Monisi, 1935 
“The Truth of Religious Propositions,” A, 1935-36 
“On Public Objects and Private Objects,” Monlst, 1936 
“Reason and the Rules of Language,” Ar.Soc., 1938-39 
“The Description of Logical Properties,” A, 1940 
“Are Necessary Truths True by Convention?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1947 
“The Nature of Arithmetic — A Reconsideration of Mill’s Views,” Ar.Soc., 
1947-48 

“Truth and Knowledge: Some Comments on Russell,” A, 1947-48 
“Seeming,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1952 

“What Does a Moral Judgment Commit Me To?,” Ar.Soc., 1953-54 
“Feelings and their Expression,” P, 1957 
Broad, C. D., “Phenomenalism,” Ar.Soc., 1914-15 

“Is There Knowledge by Acquaintance?,” ArSoc.Sup., 1919 
“The Character of Cognitive Acts,” Ar.Soc., 1920-21 
“Critical and Speculative Philosophy,” in Muirhead, J. H., Contemporary 
British Philosophy (first series), 1924 
‘The Principles of Problematic Induction,” Ar.Soc., 1927-28 
“Is ‘Goodness’ a Name of a Simple Non-natural Quality?,” ArSoc., 
1933-34 

“Mechanical and Teleological Causation,” Ar.Soc.Siip., 1935 
“Are There Synthetic A Priori Truths?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1936 
“Certain Features in Moore’s Ethical Doctrines,” in Schiipp, P. A*, The 
Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1942 
- “Hr. von Wright on the Logic of Induction, I-III,” M, 1944 

“Some of the Main Problems of Ethics,” P, 1946. Reprinted in Feigl, H. 

and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“Some Methods of Speculative Philosophy,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1947 
“Some Elementary Reflections on Sense-Perception,” P, 1952 
“The Local Historical Background of Contemporary Cambridge Philos- 
ophy,” in Mace, C. A., British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, 1957 
Bxonstein, D. J., “Stebbing’s Directional Analysis and Basic Facts,” A, 1934-35 
“What Is Logical Syntax?,” A, 1935-36 
_ “The Meaning of Implication,” M, 1936 

Brotman, H., “Could Space be Four Dimensional?,” M, 1952. Reprinted in 
. Flew, A., Essays in Conceptual Analysis 


[ 400 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Brown, D. "What the Tortoise Taught Us,” M, 1954 
“Misconceptions of Inference,” A, 1954-55 
“Evaluative Inference,” P, 1955 
“The Nature of Inference,” PR, 1955 
Brown, N., “Sense-data and Material Objects,” M, 1957 
Brown, R. and Walling, J., “Amending the Verification Principle,” A, 1950-5! 
“Hypothetical Statements in Phenomenalism,” Synthese, 1950-51 
“Connterf actual Conditionals,” M, 1952 
Buchdahl, G., “Induction and Scientific Method, M, 1951 
“Inductive Process and Inductive Inference,” AJ, 1956 
“Science and Metaphysics,” in Pears, D. F., The Nature of Metaphysics, 
1957 

Buchler, I., “Dr, von Juhos and Physicalism,” A, 1935-36 
“Value-Statements,” A, 1936-37 
‘The Class of ‘Basic’ Sentences,” M, 1939 

“Russell and the Principles of Ethics,” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy 
of Bertrand Russell, 1944 

Buckley, F. B., “Analysis of ‘X Could Have Acted Othervrise,’ ” PSi, 1956 
Burks, A. W., “Icon, Index and Symbol,” PPR, 1948-49 
“The Logic of Causal Propositions,” M, 1951 
“Reichenbach’s Theor>’ of Probability and Induction,” RM, 1950-51 
“A Tbeor>' of Proper Names,” PSt, 1951 
“On the Presuppositions of Induction,” RM, 1955 
Bushkovitch, A, V., “Some Consequences of the Positivistic Interpretation of 
Physics,” PS, 1940 

Butler, R. J., “The Scaffolding of Russell’s Theory of Descriptions,” PR, 1954 
“Aristotle’s Sea Fight and Three-Valued Logic,” PR, 1955 
“Language Strata and Alternative Logics,” AJ, 1955* 

“A Wittgensteinian on the ‘Reality of the Past,’ ” PQ, 1956 
Campbell. C. A., “Common-sense Propositions and Philosophical Paradoxes,” 
Ar.5oc.’ 1944-45 

“Ethics without Propositions,” M, 1950 

“Mr. Edwards on ‘drdinar>^ Language and Absolute Certainty,’ ” FSt, 1950 
“Is ‘Freewill’ a Pseudo-Problem?,” M, 1951. Reprinted in Edwards, P. 

and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 
“Ryle on the Intellect,” PQ, 1953 

Capek, M., “The Development of Reichenbach’s Epistemology,” RM, 1957-58 
Capilowish, L M., “Language Analysis and Metaphysical Inqmr}%” PS, 1949 
Capilowisb, I. M. and Kaplan, A., “Must There Be Propositions?,” M, 1939 
Carmichael, P., “Prof. Ayer on Individuals,” A, 1953-54 
Carnap, R., “Ober die Aufgabe der Physik und die Anwendung des Grundsatzes 
der Einfachheit,” Kanstudien, 1923 

“Dreidimensionaiitat des Raumes und Kausalitat,” Ann. d .Philos,, 1924 
“Uber die Abh^gigkeit der Eigenschaften des Raumes von denen der 
Zeit,” Kanstudien, 1925 

“Eigentiiche und uneigentliche Begriffe,” Symposion, 1927 
“Die Mathematik als Zweig der Logik,” BLf^Dt. Philos., 1930 
“Die aite und die neue Logik,” E, 1930-31. Eng. transL in the present 
volume. Fr. transL in Actualites Scientifiques, 1933 
“Bericht fiber Untersuchungen zur ailgemeinen Axiomatik,” E, 1930-31 
“Die iogizistische Grundiegung der Mathematik,” E, 1931-32 
“Uberwindung der Metaphysik dwch iogische Analyse der Sprache,” E, 




[401] 


^0iography of Logical Positivism 

transl. in the present volume „ 

' «Tv- nhvsikalische Sprache als Universalsprache der Wisse^haft, E, 
^ 1931-32. Eng. transl., The Unity of Science. London: Kegan Paul, 

■ -psyStgie in physikahscher Sprache.” E. 1932-33. Eng. transl. in the 

tyrcscnt voiiHUC 

“t^bcr Protokoiisatze, E, 1932-33 « 

«On the Character of Philosophicai Problems, ' PS, ^^34 

“S^etische Fragen nnd praktische Entscheidungen, Natuf und Geist, 

-Die^JSinomien und die UnvoUstandigkeit der Mathematik,” Mounts. 

“FormS^ffienschaft und Realwissenschaft,” E, 1935-36. ^ 

^Fom^ and Factual Science” in FeigI, H. and Brodbeck, M.. Read- 

“Les'cOTMpte^pfychXgiques^ et les concepts physiques sont-ils fonciere- 

“Die Me&JS tologSSen Vj//e.me Congres Intern, de 

Acres du Congres Intern, de Philosophie 

“Obefl^e'Enhetesprachfder^W^ dn Congres Intern. 

de Philosophie Scieniifique, Paris 19p. 19j6 , -_9 « ^ripntia 

“Exist-t-il des premisses de ia science qui scient incontrolables., Scientia, 

“Tesibmtv and Meaning, M^^” PS, 1936 and 1937. Reprinted, New 
S^en: Graduate Philosophy Club. Yale Univ.. and ( “ 
Feigl. H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in tne Pndosophy of Science 
“Logic,” in Factors Determining Hitman Behavior, Cambnage. H-nard 

“Ein^h der Wissenschaft dutch Hnheit der Sprache,” Actes IXe Congres 

“Loi^''FouncSiont’rf''tL^Unity of Science,” ^ 

Unihed Science Chicago: Univ. of Chic. Press (Int. EncycL 

fied Science), 193 8. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings 

in Philosophical Analysis 

“Science and Analysis of Language,” JUS, 1940 ^ , 

“The Two Concepts of Probability,” PPRs 1944-45. Reprinted m eig^ 
H and Sellars, W., Readings in Pkilosopnical Analysis,^ and in 
Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philosophy of Science 
“Hall and' Bergmann on Semantics,” M, 1945 
“On Inductive Logic,” PS, 1945 
' • “Remarks on Induction and Truth, ’ PPR, 194:?- 6 
“Modalities and Quantification,” JSL, 1946 
‘Theory and Prediction in Science,” Science, 1946 
“Probability as a Guide in Life,” JP, 

“On the Application of Inductive Logic, PPR, 1947-48 
,,J: “Remarks on the Paradox of Analysis: A Reply to Leonard Lmsky, P , 

. 1Q49 

“Truth and Confirmation,” in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings m 
Philosophical Analysis, 1949 



[ 402 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Carnap, R. (continued) 

“Empiricism, Semantics and Ontologj^” RevJntBhiL, 1950, Reprinted 
in Linsky, L., Semantics and the Philosophy of Language 
“The Problem of Relations in Inductive Logic,” 195! 

“Meaning Postulates,” PSt, 1952 

“On the Comparative Concept of Confirmation,” B/P5, 1952-53 
“Meaning and Synonymy in Natural Langnages,” PSt, 1955. Reprinted in 
Hook, S., American Philosophers at Work 
“On Some Concepts of Pragmatics,” PSt, 1955 

“The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts,” in Feigi, H, 
and Scriven, M., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 
VoL I 

Carnap, R, and Bachmann, F., “Ober Extremalajdome,” E, 1936-37 
Carritt, E. F., “Moral Positivism and Moral Aestheticism,” P, 1938. Reprinted 
in Seliars, W. and Hospers, J., Readings in Ethical Theory 
Cartwright, R. L., “Ontology and the Theor>' of Meaning,” PS, 1954 
Chisholm, R. M., “Sextus Empiricus and Modem Empiricism,” PS, 1941 
“The Problem of the Speckled Hen,” M, 1942 

“Russell on the Foundations of Empirical Knowledge,” in Schiipp, P. A., 
The Philosophy of Bertrand Russefl, 1944 
“The Contrar>-to-Fact Conditional.” M, 1946. Reprinted in Feigi, H. 

and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical A.nalysis 
“The Problem of Empiricism,” /P, 194S 

“The Theor>" of Appearing,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950 
“Philosophers and Ordinary Language,” PR, 1951 
“Reichenbach on Observing and Perceiving,” PSt, 1951 
“Verification and Perception,” RevJntPhiL, 1951 
“Comments on me ‘Proposal Theor/’ of Philosophy,” IF, 1952 
“Inientionaiity and the Theory of Signs.” PSt, 195J 
“Law' Statements and Counter-Facmal Inference,” A, 1954-55 
“A Note on Carnap's Meaning Analysis.” PSt. 1955 
“Sentences about Believing,” ArJoc,, 1955-56 
“Epistemic Statements and the Ethics of Belief,” PPP, 1955-56 
“ ‘Appear,' ‘Take’ and ‘Evident,* ” JP, 1956 
Church, A., “Logic, Formal,” in Runes, D. D., Dictionary of Philosophy, 1942 
“On Carnap’s Analysis of Statements of Assertion and Belief,” A, 1949- 
50. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“The Need for Abstract Entities in Semantic Analysis,” Proceedings of 
the Amer. Acad, of Arts and Sciences, 1951 
“intentional isomorphism and Identity of Belief,” PS*. 1954 
Chwistek, L., “Zasada sprzecznosd w' swietie now'szych badan Bertranda Rus- 
sella” (The Principle of Contradiction in the Light of Recent In- 
vestigations of Bertrand Russell), Rozorawy Akademii Umiejetnosci, 
1912 

“Tr 2 >^ odczyty odnoszace sie do poiecia iscnienia” (Three Lectures Relating 
to the Concept of Existence), Przeglad Filozopczny , 1917 
“Antynomje logiki formainej” (Antinomies of Formal Logic), Przeglad 
Filozoftczny, 1921 

“Ober die Antinomien der Prinzipien der Mathemaiik,” Mathematische 
Zeitschrift, 1922 

“Zastosowanie metody konstrukcyjnej do teorji poznania” (The Appli- 


^bibliography of Logical Positivism I i 

Method to the Theory of Knowledge), 

.C'- przegiad Filozoficzny, 1923 , , -.jr 

Hheory of Constructive Types (Principles of Logic and Ma^e- 
" matics) ” Annales de la Sociiti Polonaise de Mathematique, 1924 

,: r \ -Nen^^ro^agen der Logjk und Mathematik,” Mathematische Zeit- 

schTiftf 1929 . . 

“Ncue Grundlagen der Logik und Mathematik* Zweite Mitteilung, 
Mathematische Zeitschrift, 1932 , ^ ^ 

“Tragedia werbalnej metafizyki” (The Tragedy of Verbal Metaphysics), 

/ - Kwartainik Filozoficzny, 1932 

' ' **]3ie nominalistische Grundlegung der Mathematik, F, 193 *--3 3 

**0 granicach nauki” (Concerning the Boundaries of Science), Sprawoz- 
''dania Poznanskiego Towarzystwa Przyjaciol Nauk, 1935 
’ ■- “Rola semantyki racjonalnej w filozofi. Filozofiiczne znaczenie logiki 
semantycznej” (The Role of Semantics in Philosophy. Philosophical 
Significance of Semantical Logic), Przeglad Filozoficzny, 1936 
‘'Rola zasady konsekwencyi w zagadnieniu sprawiedliwosci spolecznej 
(The Role of the Principle of Consistency in the Problem of Social 
Justice), Przeglad Filozoficzny, 1936 
“Oberwindung des Begriffsrealismus,” Studia Phllosophica, 1937 
Cobitz, J. L., “The Appeal to Ordinary Language,” A, 1950-51 
Cohen, L. J., “Are Philosophical Theses Relative to Language?,” A, 1948-49 
‘Tense Usage and Propositions,” A, 1950-51. Reprinted in Macdonald, 
M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Three- Valued Ethics,” P, 1951 

“A Relation of Counterf actual Conditionals to Statements of Wnat 
Makes Sense,” Ar.Soc., 1954-55 
“On the Use of ‘the Use of," ” P, 1955 

“Theory and Definition in Jurisprudence,” ArSocSup,, 1955 
Coliingwood, R. G., “On the So-called Idea of Causation, y4r.5o*...,^^93/“38 
Cooley, J. C., “Prof. Goodman’s Fact, Fiction and Forecast/* JP, 1957 
Copi, 1. M., “Modern Logic and the Synthetic A Priori,” JP, 1949 
“Godel and the Synthetic A Priori: A Rejoinder,” IP, 1950 
“Philosophy and Language,” RM, 1950-51 
“Analytical Philosophy and Analytical Propositions ” FSt, 1953 
“Further Remarks on Definition and Analysis,” PSt, 1956 
C^opleston, F. C., “A Note on Verification,” M, 1950. Reprinted in Contem- 
porary Philosophy . . , .. . TA T> 

“Some Reflections on Logical Positivism,” Dublin Review^ 1950. Re- 
printed in Contemporary Philosophy 

“Contemporary British Philosophy,” Gregorianum, 1953. Reprintea in 
Contemporary Philosophy 

‘The Function of Metaphysics,” P, 1953. Reprinted in Contemporary 
Philosophy 

“On Seeing and Noticing,” P, 1954. Reprinted in Contemporary Philos- 
. ophy 

■ ■ “A Further Note on Verification,” in Contemporary Philosophy, 1956 

’r^Copleston, F. C. and Ayer, A. J., “Logical Positivism — A Debate,” in Ed- 

"Jv” ' ' wards, P. and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy, 1957 










[404] 

Cornelius, H., ' 
Comforth, M,, 
1934 

Consi.n, B. R., 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

‘Ziir Kiitik der wisscESciiaftliclien Grandbegriffe,” £, 193 | 

“Is Analysis a Useful Method in Philosophy?,’’ ArSocSup 


Cousin, B. R-, “Some Doubts about Knowledge,” ArSoc., 1935-36 
“Propositions,” Ar^oc,, 1948-49 
“Carnap’s Theories of Truth,” M, 1950 
‘Truth,” ArSocJSup., 1950 
“How Not to Talk,” A, 1954-55 

Crombie, I. M., “The Possibility of Theological Statements,” in Mitchell B 
Faith and Logic, 1957 ’ ” 

Cross, R. C., “The Emotive Theory of Ethics,” ArFocSup,, 1948 
“Ethical Disagreement,” P, 1950 

Cunningham, G. W., “On the Linguistic Meaning-Situation,” PPR, 1943-44 
Curry, H. B., “Language, Metalanguage, and Formal System,” PR, 1950 
“Mathematics, Syntactics and Logic,” M, 1953 
Baitz, E., “The Picture Theory of Meaning,” Af, 1953. Reprinted in Flew, A 
Essays in Conceptual Analysis 
Balkey, N., “The Limits of Meaning,” PPR, 1943-44 
van Dantzig, D., “Carnap’s Foundation of Probabilitv Theon^ ” Svnth^s^ 
1950-51 ' ' . - 

Demos, R., “Aspects of Positivism,” PPR, 1952-53 

Dewey, J,, “Unity of Science as a Social Problem.’* in Neorath. 0. al 
Encyclopedia and Unified Science, 1938 
Dingier, H., “Ober den Aufbau der experimentellen Physik.” E. 1931-32 
Donagan,^ A.^ ^“Recent Criticisms of Russell’s iknalysls of Existence?’ A, 

“The Verihcation of Historical Theses,” PQ, 1956 
“Explanation in Hisiory%” M, 1957, reprinted in Gardiner. P., Theories 
of History 

Dotterel, R. rf., “The Operational Test of Meaninglessness. " Monis:, 193z 
Dubislav, W., “Uber das Verhaltnis der Logik zur Mathematik;’ Ann.dPhilo^ 
1925-26 

“Zur kalkiilmassigen Charakterisierung der Denmtionen.’' 'Ann d Philos 
1928-29 

“Zur Lehre von den sog. schopferischen Definiiionen.*' Pans I and II, 
Philos Jahrb.d.Gorresges., 1928 and 1929 
“Zur Philosophie der Mathematik und Naturwisser^-craf' ” Anr ^ PrHo^ 
1929 ' — " 

“Uber den sogenannten Gegenstand der Mathemaiik.*’ £. 1930-31 
“Bemerkungen zur Dennitionslehre,” 1932-33 
Duc^se, C. J., “Verification, Verifiability and Meaninafulness.” JP. 1936 
“Concerning the Status of So-called^ Tseudo-objecO Seniences,’* IP, 1940 
“On the Method of Knowledge in Philosophy,” Cai Fubl in Phil., 1940 
“Propositions, Opinions, Sentences and Facts,” JP, 1940 
“Truth, Verifiability and Propositions about the Future ” PS 19^1 
“Moore’s Refutation of Idealism,” in Schiipp. P. A., The Phiiosop>^v or 
G. E. Moore, 1942 

“Propositions, Truth, and the Ultimate Criterion of Truth,” PPR, 1943-44 
“Facts, Truth, and Knowledge,” PPR, 1944.45 
“Reality, Science and Metaphysics,” Synthese, 1950-51 
Dummett, M., “Can an Effect Precede its Cause?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 


A. nn. a. Philos., 


■: 




[405 ] 


^^^^iography of Logical Positivism 

SS'‘n!anmett> M. (continued) 

^j^SSS^r^^^WcBninalism,” PR, 1956 
?'?S^-': ':: .»ConstructionaIism,” PR, 1957 

rmncaii-Joiies, A. E., “Ethical Words and Ethical Facts,” M, 1933 

and Particulars/* ArJSoc., 1933-34 
**De&iitioii of Identity of Structure/’ A, 1934-35 
- “Is Strict Implication the Same as Entailment?/* A, 1934-35 
• “Does Philosophy Analyse Common Sense?/* Ar.Soc.Sup,, 1937 
- “Further Questions about ‘Know’ and Think/” A, 1937-38. Reprinted in 
Macdonald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Lewy’s Remarks on Analysis,” A, 1937-38 
“Freedom: An Illustrative Puzzle,” Ar.Soc., 1938-39 
' “More Notes on Assertion,” A, 1940 

“Critical Notice of Stevenson’s Ethics and Language'' M, 1945 
“Are All Philosophical Questions Questions of Language?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 
1948 

“The Concert Ticket,” in Philosophical Studies — Essays in Memory of 
L. Susan Stebbing, 1948 

“Fugitive Propositions,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., Phi- 
losophy and Analysis 

“Assertions and Commands/’ Ar.Soc., 1951-52 
“Deadlock in Ethics,” Ar.SocSup., 1952 
- Duncker, K., “Behaviorismus und Gestaitpsychologie (Kritische Bemerkungen 
zu Carnaps ‘Psychologic in physikalischer Sprache’),” E, 1932-33 
DiiiT, K., “Die Bedeutung der Negation: Grundziige der empirischen Logik,” 
E, 1935 

“Die Hnheit der Wissenschaften,” E, 1937-38 
Ebersole, F. B., “Verb Tenses as Expressors and Indicators,” A, 1951-52 

“On Certain Confusions in the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction,” IP, 1956 
Edel, A., “Functional Variability of Ethical Rules,” A, 1938-39 

“The Logical Structure of Moore’s Ethical Theory,” in Schiipp, P. A., 
The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1942 
Edwards, P., “Are Percepts in the Brain,” AJ, 1942 

“Bertrand Russell’s Doubts about Induction,” M, 1949. Reprinted in 
Flew, A., Logic and Language (first series), 1951 
“Do Necessary Propositions ‘Mean Nothing’?,” IP, 1949 
“Necessary Propositions and the Future,” IP, 1949 
“Ordinary Language and Absolute Certainty/’ PSt, 1950 
“The Cosmological Argument,” Rationalist Annual, 1959 
Einstein, A., “Physics and Reality,” Journal of the Franklin Institute, 1936 
“Remarks on Bertrand Russell’s Theory of Knowledge/’ in Schiipp, P. A., 
The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, 1944 
Epstein, J., “Professor Ayer on Sense-Data,” IP, 1956 
m.! “Quine’s Gambit Accepted,” IP, 1958 
* Evans, E., “Notes on the Symbolic Process,” M, 1951 

Evans, J. L., “On Meaning and Verification,” M, 1953 
:• /; - - Ewing, A, C., “A Defense of Causality,” Ar.Soc., 1932-33 
Kinds of Analysis,” A, 1934-35 
■ ‘‘Mechanical and Teleological Causation,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1935 
. . /V /-' “Meaninglessness,” M, 1937. Reprinted in Edwards, P. and Pap, A., A 
Modern Introduction to Philosophy 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



I- 







tevi'i 


[406] 

Ewing, A. C- [continued) 

"The Linguistic Theory of A Priori Propositions,” ArSoc., 1939-40 
“Subjectivism and Naturalism in Ethics,” M, 1944. Reprinted in. Sellars, 
W. and Hospers, J., Readings in Ethical Theory 
“The Causal Argument for Physical Objects,” ArSocSup,, 1945 
“Is Metaphysics Impossible?,” A, 1947-48 

“Philosophical Analysis,” in Philosophical Studies — ^Essays in Memory 
of L. Susan Stebbing, 1948 
“Mental Acts,” M, 1948 

“Moral Subjectivism, a Reply to Professor Acton,” A, 1948-49 
“Philosophical Analysis In Ethics,” PSt, 1950 
“Causality and Induction,” PPR, 1951-52 
“Professor Ryle's Attack on Dualism,” Ar.Soc., 1952-53 
“The Relation between Mind and Body as a Problem for the Philosopher,” 
F, 1954 

“The Necessity of Metaphysics,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British 
Philosophy (third series), 1956 
“Pseudo-Solutions,” Ar.Soc„ 1956-57 

“Recent Developments in British Ethical Thought,” in Mace, C. A., 
British Philosophy in the Mid^Century 
Falk, W. D., “Goading and Guiding,” M, 1953 

Farrell, B. A., “An Appraisal of Therapeutic Positivism, I and II,” M, 1946 
“Experience,” M, 1950 

“Intentionality and the Theory of Signs,” PPR, 1954-55 
Feibleman, J. K., “A Reply to Benrand Russell’s Introduction to the Second 
Edition of The Principles of Mathematics/' in Schiipp, P. A., The 
Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, 1944 
“The Metaphysics of Logical Positivism,” RM, 1951-'$2 
Feigl, H-, “Wahrscheiniicfalceit und Erfahning,” E, 1930-31 

“Logical Analysis of the Psychophysical Problem,” PS, 1934 
‘The Logical Character of the Principle of Induction,” PS, 1934. Re- 
printed in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical 
Analysis 

“Sense and Nonsense in Scientinc Realism,” Actes du Congres Intern, de 
Philos. Scientihaue. Paris 1935, 1936 
“Moritz Schlick,” £,‘ 1937-38 

“Logical Empiricism,” in Runes, D. D., Twentieth Century Pkiioscphy, 
1943. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in PhUosophi- 
cal A nalysls 

“Operationism and Scientific Method,” Psyck.Rev., 1945. Reprinted in 
Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“Some Remarks on the Meaning of Scientific Explanation,” PsychRew, 
1948- Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philo- 
sophical Analysis 

“De Principiis Non Disputandum,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 
1950 

“Existential Hypotheses,” PS, 1950 

“Logical Reconstruction, Realism and Pure Semiotic,” PS, 1950 
“The Mind-Body Problem in the Development of Logical Empiricism/’ 
Rev. I nt. Phil., 1950 

“Confirmability and Confirmation,” Rev.lnt.PhiL, 1951 

“Scientific Method without Metaphysical Presuppositions,” PSt, 1954 










ii'BBliogTapky of Logical Positivism 


[ 407 ] 










Fdgl H. (continued) 

*‘0&er Minds and the Egocentric Predicament,” IP, 1958 
-■ ? -- “The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical,’ ” in Feigl, H., Scriven, M. and Maxwell, 
G., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, VoL il, 1958 
H. and Biumberg, A* E., “Logical Positivism, a New Movement in Euro- 
pean Philosophy,” JP, 1931 

Fener, L. S., “Mechanism, Physicalism and the Unity of Science,” PPR, 1948-49 
“The Paradox of Verifiability,” PPR, 1951-52 
... ... “Political Myths and Metaphysics,” PPR, 1955 
Feyerabend, P. K., “Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations/” PR, 1955 
“A Note on the Paradox of Analysis,” PSt, 1956 

“An Attempt at a Realistic Interpretation of Experience,” ArSoc., 1957-58 
Findlay, J. N., “Some Reactions to Recent Cambridge Philosophy I and II,” 
AJ, 1940 and 1941 

“Time: A Treatment of Some Puzzles,” AJ, 1941. Reprinted in Flew, A., 
Logic and iMnguage (first series) 

“Godelian Sentences: A Non-Numerical Approach,” M, 1942 
“Morality by Convention,” M, 1944 

“Can God’s Existence Be Disproved?,” M, 1948. Reprinted in Flew, A. 

and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philosophical Theology 
“Recommendations Regarding the Language of Introspection,” PPR, 
1948-49 

“Is There Knowledge by Acquaintance?,” Ar.Soc.Siip., 1949 
‘Xingnistic Approach to Psycho-Physics,” ArSoc., 1949-50 
“Probability without Nonsense,” PQ, 1952 
“Gn Having in Mind,” P, 1953 

“Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations/” RevJntPhiL, 1953 
“The Justification of Attitudes,” M, 1954 

“An Examination of Tenses,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British 
Philosophy (third series) 

Firth, R., “Sense-data and the Percept Theory, I and II,” M, 1949 and 1950 
“Radical Empiricism and Perceptual Relativity, I and 11,” PR, 1950 
“Phenomenalism,” in Science, Language, and Human Rights. American 
Philosophical Association, Eastern Division, 1952 
Fitch, F, B., “Tne Reality of Propositions,” RM, 1955-56 
Flew, A-, “Can an Effect Precede its Cause?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 

“Divine Omnipotence and Human Freedom,” HJ, 1954-55. Reprinted in 
a lengthened version in Flew’, A. and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in 
Philosophical Theology 

“The Third Maxim,” Rationalist Annual, 1955 

“Philosophy and Language,” PQ, 1955. Reprinted in Essays in Concep- 
tual Analysis 

“Effects before their Causes? Addenda and Corrigenda,” A, 1955-56 
“Can a Man Witness His Own Funeral?,” HJ, 1955-56 
“Determinism and Validity Again,” Rationalist Annual, 1958 
~ Flew, A. and MacKinnon, D. M., “Creation,” Church Quarterly Review, 1955. 

Reprinted in Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philosophic 
I r cal Theology, 1955 

. Foot, P. R., “When Is a Principle a Moral Principle?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 
Foster, M. B., “ ‘We’ in Modern Philosophy,” in Mitchell, B., Faith and Logic, 
1957 



[ 408 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Franl:, P., “Kamalgesetz und Erfaiming,’' Annalen der NaturphfL, 1907. Re- 
printed in Eng. transl. in Modern Science and Its Philosophy 
‘*Die Bedeutung der physikalischen Erkenntnistheorie Ernst Machs fiir 
das Geistesleben der Gegenwart,” Naturwissenschaften, 1917. Re- 
printed in Eng. transl. in Modern Science and Its Philosophy 
“Wissenschaft nnd Theoiogie»” Freier Gedanke, 1920 
“Ober die Anschaulichkeit physikalischer Theorien,” Naturwissenschajten, 

1928 

“Was bedeuten die gegenwartigen physikalischen Theorien fiir die Allge- 
meine Erkenntnislehre?,” Naturwissenschaften, 1929, and E, 1930- 
31. Reprinted in Eng. transl. in Modern Science and Its Philosophy 
“Der Charakter der heutigen physikalischen Theorien,” Scientia, 1931 
“La physique contemporaine manifeste-t-elle une tendence a rintegrer un 
element psychique?,” Revue de Synthese, 1934. Reprinted in Modern 
Science and Its Philosophy 

“Logisierender Empirismus in der Philosophie der U.S.S.R.,” Actes du 
Congres Intern, de Philos. ScientlfiQue, Paris 1935, 1936. Reprinted 
in Modern Science and Its Philosophy 
“Positivistische Oder metaphysische Auffassung der Physik?,” Scientia, 1935 
“The Mechanical versus the Mathematical Conception of Nature,” PS, 

1937. Reprinted in Modern Science and Its Philosophy 
“Philosophische Deutungen und Missdeutungen der Quanientheorie,” E, 
1936-37. Reprinted in Eng. transl. in Modern Science and Its Philos- 
ophy j 

“Was versteht der Physiker unter der ‘Grosse’ eines Kdrpers?,” J, 1937 I 

“Ernst Mach — The Centenary of His Birth,” E, 1937-38. Reprinted in 5 

Modern Science and Its Philosophy j 

“Physik und Logischer Empirismus,” E. 1937-38 ^ 

“The Instimte for the Unity of Science, Its Background and Purpose,” 

Synthese, 1947 ! 

“The Place of Logic and Metaphysics in the Advancement of Modern 

Science,” PS, 1948. Reprinted in Modern Science and Its Philosophy i 

‘The Problem of Physical Reality,” Synthese, 1948-49 j 

“Comments on Realistic versus Phenomenalistic interpretations,” PS, 1950 j 

“introduction to the Philosophy of Physical Science, on the Basis of j 

Logical Empiricism,” Synthese. 1950-51 j 

“Metaphysical Interpretations of Science, I and II,” BJPS, 1950-51 j 

Frankel. A., “Die heutigen Gegensatze in der Grundiegung der Mathematik,” j 

E, 1930-31 ^ 

Frankel, C., “Empiricism and Moral Imperatives,” JP, 1953 5 

Frankena, Wk K., “The Naturalistic Fallacy,” M, 1939. Reprinted in Sellars, i 
W. and Hospers, J., Readings in Ethical Theory 
“Obligation and Value in the Ethics of G. E. Moore,” in Schilpp, P. A., 

The Philosophy of Moore, 1942 

“Ewing's Case against Naturalistic Theories of Value,” PR, 1948 > 

“Arguments for Non-Naturaiism about Intrinsic Value,” PSt, 1950 
“Obligation and Ability,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950 
“Moral Philosophy at Mid-Century,” PR, 1951 
“Natural and Inalienable Rights,” PR, 1955 
Galiie, W. B., “Solipsistic and Social Theories of Meaning,” Ar.Soc., 1937-38 
“An Interpretation of Causal Laws,” M, 1939 


[409] 



^^lography of Logical Positivism [ 409 ] 

W. B. {continued) 

^ *‘]Dr. Ewing on ‘Mental Acts,’ ” M, 1948 

■■ «^e Function of PMlosophicai Aesthetics,” M, 1948. Reprinted in 

, Elton, W., Aesthetics and Language 

[■' "The limitations of Analytical Philosophy,” A, 1948«49 
' "Pleasure,” ArSocSup., 1954 
"Essentially Contested Concepts,” Ar.Soc., 1955-56 
. "Art as an Essentially Contested Concept,” PQ, 1956 
"What Makes a Subject Scientific?,” BJPS, 1957-58 
Gardiner, P. L., “On Assenting ,to a Moral Principle,” ArSoc,, 1954-55 

- "Metaphysics and History,” in Pears, D. F., The Nature of Metaphysics, 
1957 

bamett, A. C., “Must Empiricism Be Materialistic and Behavioristic?,” IP, 
' 1950 

' "Mind as Minding,” M, 1952 

Gasking, D. A- T., “Mr. Williams on the A Priori,” A, 1938-39 

"Mathematics and the World,” AJ, 1940. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic 
and Language (second series) 

"Professor Anderson and the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus/' AJ, 1949 
"The Philosophy of John Wisdom, I and II,” AJ, 1954 
“Causation and Recipes,” M, 1955 
Geach, P. T., “Designation and Truth,” A, 1947-48 

“Necessaiy' Propositions and Entaiiment Statements,” M, 1948 
"If’s and And’s,” A, 194S-49 
"Mr. ni-Named,” A. 1948-49 

"Russell’s Theory of Descriptions,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted in Macdonald, 
M., Philosophy and Analysis 
"Subject and Predicate,” M, 1950 
"On What Tnere Is,” Ar.SocSup., 1951 
“Form and Existence,” ArSoc., 1954-55 
“Entaiiment,” Ar.Soc.SuD., 1958 
"On Frege's Way Out,” M, 1956 
Gellner, E., "Analysis and Ontology,” PQ, 1950-51 
"Knowing How and Validity,” A, 1951-52 

"Contemporaiy Thought and Politics. Review' of Laslett, P., Philosophy, 
Poliiics and Society T P, 1957 
! "Determinism and Validity,” Rationalist Annual, 1957 
George, F. H., “Meaning and Class,” A, 1952-53 

“Epistemology and the Problem of Perception,” M, 1957 
Ginsburg, E. B., “On the Logical Positivism of the Viennese Circle,” JP, 1932 
Godei, K,, "Dber formal unenischeidbare Satze der Principia Mathematica 
und verw'andter Systeme,” Monats.Math.Phys., 1 
"Russell’s Vlathemaiical Logic,” in Schilpp, P. A., 

Bertrand Russell, 1944 
Gomperz, H., "Interpretation,” E, 1937-38 
"The Meanings of ‘Meaning,’ ” PS, 1941 
Gonseth, F., “L’idle de la ioi namrelle,” E, 1936-37 
Goodman, N., "A Query on Confirmation,” JP, 1946 
y "The Problem of Counterfactuai Conditionals,” JP, 

1 - Fact, Fiction and Forecast, and in Linsky, L. 

Philosophy of Language 


1947. Reprinted in 
Semantics and the 




Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 410 ] 

Goodman, N. (continued) 

“Some Reiections on the Theory of Systems,” PPR, 1948-49 
“On likeness of Meaning,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., 
Philosophy and Analysis, and in a revised version in Linsky, L., 
Semantics and the Philosophy of Language 
“Sense and Certainty,” PR, 1952 

“On Some Differences about Meaning,” A, 1952-53. Reprinted in Mac- 
donald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Reply to an Adverse Aliy,” JP, 1957 

Goodman, N. and Quine, W. V., “Steps toward a Constructive Nominalism,” 
JSL, 1947 

Goodstein, R. L., “Mathematical Systems,” M, 1939 

“Wittgenstein’s Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics^' M, 1957 
Grant, C. K., “Polar Concepts and Metaphysical Arguments,” Ar,Soc., 1955-56 
“On Using Language,” PQ, 1956 

“Certainty, Necessity and Aristotle’s Sea Battle,” M, 1957 
Grelling, K., “Philosophy of the Exact Sciences: Its Present Status in Ger- 
many,” Monist, 1928 

“Realism and Logic: An Investigation of RusselFs Metaphysics,” Monist, 
1929 

“Bemerkungen zu Dubislavs ‘Die Deffnition,’” E, 1932-33 
“Identitas Indiscemibiiium,” E, 1937 

Grelling, K. and Opnenbeim, P., “Der Gestaltbegriff in Lichte der neuen 
Logik,” E, 1937-38 

Grice, H. P-, “Personal Identity,” M, 1941 
“Meaning,” PR, 1957 

Grice, H. P., Pears, D. F. and Strawson, P. F., “Metaphysics,” in Pears, D. F., 
The Nature of Metaphysics, 1957 

Grice, K. P. and Strawson, P. F., “In Defense of a Dogma,” PR, 1956 
Griffiths, A. P., “Formulaiing Moral Principles,” M, 1956 
Griinbaum, A., “Causality and the Science of Human Behavior,” American 
Scientist, 1952. Reprinted in Feigi, K. and Brodbeck, M., Readings 
in the Philosophy of Science 
Haas, W., “On Speaking a Language,” ArSoc,, 1950-51 
“Value-Judgments,” M, 1953 
“Defeasibility,” M, 1957 

Haggstrom, W. C., “On Careful Reasoning in Ordinary Language,” A, 1951*52 
Hahn, H., “Die Bedeutung der Wissenschaftlichen Weltauffassung, insbesondere 
fiir Mathematik und Physik,” E, 1930-31 
“Die Krise der Anschauung,” in Krise und Neuaufbau in den Exakten 
Wissenschaften, 1933 

Hall, E- W., “Of What Use Is Metaphysics?,” JP, 1936 

“Metaphysics,” in Runes, D. D., Twentieth Century Philosophy , 1943 

“The Extra-Linguistic Reference of Language, I and 11,” M, 1943 and 1944 

“A Categorical Analysis of Value,” PS, 1947 

“On the Nature of the Predicate ‘Verified,’ ” PS, 1947 

“Stevenson on Disagreement in Attitude,” Ethics, 1947-48 

“The Metaphysics of Logic,” PR, 1949 

“On Describing Describing,” M, 1953 

“Practical Reason(s) and the Deadlock in Ethics,” M, 1955 
“Ghosts and Categorial Mistake-s,” PST, 1956 



[4111 


'gUMography of Logical Positivism 
IML E. W. (continued) 

'^^“Logical Subjects and Physical Objects ” PFR, 1956-57 
SalMen, S., “What Is a Word?/’ T, 1951 
:||g^iyn, D* W., “Behaviour,” ?, 1953 
“A Note on Experience,” A, 1953-54 
*The Stream of Thought,” ArSoc., 1955-56 
“Analytic Tmths,” M, 1956 

fiampshire, S., “Ideas, Propositions and Signs,” ArSoc., 1939-40 
“The Progress of Philosophy,” Polemic^ 1946 
“Logical Form,” ArSoc., 1947-48 
“Are AH Philosophical Questions Questions of Language?,” ArSocSup., 
1948 

“Logical Necessity,” F, 1948 

“Mr. Strawson on Necessaiy- Propositions and Entailment Statements,” 
M, 1948 

“Subjunctive Conditionals,” A, 1948-49. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., 
Philosophy and Analysis 
“Fallacies in Moral Philosophy,” M, 1949 
“Multiple General Sentences,” A, 1949-50 
“Ryle’s The Concept of MindC M, 1950 
“Scepticism and Meaning,” P, 1950 
“Changing Methods in Philosophy” P, 1951 
“The Freedom of the Will,” ArSocSup., 1951 
“The Analogy of Feeling.” Ai, 1952 

“Logic and Appreciation,” World Review, 1952. Reprinted in Elton, W., 
Aesthetics and Language 

“Self-Knowledge and the Win,” RevJntPhil., 1953 
“Dispositions,” A, 1953-54 

“Identincation and Existence,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British 
Philosophy (third series), 1956 
“On Referring and Intending,” PR, 1956 

“The Interpretation of Language: Words and Concepts,” in Mace, C. A., 
British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, 1957 
“Metaphysical Systems,” in Pears, D. F., The Nature of Metaphysics, 1957 
Hanson, N. R., “Mr. Pap on Synonymity,” M, 1951 
“Professor Ryle's ‘Mind,’ ” PQ, 1952 
“A Note on 'Statement of Fact,” .4, 1952-53 
Hardie, C. D., “The Formal Mode of Speech,” A, 1936-37 
“Logical Positivism and Scieniihc Theory,” M, 1938 
“The Necessity of A Priori Propositions,” Ar.Soc., 1938-39 
Hardie, W. F. R., “The Paradox of Phenomenalism,” ArSoc., 1945-46 
“Ordinary Language and Perception,” PQ, 1955 
Hare, R. M., “Imperative Sentences,” M, 1949 
“The Freedom of the Will,” ArSocSup. , 1951 
“Universaiisabiiity,” ArSoc., 1954-55 

“Religion and Morals,” in Mitchell, B-, Faith and Logic, 1957 
“Are Discoveries about the Uses of Words Empirical?,” IP, 1957 
Harre, R., “Dissolving the ‘Problem’ of Induction,” P, 1957 
. . Is True,” AJ, 1957 

Harrison, I., “Can Ethics Do without Propositions?,” M, 1950 
“Empiricism in Ethics,” PQ, 1952 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 412 ] 

Harrison, J. {continued) 

“Mr. Mdcolm on ‘Knowledge and Belief/ ” A, 1952-53 
“When Is a Principle a Moral Principle?/’ Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 
Hart, H. L. A., “The Ascription of Responsibility and Rights,” Ar.Soc., 1948-49 
Reprinted in Flew% A., Logic and Language (&st series) 

“Is piere Knowledge by Acquaintance?/’ Ar.Soc.Sup., 1949 
“Philosophy of Law and Jurisprudence in Britain (1945-52)/’ American 
Journal of Comparative Law, 1953 
“Are There Any Natural Rights?/’ PR, 1955 
“Theor>^ and Definition in Jurisprudence/’ Ar.Soc.Sup., 1955 
Hartmann, M., “Die methodologischen Gnindlagen der Biologic/’ E, 1932-33 
Hartnack, J., “The Alleged Privacy of Experience/’ IP, 1952^ 

“Remarks about Experience,” A, 1952-53 
Hartshome, R., “Metaphysics for Positivists,” PS, 1935 
“Anthropomorphic Tendencies in Positivism,” PS, 1941 
Hay,^ W. H., “C. L. Stevenson and Ethical Analysis,” PR, 1947 
“Bertrand Russell on the Justification of Induction/’ PS, 1950 
‘'Professor Carnap and Probability,” PS, 1952 
“Carnap’s Continuum of Inductive Methods,'' PR, 1953 
Hay, W. H. and Weinberg, J. R., “Concerning Aliegediv Necessarv Non- 
analytic Propositions,” PSt, 1951 

Heath, A. E,, ^“Communication and Verincation,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1934 
Heath, P. L., “The Appeal to Ordinary Language,’’ PQ, 1952 ' 

“Intentions,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1955 

Helmer, O., “Languages with Expressions of Infinite Lensth ” E 1937-38 
Hehner, O. and Oppenheim, P., “A Syntactical Definition of Probabiiitv and 
Degree of Confirmation,” JSL, 1 945 

Hempei, C. G., ‘’On the Logical Positivists’ Theory of Truth,” A, 1934-35 
^^Some Remarks on ‘Facts’ and Propositions,” A, 1934-35 
The Logical Analysis of Psychology,” Revue de Svnihese, 197 5. pa. 

Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophica'rAnah 

^ Dber den Gehalt von Wahrscheinlichkeitsaussagen,” E, 1935-36 
“Some Remarks on Empiricism,” ^,1935-36 

^Eine rein topologische Form nichtaristotelischer Logik ” E 1936-37 
“Le Probleme de la Verite,” T, 1937 
“On the Logical Form of Probability-Statements,” E, 1937-38 
“Vagueness and Logic,” PS, 1939 " * - 

The Function of General Laws in History,” JP, 1942. Reprinted in 
Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Phllosophicai Analysis, and 
in Garamer, P., Theories of History 
A Purely Syntactical Definition of Confirmation,” JSL, 1943 
Geometry and Empirical Science,” American Math. Monthly, 1945. Re- 

prmtea in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Anal- 
ysis 

On toe Nature of Mathematical Truth,” American Math. Monthly, 1945. 

Philosophical 

J ^ ^ Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philos- 

ophy oj Science 

“Studies in toe Logic of Confirmation, I and II/’ M, 1945 
“A Note on Semantic Realism,” PS, 1950 


t^Bihliography of Logical Positivism [ 413 ] 

f "|| 0 apel» C G. (continued) 

-K-:'.;-- ‘Troblems Md Changes in the Empiricist Criterion of Meaning,” Rew 
- 1950. Reprinted in Linsky, L., Semantics and the Philosophy 

of Language, and in the present volume 
- ^General System Theory^ and the Unity of Science,” Human Biology 1951 
-ITie Concept of Cognitive Significance,” Proceedings of American ' Acad- 
emy of Arts and Sciences, 1951 

“Reflections on Nelson Goodman’s The Structure of Appearance ” PR 

1953 i-r , . 

Hnnpel, C. a and Oppenheim, P., “L’imponance logique de la notion de 
type, Actes du Congres Intern^ de Philosophie Scientifiaue, Paris 

1935, 1936 ' " ^ 

“A Definition of ‘Degree of Confiimation,’ ” PS. 1945 
“Studies in the Logic of Explanation,” PS, 1948.' Reprinted as “Tns Lo°ic 
of ^planation” in Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the 
Philosophy of Science, 

Henderson, G. P., “Metaphysical Thinking,” PQ, 1953 
“Causal Implication,” M, 1954 

Discussion: Nelson Goodman’s Fact, Fiction and Forecas*^^ PO IQ 56 
Henie, P., “Method in Ethics.” Ethics, 1943 ‘ 

“On the Certainty of Empirical Statements.” JP, 1947 
“Mysticism and Semantics,” PPR, 1948-49' 

“Tbe Problem of Meaning,” Proceedings and Addresses of the American 
PhiL Assn,, 1956 

“The Nature of Analysis,” JP, 1957 
“Do We Discover Our Uses of Words?.” JP, 1957 
Herbst, P., “The Nature of Facts,” AJ, 1952. Repn7ted in Fjew. A.. Essays in 
Conceptual Analysis 

Hertz, P., ^ Dber den Kausalbegriff im MakroskcDischen besonders in de’' 
Classischen Physik,” £, 1930-31 ^ . 

“Kritische Bemerkungen zu Reichenbachs Behandlunc de^ Humes-h-n 
Problems,” E, 1936-37 

“Regeimassigkeit, Kausalitat und Zeitrichtung,” E 19" 6-3 
“Sprache und Logik,” E, 1937-38 

Heyting, A., “Die intuitionistische Grundiegung der Mathemaiik.” E PS 1-3'’ 

“Mathematische Grundlagenforschung''lnruitionismus-Bewe^iheorie^” *Er- 
gebnisse der Mathemaiik, 1954 " 

Hicks, G. Dawes, “Is There Knowledge by Acquainiaiice?/' Ar.Soc.SuD. 1919 
The Nature of Sensible Appearances.” AtSgc.Suv., 1926 
Hirst; R. J., “Perception, Science, and Common Sense.” M. 1951 
“Mathematics and Truth,” PQ, 1953 
“Sensing and Observing,” A 1954 

Hobart, R. £., “Free Will as Involving Determination and Inconceivable With- 
_ out It,” M, 1936 

Hofstadter, A., “On Semantic Problems,” JP, 1938 
^^Causality and Necessity,” JP, 1949 
“The Causal Universal,” JP, 1949 
: ^Explanation and Necessity,” PPR, 1950-51 
' Ryle’s Category-Mistake,” JP, 1951 

^ Consideration of Quine’s View of Knowl- 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 414 ] 

Hofstadter, A. {continued) 

“Does Intiiitive Knowledge Exist?,” PSt, 1955 
Hofstadter, A. and McKinsey, J. C. C., “On tlie Logic of Imperatives,” PS, 1939 
Hohenemser, K., “Beitrag zn den Gnindlagenprobiemen in der Wahrscbein- 
lichkeitsreciinung,” E, 1931-32 

Holland, R. F., ‘Tlie Empiricist Theory of Memory,” M, 1954 
“Religious Discourse and Theological Discourse,” AJ, 1956 
Holloway, J., “Ethical Qualities,” ArSoc., 1947-4S 

Hoizapfel, W., “Bemerkungen zur Wissenschaftslehre des Wiener Kreises,” E, 
1937-38 

Hosiasson, J., “Definicja rozumowania indukcyjnego” ( A Definition of Induc- 
tive Reasoning), Przeglad Filozoficzny, 1928 
“WTiy Do We Prefer Probabilities Relative to Many Data?,” M, 1931 
“La theorie des probabiiites est-elle une logique generalisee? Analyse 
critique,” Actes du Congres International de Philosophie Scientinque, 
Paris 1935, 1936 

“Induction et Anaiogie,” M, 1941 

Hospers, J., “On Explanation,” JP, 1946. Reprinted as “What Is Explana- 
tion?” in Flew, A., Essays in Conceptual Analysis 
“Meaning and Free Will,” PFR, 1949-50. Reprinted in part in Sellars, W, 
and Hospers, 1., Readings in Ethical Theory: 

“The Concept of Artistic Expression,” Ar.Soc., 1954-55 
Hudson, H., “Achievement Expressions.” A, 1955-56 
Hughes, G. E., “Is There Knowledge by Acquaintance?,” Ar.SocSup., 1949 
Hung, T., “Moritz Schlick and Modern Empiricism,” PPR, 1948-49 
Hutten, E. H., “On Semantics and Physics,” Ar.Soc., 1948-49 
“Induction as a Semantic Problem,” A, 1949-50 
“Probability-Sentences,” M, 1952 
“Natural and Scientific Language,” P, 1954 
Isenberg, A., “Critical Communication,” PR, 1949. Reprinted in Elton, W., 
Aesthetics and Language 
“The Esthetic Function of Language,” JP, 1949 
Jensen, J. C., “Ethical Propositions and Their Foundation,” T, -1941 
Johansen, H-, “Die Russelsche Theorie der definiten Deskriptionen vom 
Standpunkt der Sprachwissenschaft aus betrachtet,” T, 1952 
Jones. J. R., *'Our Knowledge of Other Persons,” P, 1950 
“Simple Particulars,” PSt, 1950 

“Dr. Moore’s Revised Directions for Picking Out Visual Sense Data,” 
PQ. 1950-51 

“What Do We Mean by an ‘Instance’?,” A, 1950-51 
“Sense Data: A Suggested Source of the Fallacy,” M. 1954 
Jorgensen, J., “Ober die Zieie und Probleme der Logistik,” E, 1932-33 

“Die logischen Grundlagen der Wissenschaft,” Actes du Vllle Congres 
Intern, de Philosophie, Prague 1936, 1936 
“Imperatives and Logic,” E, 1937-38 
“Reflexions on Logic and Language,” JUS, 1939-40 
“Remarks concerning the Concept of Mind and the Problem of Other 
People’s Minds,” T, 1949 

von Juhos, B., “Kritische Bemerkungen zur Wissenschaftstheorie des Physi- 
kalismus,” E, 1934 

“Empiricism and Physicalism,” A, 1934-35 


[Bibliography of Logical Positivism [ 415 ] 

- fon Jiihos, B- (continued) 

“Some Modes of Speech of Empirical Science,” A, 1935-36 
“Negationsformen empirischer Satze,” E, 1936 
‘The Tnitii of Empirical Statements,” A, 1936-37 
“Principles of Logical Empiricism,” M, 1937 
“The Empirical and the Grammatical Doubt,” A, 1937-38 
“Empirische Satze und Logische Konstanten,” JUS, 1939-40 
Kaila, E., “Der Satz vom Ausgieich des Zufails und das Kausalprinzip,” An- 
nates Universitatis Fennicoe Aboensis, 1924 
“Die Prinzipien der Wahrscheinlichkeitslogik,” Annales Universitatis 
Fennicae Aboensis, 1926 

“Beitrage zu einer synthetischen Philosophic,” Annales Universitatis Fen- 
nicae Aboensis, 1928 

“Probleme der Deduktion,” Annales Universitatis Fennicae Aboensis, 
1928 

“Rudolf Carnap’s Logische Syntax der Sprache,*’ T, 1936 
“Logistik und Metaphysik,” T, 1942 
“Physikalismus und Phanomenalismus,” T, 1942 

“Logik und Psychophysik. Ein Beiiras zur theoreiischen Psvchologie,” 
T, 1944 

“Wenn . . . so . . . T, 1945 

Kaiish, D., “Meaning and Truth,” Univ. of Calif. Publications in Fkilosouky, 
1950 

“Logical Form,” M, 1952 

Kaminsky, J., “Analytic and Synthetic Moral Judgments,” JP, 1949 
“Metaphysics and the Problem of Synonymity,” PFR, 1953-54 
Kanger, S., “The Morning Star Paradox,” T, 1957 
Kaplan, A., “Are Moral Judgments Assertions?,” PR, 1942 
“Definition and Specification of Meaning.” JF, 1946 
“What Good Is Truth’?”, FPR, 1954-55 
Kaplan, A. and Capilowish, L. M., “Must There Be Propositions?,” M, 1939 
Kaufman, A. S., “The Analytic and the Synthetic,” PR, 1953 
Kaufmann, F., “Bemergungen zum Grundlagenstreit in Lodk und Mathematik,” 
£, 1931-32 

“Verification, Meaning and Truth,” PPR. 1943-i4 
“Scientific Procedure and Probability,” PPR. 1945-46 
“Three Meanings of ‘Truth’,” JP, 1948 
“Rudolf Carnap’s Analysis of ‘Truth,’” PPR, 1948-49 
Kazemier, B. H., “Remarks on Logical Positivism.” Synthese, 1946 
Keene, G. B., “Mathematical Statements — A Repi>- to Mr. Hirst,” PQ, 1955 
“Analytical Statements and Mathematical Truth," A, 1955-56 
-Kemeny, J. G., “Carnap on Probability,” RM, 1951-52 
“A Contribution to Inductive Logic,” PPR, 1952-53 
“The Use of Simplicity in Induction,” PR, 1953 
K^eny, J. G. and Oppenheim, P., “On Reduction,” PSt, 1956 
King, H. R., “Professor Ryle and The Concept of Mind,” JP, 1951 
Kneale, M., “Logical and Metaphysical Necessity,” ArSoc., 1937-38 
“What Is the Mind-Body Problem?,” ArSoc,, 1949-50 
Kne^e, W, C., “The Objects of Acquaintance,” Ar.Soc., 1933-34 

Ts Existence a Predicate?”, Ar,Soc.Sup,, 1936. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and 
Seilers, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 416 ] 

Kneale, W. C. (continued) 

^Verifiability,” ArSocSup,, 1945 
“Tmtiis of Logic,” ArSoc.y 1945-46 
“Are Necessary Truths True by Convention?,” ArSoc.Supp.y 1947 
“What Can Logic Do for Philosophy?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1948 
“Experience and Introspection,” ArSoc., 1949-50 

“Natural Laws and Contrary to Fact Conditionals,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted 
in Macdonald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Objectivity in Morals,” P, 1950. Reprinted in Sellars, W. and Hospers, J., 
Readings in Ethical Theory 
“Sensation and the Physical World,” PQ, 1950-51 

“Gottlob Frege and Mathematical Logic,” in Ayer, A. J. et a/.. The 
Revolution in Philosophy ^ 1956 

“The Province of Logic,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British Philos- 
ophy (third series), 1956 

Knight, H., “The Use of ‘Good’ in Aesthetic Judgments,” Ar.Soc., 1935-36. 

Reprinted in Elton, W., Aesthetics and Language 
Kokoszynska, M., “Ober den Absoluten Wahrheitsbegrifi und einige andere 
semantische Begrifie,” E, 1936-37 
“Bemerkungen liber die Einheitswdssenschaft,” E, 1937-38 
Komer, S., “Are All Philosophical Questions, Questions of Language?”, Ar.Soc. 
Sup.y 1948 

“Entailment and the Meaning of Words,” A, 1949-50 

“On Theoretical and Practical Appropriateness,” Ar.Soc., 1951-52 

“On Laws of Nature,” M, 1953 

‘Truth as a Predicate,” A, 1954-55 

“Some Remarks on Philosophical Analysis,” JP, 1957 

“Reference, Vagueness and Necessity,” PR, 1957 

“Some Types of Philosophical Thinking,” in Mace, C. A., British Philos- 
ophy in the Mid-Century' 

Kotarbinski, T., “O istocie doswiadczenia wewnetrznego” (On the Essence of 
Introspective Experience), Przeglad Filosoficzny , 1922 
“Le reaiisme radical,” Proceedings of the 7th Intern. Cong, of Philosophy, 
Oxford, 1930, 1931 • 

“Gnindlinien und Tendenzen der Philosophie in Poien,” Shvische Rund- 
schau, 1933 

“The Fundamental Ideas of Pansomatism,” M, 1955 
Kraft, J., “Das Problem der Geisteswissenschaft,” £, 1936-37 
Kraft, V., “Grundformen der wdssenschaftiichen Methoden,” S-B d. Wiener 
Akad. der V/issenschaften, 1925 

“Die Grosse eines Korpers gemass der Relativitatstheorie,” T, 1940 
“Ober Moralbegriindung,” T, 1940 

“Die Grosse eines Korpers gemass der Relativitatstheorie-Diskussion,” T, 
1941 

“Logik und Erfahrung,” T, 1946 

Ladd, J., “Value Judgments, Emotive Meaning, and Attitudes,” JP, 1949 
“Ethics and Explanation,” JP, 1952 
Laird, J., “Positivism, Empiricism and Metaphysics,” Ar.Soc., 1938-39 
Lake, B., “Necessary and Contingent Statements,” A, 1951-52 

“A Study of the Irrefutability of Two Aesthetic Theories,” in Elton, W., 
Aesthetics and Language, 1954 





f 


I 

I 

3 


I' 


I 

I- 


I- 

I 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism [ 417 ] 

Rambert K. J-, “On Naming and Claiming,” PSi, 1956 

~ l^gford, C. H., “Moore’s Notion of Analysis,” in Scbiipp, P. A., The Philos- 
ophy of G. E, Moore j 1942 

“A Proof that Synthetic A Priori Propositions Exist,” JP, 1949 
“The Institutional Use of The,’ ” PPR, 1949-50 
Langford, C. H. and Langford, M., “Logic, I and n,” PPR, 1951-52 and 
1952-53 

“Introduction to Logic,” PPR, 1953-54 
“Strict, Causal and Material Propositions,” IP, 1954 
Lazerowitz, M., “The Principle of Verifiability,” M, 1937 
“Tautologies and the Matrix Method,” M, 1937 
“Meaninglessness and Conventional Use,” A, 1937-38 
“The Null Class of Premises,” M, 1938 

“Strong and Weak Verification I,” M, 1939. Reprinted in The Structure 
of Metaphysics 

“Self-Contradictory Propositions,” PS, 1940 

“Moore’s Paradox,” in Schilpp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 
1942. Reprinted in The Structure of Metaphysics 
“The Existence of Universals,” M, 1946. Reprinted in The Structure of 
Metaphysics 

“The Positivistic Use of ‘Nonsense,’ ” M, 1946. Reprinted in The Structure 
of Metaphysics 

“Are Self-Contradicton- Expressions Meaningless?”, PR, 1949. Reprinted 
in The Structure of Metaphysics 

“Strong and Weak Verification II,” M, 1950. Reprinted in The Structure 
of Metaphysics 

“Substratum,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950. Reprinted in 
The Structure of Metaphysics 

“Negative Terms,” A, 1951-52. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., Philosophy 
and Analysis and in The Structure of Metaphysics 
“The Paradox of Motion,” ArSoc., 1951-52. Reprinted in The Structure 
of Metaphysics 

“Logical Necessity,” in The Structure of Metaphysics, 1955 
“The Nature of Metaphysics,” in The Structure of Metaphysics, 1955 
Lejewski, C., “Logic and Existence,” BJPS, 1954-55 
“Proper Names,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1957 

Lenz, J. W., “Carnap on Defining ‘Degree of Confirmation,’” PS, 1956 
Lenzen, V. F., “Physical Causality,’' Univ. of Calif. Fubl. in Philosophy, 1932 
“A Positivistic Theory of Possibility,” Univ. of Calif. Publ. in Philosophy, 
1934 


“The Interaction between Subject and Object in Observation,” E, 1936-37 
“Experience and Convention in Physical Theory,” E, 1937-38 
“The Concept of Reality in Physical Theory,” PR, 1945 
Leonard, H. S., “Ethical Predicates,” JP, 1949 
“The Logic of Existence,” PSi, 1956 

Lewis, C. L, “A Pragmatic Conception of the A Priori,” JP, 1923. Reprinted 







[418 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Lewis, C. I. (continued} 

“Some Logical Considerations concerning the Mental,” IP, 1941. Reprinted 
in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“The Modes of Meaning,” PPR, 1943-44. Reprinted in Linsky, L., Seman- 
tics and the Philosophy of Language 
“Professor Chisholm and Empiricism,” /P, 1948 
“The Given Element in Empirical Knowledge,” PR, 1952 
“Realism or Phenomenalism?”, PR, 1955 

“Some Suggestions Concerning Metaphysics of Logic,” in Hook, S., 
American Philosophers at Work 
Lew>% C., “A Note on Empirical Propositions,” A, 1937-38 
“Some Remarks on Analysis,” A, 1937-38 
“On the ‘Justification’ of Induction,” A, 1938-39 

“Some Notes on Assertion,” A, 1939-40. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., 
Philosophy and Analysis 

“Is the Notion of Disembodied Existence Self-Contradictory?,” Ar.Soc,, 
1942-43 

“On the Relation of Some Empirical Propositions to Their Evidence,” M, 
1944 

“Entailment and Empirical Propositions,” M, 1946 

“Equivalence and Identity,” M, 1946 

“The Terminology of Sense-Data,” M, 1946 

“Why Are the Calculuses of Logic and Arithmetic Applicable to Reality?,” 
Ar.Soc.Sup,, 1946 

“Truth and Significance,” A, 1947-48. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., 
Philosophy and Analysis 
“Carnap’s Meaning and Necessity,"* M, 1949 

“Entailment and Necessary Propositions,” in Black, M., Philosophical 
Analysis, 1950 

“Entailment,” ArSocSup., 1958 
Lieb, 1. C., “Wittgenstein’s Investigations,"’ RM, 1954-55 
Lindenbaum-Hosiasson, J., “Bemerkungen fiber die Zurfickffihrung der phy- 
sischen auf psychische Begriffe,” E, 1937-38 
Linsky, L., “Some Notes on Carnap’s Concept of Intensional Isomorphism and 
the Paradox of Analysis,” PS, 1949 
“A Note on Carnap’s ‘Truth and Confirmation,’ ” PSt, 1950 
“On Using Inverted Commas,” Method os, 1950 
“On Understanding Philosophical Writings,” PPR, 1954-55 
“Wittgenstein on Language and Some Problems of Philosophy, JP, 1957 
Lloyd, A. C., “Empiricism, Sense Data and Scientific Languages,” M, 1950 
“Thinking and Language,” ArSocSup. , 1951 
Long, P., “Natural Laws and So-called Accidental General Statements,” A, 
1952-53 

Lucas, J. R., “The Soul,” in Mitchell, B., Faith and Logic, 1957 
Lukasiewicz, J., “O logice trojwartosciowej” (On Three-valued Logic), Ri/ch 
Filozoficzny, 1920 

“Philosophische Bemerkungen zu mehrwertigen Systemen des Aussagen- 
kalkfils,” Comptes rendus des seances de la Societe des Sciences et 
des Lettres de Varsovie, 1930 
“Zur Geschichte der Aussagenlogik,” E, 1935 

“Bedeutung der logischen Analyse ffir die Erkenntnis,” Actes du Vllle 
Congres Intern, de Philosophie, Prague 1936, 1936 


' Bihliography of Logical Positivism [ ] 

l^zsimicz, J. {continued) 

‘‘Die Logik und das Gmndlagenproblem,” Les entretiens de Zurich sur 
les fondements et la methode des sciences mathematiques, 1938 
‘Tbe Principle of Individuation/’ ArSocSup,, 1953 
. I^nkasiewicz, J. and Tarski, A., “Untersuchungen xzber den Anssagenkalkiil/’ 
Comptes rendus des seances de la Societe des Sciences et des Lettres 
de Varsovie, 1930. Eng. transl. in Tarski, A., Logic, Semantics, 
Metamaihematics 

Tnndberg, G. A., ‘The Concept of Law in the Social Sciences,” PS, 1938 
“Contemporary Positivism in Sociology,” Amer. SocioL Rev., 1939 
“Operational Definitions in the Social Sciences,” Amer. Journal of SocioL, 
1941-42 

Mabbott, J. D., “Negation,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1929 
“True and False in Morals,” Ar.Soc., 1948-49 
“The Specious Present,” M, 1955 

Macdonald, M., “Verification and Understanding,” Ar.Soc., 1933-34 
“Language and Reference,” A, 1936-37 
“Induction and Hypothesis,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1937 

“The Philosopher’s Use of Analogy,” ArSoc., 1937-38. Reprinted in Flew, 
A., Logic and Language (first series) 

‘Things and Processes,” A, 1938-39. Reprinted in Philosophy and Analysis 
“Necessary^ Propositions,” A, 1940 

“The Language of Political Theory,” Ar.Soc., 1940-41. Reprinted in Flew, 
A., Logic and Language (first series) 

“Natural Rights/’ Ar.Soc., 1946-47. Reprinted in Lasiett, P., Philosophy, 
Politics and Society 

“Some Distinctive Features of Arguments Used in Criticism of the Arts,” 
Ar.Soc.Sup., 1949. Reprinted in Elton, W., Aesthetics and Language 
“Ethics and the Ceremonial Use of Language,” in Black, M., Philosophical 
Analysis, 1950 

“Professor Ryle on the Concept of Mind,” PR, 1951 
“Art and Imagination,” Ar.Soc., 1952-53 
“Linguistic Philosophy and Perception/’ P, 1953 
“Sleeping and Waking,” M, 1953 
“Language in Fiction,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 
Mace, C. A., “Representation and E.xpression,” A, 1933-34. Reprinted in Mac- 
donald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Metaphysics and Emotive Language,” A, 1934-35 

“Mechanical and Teleological Causation,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 2935. Reprinted 
in Feigl, FI. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical A^nalysis 
“Physicalism,” Ar.Soc., 1936-37 
“Self Identity,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1939 

“On How We Know that Material Things Exist/’ in Schilpp, P. A., The 
Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1942 

“The Logic of Elucidation,” in Philosophical Studies — Essays in Memory 
of L. Susan St ebbing, 1948 

“Some Implications of Analytical Behaviorism,” Ar.Soc., 194S-49 
“Introspection and Analysis,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950 
“Some Trends in the Philosophy of Mind,” in British Philosophy in the 
Mid‘Century, 1957 

MacIntyre, A., “A Note on Immortality,” M, 1955 


[ 419 

trick sur I 





Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


[ 420 ] 

MacIntyre, A. (continued) 

“Visions,” in Flew. A., and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philosophical 
Theology, 1955 

“Hie Logical Status of Religioiis Belief,” in Toulmin, ei a!,, MetanhyNimi 
Beliefs, 1957 

Maciver, A. M., “Demonstratives and Proper Names,” A, 1935-36, Reprinted 
in Macdonald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Token, Type and Meaning,” A, 1936-37 

“Some Questions about ‘Know’ and ‘Tnink,’” A, 1937-38. Reprinted in 
Macdonald, M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“More about Some Old Logical Puzzles,” A, 1938-39 
“Metaphor,” A, 1940 

Mackie, J., “A Refutation of Morals,” AJ, 1946 
“The Nature of Facts,” AJ, 1952 
“Responsibility and Language,” AJ, 1955 
MacKnnon, D. M., “Are There A Priori Concepts?,” ArSoc.Sup,, 1939 
“What Is a Metaphysical Statement?,” Ar.Soc., 1940-41 
“Verifiabiliiy%” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1945 

MacKinnon, D. M. and Flew, A., “Creation,” Church Quarterly Review, 1955 . 

Reprinted in Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philosophi- 
cal T heology 

Macnabb, D. G. C., “Phenomenaiism,” Ar.Soc., 1940-41 

“The Causal Argument for Physical Objects,” ArSoc.Sup., 1945 
Malcolm, N., “Are Necessary Propositions Really Verbal?,” 1940 
“The Nature of Entaiiment,” M, 1940 
“Certainty and Empirical Statements,” M, 1942 

“Moore and Ordinary' Language,” in Schiipp, p. A., The Philosophv of 
G. E. Moore, 1942 

“Defending Common Sense,” PR, 1949 
“Russell's Human Knowledge^ PR, 1950 
■^5.^ "^'orincation Argument, in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950 
“Philosophy for Philosophers,” PR, 1951 
“Knowledge and Belief,” M. 1952 
“Direct Perception,” PC- 1^53 
“Moore’s Use of ‘Know,’ ” M, 1953 
“On Knowledge and Belief,” A, 1953-54 
“Wittgenstein’s Phiiosopkical Investigations^ PR, 1954 
“Dreaming and Skepticism.” PR, 1956 
“Knowledge of Other Minds,” JP, 1958 

Mamtano, G„ “L'unite de I'experience scieniifique seion la positivite veritable 
ccnventioneliement dehnee,” £, 1937-38 
Mannoury, G., “Signifische Analyse der V/illensprache als Grundlage einer 
physikaiistischen Sprachsynthese,” E, 1937-3S 
Marc-Wogau. K., “Bemerkungen zum BegriS ‘Sinnesdatum’ in der Diskussion 
der letzten Jahre,” T, 1950 

“Der Zweifei Descartes und das Cogito ergo sum/' T, 1956 
Margenau, H., “Metaphysical Elements in Physics,” Rev. of Modern Physics, 
1941 

“On the Frequency Theory' of Probability,” PPR, 1945-46 
Marhenke, P., “Moore’s Analysis of Sense-Perception,” in Schiipp, P. A. The 
Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1942 ' ’ 


^ MbMography of Logical Positivism 


1^21] 

‘^‘Xfas Criterion of Significance,” Proceedings and Addresses of the Amer. 
Phil, Assn,, 1950. Reprinted in Linsky, L., Semantics and the Philos- 
ophy of Language 

^ - '“Plienoinenalism/’ in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950 

‘‘Propositions and Sentences,” Univ. of Calif. Publ. in Philosophy, 1950 
Martin, C. B., “Mr. Geach on Mention and Use,” M, 1949 
“Mr. Hanson on Statements of Fact,” A, 1952-53 

“A Religions Way of Knowing,” M, 1952. Reprinted in Flew, A. and Mac- 
Intyre, A., New Essays in Philosophical Theology 
Martin, R. M., “Some Comments on Truth and Designation,” A, 1949-50 
“On Inscriptions,” PPR, 1950-51 

“On Tarski’s ‘Semantic Conception of Truth,’ ” PPR, 1950-51 
“On ‘Analytic,’ ” PSt, 1952 

“On the Berkeley-Russell Theory of Proper Names.” PPR, 1952-53 
“On Woodgers Analysis of Biological Language,” RM, 1954-55** 

Masierman, M., “Words,” ArSoc., 1953-54 

“Metaphysical and Ideographic Language,” in Mace, C. A., British Philos- 
ophy in the Mid-Century, 1957 

Mates, B., “Synonymity,” Unix, of Calif. Publ. in Philosophy. 1950. Reprinted 
in Linsk}', L., Semantics and the Philosophy of Laiipitatte 
“xA.nalytic Sentences,” PR, 1951 * " 

Mayo, B., “Events and Language,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted in Macdonald, M 
Philosophy and Analysis ' 

“Is There a Case for the General Will?,” P, 1950. Reprinted in Laslett P 
Philosophy, Politics and Society' ’ ' 

“Facts, Feelings and Attitudes,” Ar.Soc., 1950-51 
“The Logical Status of Supposition,” Ar.SocSup., 1951 
“ ‘Rules’ of Language,” PSt, 1951 
“Ethics and Moral Controversy,” PQ, 1954 
“Rule-Making and Rule-Breaking,” A, 1954-55 
“Commitments and Reasons,” M, 1955 
“Conditional Statements,” PR, 1957 
McEunney, J. P., “The Status of Theoretical Entities,” A.J, 1956 
^“Philosophical Implications of Logical Analysis,” HI, 195? 

Hofstadter, A., “On the Logic of imperanves.” PS 1939 

McPherson, T., “Ramsey on Rules,” A, 1951-52 

“Positivism and Religion,” PPR, 1953-54. Reprinted as “Religion as the 
Inexpressible,” in Flev/, A. and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philo- 
sophical Theology, 1955 

MecUer, L., “The Value-Theory of C. 1. Lewis,” JP, 1950 
“Normative and Descriptive Expressions,” JP, 1953 
^^On Goodman’s Refutation of Synonymy,” A, 1953-54 
^Are Indubitable’ Statements Necessarv'?,” M, 1955 
M -Analysis of Belief-Sentences,” PPR, 1955-56 

^leiiiberg, H., “Essais sur la theorie causale du temps, I and II,” Studia Philo- 
1935 and 1937 

“Bositivisme et Science, I,” Studia Philosophica, 1939-40 
. JtteKien, A. L, “On the Method of Ethics,” JP, 1948 

- ^Action,” PR, 1956 
“On Promising,” M, 1956 










Hi ‘-.i'v 




[ 422 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Melior, W. W., “Believing the Meaningless;’ A, 1954-55 
“Tiiree Problems about Other Minds,” M, 1956 
Menger, K., “Intuitionismus;’ Zeitschrift j. deutsche Philosophie, 1930 

“Die neue Logik;’ in Krise und Neuaufbau in den exakten Wissenschaften 
1933 

“The New Logic,” PS, 1937 
Miller, D. L., ‘Two Kinds of Certainty;’ PS, 1940 

Miller, D. S., “ ‘Descartes’ Myth’ and Professor Ryle’s Faliacy,” JP, 1951 
von Mises, R., “Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung,” Naiurwissenschaften, 1919 
“trber die Wahrscheinlichkeit seltener Ereignisse,” Zeitschrift fur Ange- 
wandte Mathematik und Meckanlk, 1921 
“Ober das Gesetz der grossen Zahlen und die Haungkeitstheorie der Wahr- 
scheinlichkeit,” Naiurwissenschaften, 1927 
“trber kausale und statistische Gesetzmassigkeit in der Physik,” E, 1930-31 
von Mises, R. and Pollaczek-Geiringer, H., “Probabiiirv%” EncycL of Social 
Sciences, 1932 

Moore, A., “Verifiability and Phenomenalism;’ JP, 1950 

“The Emotive Theorv and Rational Methods in Moral Controversy,” Af 
1951 

“The Principles of Induction,” JP, 1952 
Moore, G. E., “The Nature of Judgment,” M, 1899 

“The Refutation of Idealism,” M, 1903. Reprinted in Philosophical Studies 
and in Ewing, A. C. (ed.), The Idealist Tradition 
“The Nature and Reality of Objects of Perception,” ArSoc,, 1905-6. Re- 
printed in Philosophical Studies 

“Professor James’s ‘Pragmatism,’ ” A^rSoc,, 1907-8. Reprinted in Philo- 
sophical Studies 

“Hume’s Philosophy,” The New Quarterly. 1909. Preprinted in Philosophi- 
cal Studies, and in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W.. Readings in Philosophical 
Analysis 

“The Status of Sense-Data,” ArSoc., 1913-14. Reprinted in Philosophical 
Studies 

“Are the Materials of Sense Affections of the Mind?,” ArSoc., 1916-17 
“The Conception of Reality,” ArSoc., 1917-18. Reprinted in Philosophical 
Studies 

“Some Judgments of Perception,” Ar.Soc., 1918-19. Reprinted in Philo- 
sophical Studies 

“Is There Knowledge by Acquaintance?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1919 
“External and Internal Relations,” A.r.Soc., 1919-20. Reprinted in Philo- 
sophical Studies 

“The Character of Cognitive Acts,” ArSoc., 1920-21 
“Are the Characteristics of Particular Things Universal or Particular?,” 
Ar.Soc.Sup., 1923 

“A Defence of Common Sense,” in Muirhead, J. H., Contemporary Brit- 
ish Philosophy (second series), 1925 
“The Nature of Sensible Appearances,” ArSoc. Sup., 1926 
“Facts and Propositions,” ArSoc.Sup., 1927 
“Indirect Knowledge,” Ar.SocSup., 1929 
“Is Goodness a Quality?,” Ar.SocSup., 1932 
“Imaginary Objects,” ArSoc.Sup., 1933 

Ts Existence a Predicate?,” ArSocSup., 1936. Reprinted in Flew, A., 
Logic and Language (second series) 



f/sii^!iography of Logical Positivism [ 423 ] 

• Moore, G. E. {continued) 

----- • **A Reply to My Critics,” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. E, 
Moore, 1942 

"EnsselFs ‘Theory of Descriptions,*” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy of 
- - Bertrand Russell, 1944 

• - ^Addendum to My ‘Reply,’ ” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. E. 
Moore (second edition), 1952 

^^Wittgenstein’s Lectures in 1930-1933, I-HI,” M, 1954 and 1955 
“Visual Sense-Data,” in British Philosophy in Mid-Century, 1957 
Morgenbesser, S., “On the Justification of Beliefs and Attitudes,” IP, 1954 
Morris, C. W., “Truth, Action and Verification,” Monist, 1932 
“Philosophy of Science and Science of Philosophy,” PS, 1935 
“The Relation of the Formal and Empirical Sciences within Scientific Em- 
piricism,” E, 1935 

“Some Aspects of Recent American Scientific Philosophy,” B, 1935 
“The Concept of Meaning in Pragmatism and Logical Positivism,” Pro- 
ceedings of the 8th Intern. Congress of Philosophy, 1934 (Prague, 
1936) 

“Science and Discourse,” Synthese, 1946 
Mothersiil, M., “The Use of Normative Language,” JP, 1955 
Mundie, C. W, K., “How Specious Is the Specious Present?,” M, 1954 
Murdoch, L, “Thinking and Language,” Ar.SocSup., 1951 

“Metaphysics and Ethics,” in Pears, D. F., The Nature of Metaphysics, 
1957 

Murphy, A. E., “Two Versions of Critical Philosophy,” Ar.Soc., 1937-38 

“Moore’s ‘Defense of Common Sense,’ ” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy 
of G. E. Moore, 1942 

Myhiil, J., “Two Ways of Ontology in Modern Logic,” RM, 1951-52 

“Some Philosophical Implications of Mathematical Logic. Three Classes of 
Ideas,” RM, 1952-53 

Naess, A., “Common-Sense and Truth,” T, 1938 

‘“Ober die Funktion der Verallgemeinerung,” E, 1937-38 
“Toward a Theory of Interpretation and Preciseness,” T, 1949. Reprinted 
in Linsky, L., Semantics and the Philosophy of Language 
“Synonymity as Revealed by Intuition,” PR, 1957 
Nagel, E., “Intuition, Consistency, and the Excluded Middle,” JP, 1929 
“Nature and Convention,” JP, 1929 

“Review of A. S. Eddington’s The Nature of the Physical WorldJ* The 
Symposium, 1930. Reprinted as Part I of “Eddington’s Philosophy of 
Physical Science” in Sovereign Reason 
“Measurement,” £, 1931-32 
“A Frequency Theory of Probability,” JP, 1933 

“Verifiability, Truth and Verification,” JP, 1934. Reprinted in Logic with- 
out Metaphysics 

“Carnap’s Logische Syntax der SpracheJ' JP, 1935 
“The Logic of Reduction in the Sciences,” E, 1935 

“Impressions and Appraisals of Anal 5 dic Philosophy in Europe, I and II,” 

' ' JP, 1936. Reprinted in Logic without Metaphysics 

> “The Meaning of Probability,” Journal of Amer. Statistical Assn., 1936 
“v “Reichenbach’s WahrscheinlichkeitslehreJ* M, 1936 
“Some Theses in the Philosophy of Logic,” PS, 1938 
“Probability and the Theory of Knowledge,” PS, 1939. Reprinted in Sov- 
ereign Reason 


Bibliography of Logical Fosltivism 


[ 424 ] 

Nagel, E. {continued) 

“Charles S. Peirce, Pioneer of Modem Empiricism,” FS, 1940. Reprinted 
in Sovereign Reason 

“Mr. Russell on Meaning and Truth,” /F, 1941. Reprinted in Sovereign 
Reason 

“Recent Philosophies of Science,” Kenyon Review, 1941. Reprinted in Sov- 
ereign Reason 

“Operational Analysis as an Instrument for the Critique of Linguistic 
Si^s,” /F, 1942 

“Malicious Philosophies of Science,” Partisan Review, 1943. Reprinted in 
Sovereign Reason 

“Logic without Ontolog>%” in Krikorian, Y,, Naturalism and the Human 
Spirit, 1944. Reprinted in Feigl, H., and Sellars, W., Readings in 
Philosophical Analysis and in Logic without Metaphysics 
“Russell’s Philosophy of Science,” in Schilpp. P. A., The Philosophy of 
Bertrand Russell, 1944. Reprinted in Sovereign Reason 
“Critical Notice of Schiipp’s The Philosophy of G. E. Moore!' M, 1944 
“Truth and Knowledge of the Truth,” FPR, 1944-45. Reprinted in Logic 
without Metaphysics 

“Probability and Non-demonstrative Inference." PPR. 

“Some Reflections on the Use of Lannuace in the Natural Sciences.” JP, 
1945 

“Sovereign Reason,” in Kook, S. and Konvitz, M. R.. Freedom and Expe- 
rience, 1947. Reprinted in Sovereign Reason and in Ewing, A. C,. The 
Idealist Tradition 

“William’s The Ground of induction^ JF. 1947 
“Carnap’s Meaning and Necessity F IF, 1948 

“The Basis of Human Knowledge,” The Nation, 1949. ■Reprinted in Sov- 
ereign Reason 

“In Defense of Logic without Metaphysics." FF, 1949. Reprinted in Logic 
without Metaphysics 

“The Meaning of Reduction in the Natural Sciences,” in Siaufer, Pv. C., 
Science and Civilization, 1949 

“Einstein’s Philosophy of Science,” Kenyon Review, 1950. Reprinted in 
Logic without Metaphysics 
“Reicnenbach’s The Theory, cf Probability !' JF, 1950 
“Science and Semantic Realism,” F5. 1950 

“Mechanistic Explanation and Organismi: Biology." FFF. 1950-51. Re- 
printed in Hook, S., American Philosophers a: Tl’ork 
“The Logic of Historical Analysis,” Scientific Monthly. 1952. Reprinted in 
Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philosophy of Science 
and in Gardiner, P., Theories of History 
“Wholes, Sums and Organic Unities,” FSi, 1952 

“On the Method of ‘Verstehen’ as the Sole Method of Philosophy’,” JF 
1953 

“A Budget of Problems in the Philosophy of Science,’* x®F, 195"^ 
Nakhnikian, G. and Salmon, W. C., “ ‘Exists’ as a Predicate.” FF, 1957 
Nelson, E. J., “Deductive Systems and the Absoluteness of Logic, M, 1933 
“Professor Reichenbach on Induction,” JF. 1935 
“Contradiction and the Presupposition of Existence,” M, 1946 
“The Relation of Logic to Metaphysics,” PPR, 1948-49, and FF. 1949 
“The Verification Theory of Meaning,” PR, 1954 





h:': Bibliography of Logical Positivism [ 425 ] 

, - O., “Eindeotigkeit und Kommutativitat des logiscfaen Produktes ‘ab/ ” 


' Arch. f. Syst. PhiL, 1910 
Philos. Ges. a.d. Univ. 


Jahrb. d. Philos. 


1931 


Encv- 


Arch. f. 


Arch. f. syst. PhiL, 1909 

“De&idoBSgieichheit und symboiische Gleicbheit. 

Problem des Lustmaximums,” Jahrb. d. 

Wien, 1912 

‘TOe Verinten des Cartesius und das Auxiliarmotiv, 

Ges. a.d. Univ. Wien, 1913 

"Wege der Wissenschaftlicben Weltauffassung,” E, 1930-31 
“Physicalism: The Philosophy of the Viennese Circle,” Monist, 
‘Thysikalismus,” Scientia, 1931 

“Soziologie im Physikalismus,” E, 1931-32. Reprinted in Engl. transL in 
the present volume 

“Protokollsatze,” E, 1932-33. Reprinted in Engl, transl. in the present 
volume 

“Radikaier Physikalismus und ‘Wirkliche Welt,’” E, 1934 
“Einheit der Wissenschaft als Aufgabe,” E, 1935 
“Pseudorationalismus der Falsinkation,” E, 1935 
“Den Logiska empirismen och Wienerkretsen,” T, 1936 
“Soziologische Prognosen,” E, 1937 
“Unified Science and its Encyclopedia,” PS, 1937 
“The Departmentalization of Unified Science,” E, 1937-38 
“Unified Science as Encyclopedic Integration,” in Neurath e( aL 
clopedia and Unified Science, 1938 
“Universal Jargon and. Terminology,” Ar.Soc., 1940-41 
Neurath, O. and Hahn-Neurath, O., “Zum Dualismus in der Logik, 
syst. Phil., 1909 

Nielsen, K., “The Functions of Moral Discourse,” PQ, 1957 
Northrop, F. S. C., “The Significance of Epistemic Correlations in Scientific 
Method,” JUS, 1939 

“The Importance of Deductively Formulated Theory in Ethics and So- 
cial and Legal Science,” in Henle, P., Kallen, H. M. and Langer, S. 
K-, Structure, Method and Meaning, 1951 
Noweli-Smith, P. H., “Subjectivism and the Empiricists,” A, 1938-39 
“Philosophical Theories,” Ar.Soc., 1947-48 

“Freewill and Moral Responsibility,” M, 1948. Reprinted in Munitz, 
M. K., A Modern Introduction to Ethics 
“Science and Politics,” Ar.Soc.Siip., 1949 

“Fugitive Propositions,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., PhL 
losophy and Analysis 

“Miracles,” HI, 1949-50. Reprinted in Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A., New 
Essays in Philosophical Theology 
“Determinists and Libertarians,” M, 1954 

“Psycho-analysis and Moral Language,” Rationalist Annual, 1954 
“Are Historical Events Unique?,” ArEoc., 1956-57 
O’Connor, D. I., “Pragmatic Paradoxes,” M, 1948 

“Is There a Problem about Free-Will?,” Ar.Soc., 1948-49 

“Some Consequences of Professor A. J. Ayer’s Verification Principle,” 

• ; A, 1949-50 

‘The Analysis of Conditional Sentences,” M, 1951 
“Philosophy and Ordinary Language,” JP, 1951 
“Names and Universais,” Ar.Soc., 1952-53 
“The Identity of Indiscernibies,” A, 1953-54 




Bibliography of Logical Fositivism 



[ 426 ] 

O’Connor, B. J. {continued) 

“Incompatibie Properties,” A, 1954-35 
“Awareness and Cominniiicatioii,” /P, 1955 
“Causal Statements,” PQ, 1956 
“Validity and Standards,” ArSoc,, 1956-57 
“Detemiimsm and Predictability,” BJPS, 1956-57 
O’Connor, D. J. and Basson, A. H., “Language and Pbilosophy,” F, 1947 
Olds, M. E., “Synonymity: Extensionai Isomorphism,” M, 1956 
Oliver, D., “Logic and Necessity,’ JP, 1950 

“A Reexamination of the Problem of Induction,” JP, 1952 
Oppenheim, F. E., “Outline of a Logical Analysis of Law,” PS, 1944 
Oppenbeim, P. and Greiling, K., “Der Gestaitbegriff im Lichte der neuen 
Logik,” £, 1937-38 

Oppenheim, P. and Helmer, O., “A S\Titactical Definition of Probability and 
Degree of Confirmation,” JSL, 1945 

Oppenheim,"^?., and Hempel, C. G., “L'importance iogique de la notion de 
i\pe,” Acies du Congres Intern, de Philosophie Scientifique, Paris 
J93L 1936 

“Studies in the Logic of Explanation,” PS. 1948. Reprinted as “The Logic 
of Explanation” in Feigi, K. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in she 
Philosophy of Science 

Oppenheim, P. and Kemeny, J. G., “On Reduction,” PSt, 1956 
OiT, S. S.. “Some Reflections on the Cambridge Approach to Philosophy, 1 
and II,” AJ, 1946 

O’Shaughnessy, B., “The Origin of Pain,” A, 1954-55 
“The Limits of the Will,” PR, 1956 
'The Location of Sound,” M, 1957 ^ 

Ossowska, M., “W sprawie podstaw semantyki” (On the Question of the 
Foundation of Semantics), Przcglad Filozoficzny, 1925 
Ossowski, S., “Analiza poiecia znaku” (Analysis of the Notion of Sign), 
Przeglad Filozoficzny, 1926 

Oxiensliema, G., “Was versteht der Physiker unier der ‘Grosse’ eines Korpers? 

Bemerkungen zu Philipp Frank's vorherstehendem Artikei,” T, 1937 
Paimieri, L. E., “Verification and Descriptive Predicates,” PPR, 1954-55 
“Eniaiiment and Contradiction,” PPR., 1956-51 
Pap, A., “The Meaning of Necessity,'* JP, 1943 
“The Dinereni Kinds of A Priori,” PR, 1944 
• “Indubitable Existential Statements.** Af. 1946 
“A Note on Logic and Existence.” M, 1947 
“A Semantic Examination of Realism,” JP, 1947 
“Logical Nonsense,” PPR, 1948-49 
“Synonymity and Logical Equivalence,” A, 1948-49 
“Are All Necessary Propositions Anai>Tic?,” PR, 1949 
“Are Individual Concepts Necessarx^?,” PSt, 1950 
“Logic and the Concept of Entaiimeni,” JP, 1950 
“Osiensive Definition and Empirical Cenainty,” M, 1950 
“Other Minds and the Principle of Verifiability,” RevJntPhiL, 1951 
“Note on the ‘Semantic’ and the 'Absolute’ Concept of Truth,” PSs, 1952 
“Philosophical Analysis, Translation Schemas and the Regularity Theory 
of Causation,” JP, 1952 

“Semantic Analysis and Psycho-Physical Dualism,” M, 1952 






Bibliography of Logical Positivism [ ^2.7 ] 

' 'P 2 in icondnued) ^ ^ <-2 

^gic, Existence and the Theory of Descnptions, A, 1952-53 
‘The Linguistic Hierarchy and the Vicious-Circie^Principl^ FSd 
“Propositions, Sentences and the Semantic Definition of Truth, i, 1954 
“Belef, Synonymity and Analysis,” FSt, 1955 
*^eiiefs and Propositions,” FS, 1957 
‘Tact, Fiction and Forecast,” RM, 1955 
“Once More: Colors and the Synthetic A Priori,” Pi?, 1957 
p«<«:h A., “Empiricism: One ‘Dogma’ or Two?,” JP, 1956 
Passmore, J. A.. Logical Positivism, I-m,” AJ, 1944 1948 

“Philosophy and Scientific Method,’ Ar.Soc., 1948-49 
“Reflections on Logic and Language ^ AJ, 1952 
“Professor Ryle’s Use of ‘Use’ and ‘Usage,’ ” PR, 1954 
“Intentions,” ArSocSup., 1955 

“Christianity and Positivism,” AJ, 1957 , . o - -t -da 

Paton H. J., “Inc Alleged independence of Goodness,’ sn Scnilpp, ^ . a.. 
The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 1942 
“The Emotive Theory of Ethics,” ArSocSup., 1948 „ . . : 

“Fifty Years of Philosophy,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British 
Philosophy (third series), 1956 

Paul, G. A., “The Analysis of Sense-Data” A., 1935-36 ^ . 

“Is Tnere a Problem about Sense Data?,” ArSocSup., 1936. Reprmted 
in Flew, A., Logic and Language (first series) ^ 

“Lenin’s Theor>^ of Perception,” .4, 1937-38. Reprmted m Macaonald, M., 
Philosophy and Analysis „ ♦ a ^ 

“G. E. Moore: Analysis, Common Usage, and Common Sense, in Ayer, 
A. J. et al, The Revolution in Philosophy, 1956 
“Wittgenstein,” ^ 

Peach, B., “A Nondescriptive Theoiy' or the Anahoic,^ 4 K, 

“Logical and Practical Contradictions,” A, 1953-54 
Pears, D. F., “Hypotheticals,” A, 1949-50. Reprinted m Macaonald, M.; 
Philosophy and Analysis 

“Symthetic Necessary^ Truth,” M, 1950 , . 

‘Time, Truth and Inference,” ArSoc., 1950-51. Reprintec m Flew, 
Essays in Conceptual Analysis 
“The Logical Status of Supposition,” Ar.SocSup., 1951 
“Universais,” PQ, 1950-51. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic and Language 

(second series) / ^ 

“Incompatibilities of Colors,” in Fiew, A., Logic and uinguage (second 

series), 1953 

“The Identity of Indiscemibles,” M, 1955 

“Logical Atomism: Russell and Wittgenstein,” in Ayer, A. J. et ah, The 
Revolution in Philosophy, 1956 

Pears, D. F., Grice, H. P. and Strawson, P. F., “Metaphysics, m The Nature 
of Metaphysics, 1957 

Penelmum, T., “The Logic of Pleasure,” PPR, 1957 

Penttila, A. and Saarnio, U., “Einige grundiegende Tatsachen der Worttheone 
neben Bemerkungen fiber die sogenannten unvoilstkndigen Symboie, 
E, 1934 

Peters, R. S., “Observationalism in Psychology,” M, 1951 
“Motives and Causes,” ArSocSup., 1952 


195: 


A., 



j- 42 g ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Pinsky, L. O., “Positivism and Realism,” M, 1954 

Place, U. T. and Smart, J- J. C., “Contradictories and Entailment,” FPR, 
1954-55 

Popper, K. R., “mat is Dialectic?,” M, 1940 
“i^e Contradictions Embracing?,” M, 1943 
“The Poverty^ of Historicism,” Economica, 1944 

“my Are the Calculuses of Logic and Arithmetic Applicable to Real- 
ity?,” ArSocSup., 1946 
“Logic without Assumptions,” ArSoc., 1946-47 

“New Foundations for Logic,” M, 1947, vith Corrections and Additions, 
M, 1948 

“mat Can Logic Do for Philosophy?/' ArSocSup., 1948 
“A Note on Natural Laws and So-Called ‘Contrary-to-Fact Condi- 
tionals,’ ” M, 1949 ^ , tt « 

“Indeterminism in Quantum Physics and in Classical Physics, I and II, 

BJPS, 1950-51 , . . „ 

“The Nature of Philosophical Problems and their Roots in Science,” 
BJPS, 1952-53 

“The Principle of Individuation,” ArSocSup., 1955 
“Self-Reference and Meaning in Ordinary Language,” M, 1954 
“Degree of Connrmation,” BJPS, 1954-55 
“A Note on the Body-Mind Problem,” A, 1954-55 
“A Note on Tarski's Definition of Truth,” Af, 1955 
“Three Views concerning Human Knowledge.” in Lewis, H. D., Con- 
temporary British Philosophy (third series), 1956 
“Philosophy of Science: A Personal Repon." in Mace, C. A., British 
Philosophy in the Mid-Century, 1^57 

Popper-Lymkeiis. J.' “Dber die GrundbegriSe der Philosophie und die_Gewiss- 
heit unserer Erkenntnisse (aus dem literarischen Nachiass hsraus- 
gegeben von Margit Omstein).” £. 1932-33 
Porteous. A, J, D., “Are There Synthetic A Prion i ruths?, Ar.SocSup,, i9:>6 
Pratt, J. B., “Logical Positivism and Professor Lewis,” IP, 1934 
Price, H, H., “The Nature of Sensible Appearances." ArSocSup., 1926 
“Mill’s View of the External World,” Ar.Soc., 1926-27 
“Negation,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1929 
“Our Knowledge of Other Minds,” Ar.Soc.. 1931-32 
“Some Considerations about Belief.” 1934-35 

“Logical Positivism and Theology,” P, 1935 
“Memory- -Know iedge/' Ar.Soc.Sup., 1936 
“Our Evidence for the Existence of Other Minds.” P, 1938 
“Critical Notice of A. J. Ayer's The Foundaiions of Empirical Knowl- 
edges M, 1941 

“The Causal Argument for Physical O'Djecis,” Ar.SocSup., 1945 

“Clarity Is Not Enough,” Ar.SocSup., 1945 

“Ayer’s Thinking and Meaning,’* P, 1948 

“British Philosophy betw'een the W’ars,” Horizon, 1949 

“Image Thinking,” Ar.Soc., 1951-52 

“Seeming,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1952 

“Belief and Will,” Ar.5oc.Swp., 1954 

“Discussion: Professor Ayer’s Essays,” FO, 1955 

“The Argument from Illusion,” in Lewis, H. D.. Contemporary British 
Philosophy (third series), 1956 


.Bihliography of Logical Positivism [ 429 ] 

piice-WIlliams, D. R., “Proprioception and Personal Identity,” PPR^ 1956-57 
Pricbard, H. A., “The Sense-Datum FaOacy,” ArSocSup,, 1938 
Prior, A- N., “Can Religion Be Discussed?,” AJ, 1942. Reprinted in Flew A. 
and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philosophical Theology 
‘Tacts Propositions and Entailment,” M, 1948 
*Ts Necessary Existence Possible?,” PFR, 1954-55 
Putnam, H., “Synonymity' and the Analysis of Belief Sentences,” A, 1953-54 
“Mathematics and the Existence of Abstract Entities,” PSt, 1956 
“Reds, Greens and Logical Analysis,” FR, 1956 

“Psychological Concepts, Explication, and Ordinary Language,” /F, 1957 
Quine, W. V., “Ontological Remarks on the Propositional Calculus,” Af, 1934 
“Truth by Convention,” in Philosophical Essays for A. N. Whitehead, 
1936. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophi- 
cal Analysis 

“Designation and Existence,” IP, 1939. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sel- 
lars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“Notes on Existence and Necessity,” JP, 1943. Reprinted in linsky, L., 
Semantics and the Philosophy of Language 
‘The Problem of Interpreting Modal Logic,” JSL, 1947 
“On Universais,” JSL, 1947 

“On What There Is,” RM, 1948-49. Reprinted in From a Logical Point 
of View, and in Linsky, L., Semantics and the Philosophy of Lan- 


guage 

“Identity, Ostension and Hypostasis,” JP, 1950. Reprinted in From a 
Logical Point of View 

“Goodman’s The Structure of Appearance^ JP, 1951 
“On Carnap’s Views on Ontology,” PSt, 1951 
“Ontology and Ideology,” PSt, 1951 
“On What There is,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1951 

“Semantics and Abstract Objecis,” Proceedings of the American Academy 
of Arts and Sciences, 1951 

“Two Dogmas of Empiricism,” PR, 1951. Reprinted in From a Logical 
Point of View 

“Mr. Strawson on Logical Theory,” M, 1953 
“On a So-Called Paradox,” M, 1953 

“The Problem of Meaning in Linguistics,” in From a Logical Point of 
View, 1953 

“On Frege’s Way Out,” M, 1955 
“Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes,” JP, 1956 
“The Scope and Language of Science,” BJPS, 1957-58 
Quine, W. F. and Goodman, N., “Steps toward a Constructive Nominalism,” 
JSL, 1947 

Quinton, A., “Seeming,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1952 

“On Punishment,” A, 1953-54. Reprinted in Laslett, P., Philosophy, 
Politics and Society 

“The Problem of Perception,” M, 1955 
“Properties and Classes,” Ar.Soc., 1957-58 
Ramsey, F., “Critical Notice of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logic o-Philosophlcus,** 
M, 1923. Reprinted in The Foundations of Mathematics 
“Universais,” M, 1925. Reprinted in The Foundations of Mathematics 
“The Foundations of Mathematics,” Proceedings of the London Mathe- 
matical Society, 1926. Reprinted in The Foundations of Mathematics 









■ 






[ 430 ] 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


mS: 


■■■ ^ 
• £ 


tii 


Ramsey, F. {continued) 

“Universals and the ‘Method of Analysis/ ” ArSocSup., 1926 
“Facts and Propositions,” ArSocSup., 1927. Reprinted in The Founda- 
tions of Mathematics 

Rand, R,, “Kotarbinski’s Philosophie,” E, 1937-38 

“Die Logik der Fordenmgssatze,” Int. Zeitschrift f. Theorie d. Rechts, 
1939 

Rankin, K. W., “Linguistic Analysis and the Justification of Induction,” PQ^ 
1955 

“Causal Modalities and Alternative Action,” FQ, 1957 

Ranulf, S., “Positivism and Sociology,” T, 1942 

Raphael, D. D., “Universals, Resemblance and Identity,” ArSoc., 1954-55 
“Linguistic Performances and Descriptive Meaning,” M, 1956 

Rees, D. A., “The Meaning of ‘Survival,’” A, 1951-52 

Relchenbach, H., “Der Begriff der Wahrscheinlichkeit fur die mathematische 
Darsteliung der Wirklichkeit,” Zeitschiifi fur Philosophie und philo- 
sophische Kritik, 1916 

“Ober die physikalischen Voraussetzungen der Wahrscoeinliclikeitsrecli- 
nung,” Zeitschrift fur Fhysik, 1920 and 1921 
“Die physikalischen Voraussetzungen der Vvahrscheiniichkeitsrechnung,” 
Die Naturwissenschaften, 1920 

“Philosophische Kritik der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung,” Die Naiurms- 
senschaften, 1920 

“Die Einsteinsche Raumlehre,” Die Umschau, 1920 
“Bericht liber eine Axiomatik der Einsteinchen Pvaum-Zeit-Lehre,” Pky- 
sikalische Zeitschrift, 1921 

“Die Einstemsche Bewegungslehre,” Die Umschau, 1921 
“La signification phiiosophique de ia theorie de ia relamite,” Revue 
Philosophique de la France et de VEtranger. 1922 
“Der gegenwlirtige Stand der Reiativiratsdiskussion,” Logos, 1921-22. 
Eng. transL, “The Present State of the Discussion on Reiativiiy.” 
in Selected Essays 

“Die Bewegungslehre bei Newton, Leibniz und Kuvshens,” Kanistudien, 
1924 

“Die reiativistische Zeitlehre,” Scientia, 1924 

“Die Kausaistruktur der Welt und der Unierschied von Vergangenheir 
und Zukunft,” Bayerische Akademic der V/issenschafien, Sitzungs- 
berichte, 1925 

“Wahrscheinlichkeitsgesetze und Kausaigesetze,” Die Urnscha:., 1925 
“Lichtgeschwindigkeit und Gleichzeidgkeit,” Aroialen der Philosophie, 1927 
“Meiapbysik und Naturvrdssenschaft,” Symposion, 1927 
“Wandiungen im physikalischen Weitbiid,” Zeiischrif: fiir angewandte 
Chemie, 1928 

“Das Kausalproblem in der gegenwartigen Physik,” Zeitschrift fur ange- 
wandte Chemie, 1929 

“Neuere Forschungsergebnisse in der Naturphilosophie,” Forsckungen und 
Fortschritte, 1929 

“Ziele und Wege der physikalischen Erkenntnis,” Handbuch der Physik, 
1929 

“Probleme und Denkweisen der gegenwartigen Physik,” Deutsche Rund- 
schau, 1930 







Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

: - ®’®‘^“^^^pMlosoplusche Bedeutung der modemen PhysS” E, 

' “Kaukntat uad Wahrscheinlichkeit E, 1930-31. Eng. transL, Causality 

and Probability,” in Selected Essays 

“Das Kausalproblem in der Physik,” Naturwissenschaften, 1931 
“Axiomatik der Wahrscheinlicbkeitsrechnung,” Mathematische Zeitschntt, 

1931-32 

“Bemerkungen ziim Wahrsdieinlichkeitsproblein,’ H, 1931-32 
“Der physikaiische Wahrheitsbegriff,” £, 1931-32 
“Zbih Anscbauiichkeitsproblem der Geometrie,” E, 1931-32 
^Wabrscbeinlichkeitslogik,”’ Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akadem 
der Wissenschaften, Phys.-Maik, Klasse, 1932 _ 

-Die Kaosalbebauptung iind die MogHcbkeit ibrer empmschen Nachpm- 
fong” E, 1932-33. Eng. transL, “The Principle of Causality and the 
Possibility of Its Empirical Confirmation^’ in 
“Die iogischen Grundlagen des Wafaxscheinlichkeitsbegriffs, ^ ‘ 

Eng! transL, “The Logical Foundations of the Concept of Prob- 
abiW” in Feiai. H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical 
Analysis, and in>eigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philos- 
ophy of Science . „ , 

“Kausalitat und Wahrscheinlichkeit in der gegenwartigen PhysiL, Unter- 
richtsbldtter fiir Mathematik und Naturwissenschaften, 1933 
“Bemerkungen zu Carl Hempels Versuch einer finitistischen Deutung 
des Wahrscheinlichkeitsbegrifis,” E, 1935 
“Bemerkungen zu Karl Marbes statistischen Untersuchungen zur Wahr- 
scheinlichkeitsrechnung,” E, 1935 

“Uber Induktion und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Bemerkungen zu Karl Poppers 
Logik der Forschung," E, 1935 

“Wahrscheiniichkeitslogik,” £, 1935 __ , 

“Die Bedeutung des Wahrscheinlichkeitsbegnffs lur die ErKenntms, 

Actes du Vlllemc Congres Intern, de Pnilosophie, Prague 193., 

“Die^Sduktion als Methode der wissenschaMchen Erkemtnis,” Actes 

du Congres Intern, de Pnilosophie Scientifique, Pans 1935, 1936 
“Uempirisme iogistique et la desagreation de Fa pnon, Actes du Con- 
ores Intern, de Philosophie Scientifiaue, Pans 1935, 1“36 
“Logistic Empiricism in Germany and the Present State of 2 ts Problem , 
jp 1935 ,, 

“WahrscheinUchkeitslogik als Form wissenschaftiichen Denkens,” Actes 
du Congres intern, de Philosophie Scientifique, Pans 1935, 1936 
“Warum ist die Anwendung der induktionsregel fur uns notwen ^ 
Bedingung von Voraussagen?,” E, 1936-37 , .7 r • 

“Causalite et Eduction,” Bulletin de la Sociiti Frangaise de Philosophie, 

“La philosophie scientifique: une esquisse de ses traiu pnncipaux, Tra- 
vaux de IXetne Congres Intern, de Philosophie Pans, 1937 
“Les fondements logiques du calcul des probabilites, Annales de I 
L..' . stitut Henri Poincare, 1937 

“On Probability and Induction,” P5, 1938 

“Dewey’s Theory of Science,” in Scfailpp, P. A., The Philosophy of John 
■ ■ Dewey, 1939 



[ 432 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Reichenbacb, H. (continued) 

“Bemerkungen zur Hypothesenwabrscheinliclikeit,” JUS, 1939-40 
“0ber die semantische und die Objekt-aiiffassiing von Wahrscbeiiilicb- 
keitsaasdriicken,” JUS, 1939-40 

“On the Justificatioii of Inductioii,” JP, 1940, Reprinted in Feigi, H. and 
Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“On Meaning,” JUS, 1940 

“Bertrand RusseE’s Logic,” in Schilpp, P. A., The Philosophy of Bertrand 
Russell, 1944 

“Reply to lOonald C. William’s Criticism of the Frequency Theory of 
Probability',” PPR, 1944-45 

“The Principle of Anomaly in Quantum Mechanics,” Dialectica, 1948. 
Reprinted in Feigi, H. and Brodbeck, M,, Readings in the Philosophy 
of Science 

“RationaEsm and Empiricism: an Inquiry^ into the Roots of PhEosophical 
Error,” PR, 1948 

“Tns Philosophical Analysis of Quantum Mechanics.” Library of the 10th 
Intern. Congress of Philosophy, Amsterdam, 1948, 1949 
“Philosophical Foundations of Probability,” Proceedings of the Berkeley 
Symposium on Mathematical Staiistics and Probability, 1949 
“On Observing and Perceiving,” PSt, 1951 

“The Philosophical Significance of the Theory of Relativity,” in Schilpp, 
P. A., Albert Einstein: Phiiosopher-Scientist, 1951. Reprinted in 
Feigi, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philosophy of Science, 
and in Wiener, P. P., Readings in Philosophy of Science 
“t)ber die erkenntnistheoretische Probiemiage und den Gebrauch einer 
dreiwertigen Logik in der Quanienmechanil;,” Zeitschrift fur Natur- 
forsckung, 1951 y 

“Tne Verifiabihty Theory of Meaning,” Froceedings of the Amer. Acad, 
of Arts and Sciences, 1951. Reprinted in Feigi, H. and Brodbeck, M., 
Readings in the Philosophy of Science 
“Are Phenomenal Reports Absolutely Certain?,” PR, 1952 
“The Syllogism Revised,” PS, 1952 

“Les fondements logiques de la mecanique des quanta,” Annales de 
VInstitut Henri Poincare, 1952-53 

Rescher, N., “The Identity of Indiscemibies : A Reinterpretation,” JF, 1955 
“Translation as a Tool of PhEosophical Analysis,” JF, 1956 
Rhees, R., “Science and Politics,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1949 

“Can There Be a Private Language?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 
Richards, L A., “Multiple DefiniUon,” Ar.Soc., 1933-34 
“Emotive Meaning Again,” PR, 1948 
Ritchie, A. D., “The Errors of Logical Positivism,” P, 1937 
Robinson, R., “Mr. Ryle on Propositions,” M, 1931 
“The Emotive Theory of Ethics,” Ar.SocSup., 1948 
Rollins, C. D., “Professor Ayer’s Query on ‘Other Minds’,” A, 1947-48 
“Are There Indubitable Existential Statements?,” M, 1949 
“The Philosophical Denial of Sameness of Meaning,” A, 1950-51 
“Ordinary' Language and Procustean Beds,” M, 1951 
“Logic and Description,” JP, 1956 
Ross, A-, “Imperatives and Logic,” T, 1941 

“On the Logical Nature of Propositions of Value,” T, 1945 


$ibUography of Logical Positivism [ '*33 ] 

B., “Znr Krise der Wissenschaft iind libder den logistischen Neo 
Positivismus,'^ Synthese, 1939 
- IL., “I-a Scoiastique et la logiqne ” E, 1935 

“Xe L^gage de la Physique est-il Universel et Autonome?,” E, 1937-38 
“The Relatiyity of Logic,"’ PPR, 1941-42 
Rttbiis, E., ^‘Bemerlmgeii tiber unser Wissen von anderen Menschen,"" E, 
1936-37 

Rudner, R-, “Formal and Non-Formal,” PS, 1949 

“The Ontological Status of the Esthetic Object,” PPR, 1949-50 
“Counter-Intuithity and the Method of Analysis,” PSt, 1950 
“On Semiotic Aesthetics,” Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 1951 
Rnja, H., “The Logic of Logical Positivism,” JP, 1936 

Russell, B., “Sur la logique des relations avec des applications a la theorie 
des series,” Rivista di matematica, 1900-01. Reprinted in Eng. transL 
as “The Logic of Relations” in Logic and Knowledge 
“G. E. Moore’s Principia EihicaJ* Independent Review, 1904 
“Meinong’s Tneory of Complexes and Assumptions, I-III,” M, 1904 
“On Denoting,” M, 1905. Reprinted in Logic and Knowledge, and in 
Feigl, H. and Sellars, W-, Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“The Nature of Truth,” M, 1906. 

“On the Nature of Truth,” Ar.Soc., 1906-07. Reprinted as ‘The Monistic 
Theory of Truth” in Philosophical Essays 
“The Study of Mathematics,” New Quarterly, 1907. Reprinted in Philo- 
sophical Essays, and in Mysticism and Logic 
“Pragmatism,” Edinburgh Review, 1909. Reprinted in Philosophical Essays 
“Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description,” ArSoc., 
1910-11. Reprinted in Mysticism and Logic 
“On the Relation of Universais and Particulars,” 4r.5oc., 1911-12. Re- 
printed in Logic and Knowledge 

“On the Notion of Cause,” ArSoc., 1912-13. Reprinted in Mysticism and 
Logic 

“Mysticism and Logic,” HJ, 1913-14. Reprinted in Mysticism and Logic 
“On the Nature of Acquaintance,” Monisi, 1914. Reprinted in Logic and 
Knowledge 

“The Relation of Sense-Data to Physics,” Scientia, 1914. Reprinted in 
Mysticism and Logic 

“The Uitknaie Constituents of Matter,” Monist, 1915. Reprinted in 
Mysticism and Logic 

‘The Philosop’ny of Logical Atomism, I-VII,” Monist, 1918 and 1919. 

Reprinted in Marsh, R. C., Logic and Knowledge 
“On Propositions: What They Are and How They Mean,” ArJSocSup., 
1919. Reprinted in Logic and Knowledge 
“Introduction to Ludwig Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, 
1922 

“Logical Atomism,” in Muirhead, J. H., Contemporary British Philosophy 
(first series), 1924. Reprinted in this volume, and in Logic and 
Knowledge 

“C. D. Broad's The Mind and its Place in Nature/' M, 1926 
“F. P. Ramsey’s The Foundations of Mathematics," M, 1931 
“The Limits of Empiricism,” ArSoc,, 1935-36 
“On Verification,” ArSoc., 1937-38 










[ ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

RmseH B. {continued} 

“On the Importance of Logical Form,” in Encyclopedia and Unified 
Science, 1938 

“The Relevance of Psychology to Logic,” ArSocSup., 1938 
“Dewey’s New Logic,” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy of John Dewey 
1939 

“The Philosophy of Santayana,” in ScMlpp, P. A., The Philosophy of 
George Santayana, 1940 

“Reply to Criticisms,” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy of Bertrand 
Russell, 1944 

“Logical Positivism,” Polemic, 1946 

“The Problem of Universals,” Polemic, 1946 

“Logical Positivism,” RewlntPhil, 1950. Reprinted in Logic and Knowl- 
edge 

“Ludwig Wittgenstein,” M, 1951 

“The Cult of ‘Common Usage,’” BJPS, 1952-53. Reprinted in Portraits 
from Memory 

“Philosophical Analysis,” HJ, 1955-56 
“Logic and Ontology,” JP, 1957 
“Mr. Strawson on Referring,” M, 1957 
“What is ‘Mind?,’” JP, 195S 

Russell, L. J., “Communication and VerificatioR,” ArSocSup., 1934 

“Epistemology' and the Ego-centric Predicament,” in Philosophical Studies 
— Essays in Memory of L. Susan Stehbing, 1948 
“Von Mises’ Kleines Lehrbuch des Positivismus,*^ M, 1940 
“Probability,” Ar.Soc.Siip., 1950 
Ryle, G., “Negation,” Ar.SocSup., 1929 

“.Are There Propositions?,” Ar.Soc., 1929-30 

“Systematically Misleading Expressions,” Ar.Soc., 1931-32. Reprinted in 
Flew', A., Logic and Language (hrst series) 

“Phenomenology,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1932 
“Imaginarv^ Objects,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1933 
“About,” A, 1933-34 

“Mr. Collingwood and the Ontological Argument,” M, 1935 
“Internal Relations,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1935 
“Unverihabliity-by-me,” A, 1936-37 
“Back to the Ontological Argument,” M, 1937 
“Induction and Hypothesis,” Ar.Soc.Sup._, 1937 
“Taking Sides in Philosophy,” P, 1937 

“Categories,” Ar.Soc., 1937-38. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic and Lan- 
guage (second series) 

“Conscience and Moral Convictions,” A, 1940. Reprinted in Macdonald, 
M., Philosophy and Analysis 
“Knowing How and Knowing That,” Ar.Soc., 1945-46 
“Why Are the Calculuses of Logic and Arithmetic Applicable to Reality?,” 
Ar.Soc.Sup., 1946 

“Carnap’s Meaning and Necessity,'* P, 1949 

“ ‘If,’ ‘So’ and ‘Because,’ ” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 1950 
“Logic and Professor Anderson,” AJ, 1950 

“Feelings,” PQ, 1950-51. Reprinted in Elton, W., Aesthetics and Language 
“Heteroiogicality,” A, 1950-51. Reprinted in Macdonald, M., Philosophy 
and Analysis 


Syntkese, 


; Bibliography of Logical Positivism [ 435 ] 

Ryie, G. (continued) 

“ThksMiig and Language,” ArSocSup., 1951 
•Xadwlg Wittgenstein,” A, 1951-52 
' ■ " “Ordinary Language,” FR, 1953 
“Pleasure,” ArSocSup,^ 1954 
“Proofs in Pfailosopliy,” RevJntRhlL, 1954 

“Sensation,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British Philosophy (third 
~ series), 1956 

"The Theor}^ of Meaning,” in Mace, C. A., British Philosophy in the Mid- 
Century, 1957 

Rynin, D., ‘The Nature of Communication,” JF, 1932 

"A Critical Essay on Johnson’s Philosophy of Language,” in Johnson, 
A. B., A Treatise on Language, 1947 
"Probability and Meaning,”/?, 1947 

"Dehnitions of ‘Value’ and the Logic of Value Judgments,” JF, 1948 
"Remarks on M. Schlick’s Essay ‘Positivism and Realism,’” Syntkese, 
1948-49 

"Meaning and Formation Rules,” /P. 1949 
*The IJogma of Logical Pragmatism,” M, 1956 

"A Vindication of Logical Positivism,” Proceedings and Addresses of 
Amer, Philosophical Ass?i., 1956, 1957 
"The Autonomy of Morals,” M, 1957 
Saamio, U., "Zur heterologischen Paradoxie,” T, 1937 

Saamio, U. and Penttila, A.. "Einige grundlegende Tatsachen der Worttheorie 
nebst Bemerkungen iiber die sogenannten unvoUstandigen Symbole,” 
E, 1934 

Salmon, W. C., “The Uniformity of Nature,” PPR, 1953-54 
"Regular Rules of Induction,” PR, 1956 
Salmon, W. C. and Nakhnikian, G-, “ ‘Exists’ as a Predicate,” PR, 1957 
Scheffier, I., “The Nev.^ Dualism,” JP, 1950 

"Anti-Naturalisi Restrictions in Ethics.” JF, 1953 
"An Inscripdonal Approach to Indireci Quotation.’' A, 1953-54 
"On Justification and Commitment.” JP, 1954 
"Prospects of a Modest Empiricism, I and IL” RM, 1956-57 
Schiick, M., “Gas Grundproblem der Asthetik in entwicklungsgeschichtlicher 
Beleuchtung,” Archiv f. d. gesamie Psychologie, 1910 
"Die Greuze der rAaturwissenschafilichen und philosophischen Begriffs- 
bildung,” Viertelj. f. Phil. u. 5oc.. 1910 
"Das Wesen der Wahrheit nach der modernen Logik,” ibid. 

“Gibt es intuitive Erkenntnis?,” Vierieij. f. Iv'Ls. Phil. u. Soz., 1913 
"Die phiiosophische Bedeutung ces Relativitaisprinzips,” Zeitschrift fur 
Philosophie und phiiosophische Kritik, 1915 
“Idealitat des Raumes. Introjektion und psychophysisches Problem,” 
Viertelj. f. H''iss. Phil. u. Soz., 1916 
"Erscheinung und Wesen,” Kantstudien, 1918-19 

"Naturphiiosophische Betrachtungen fiber das Kausaiprinzip,” Natur- 
wissenschaften, 1920 

. , "Ejritizistische oder empiristische Deuiung der neuen Physik?,” Kant- 
studien, 1921 

"Helmholtz als Erkenntnistheoretiker,” in Helmholtz als Physiker, Physi- 
ologe und Philosoph, Karlsruhe, 1922 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 



[ 436 ] 

Scblick, M. {continued') 

“Die RelativitMstheorie in der Philosophie,” V erhandlungen der Geselh 
schaft deutscher Naturforscher und Arzte, 1922 
“Erleben, Erkennen, Metaphysik,” Kantstudien, 1926 
“Erkenntnistheorie nnd mcxieme Physik,” Scientia, 1929 
“Gibt es ein materiaies Aprioii?,” WissenschaftUcher Jahresbericht der 
philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universitdt zu Wien fur das 
Vereinsjahr, 1930-31. Eng. transi. in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Read- 
ings in Philosophical Analysis 
“La relativite de Fespace,” Nouvelles Utteraires, 1930 
“Die Wende der Philosophic,” E, 1930-31. Reprinted in Gesammelte Auf- 
s'dtze, Eng. transi. in the present volume 
“Die Kansaiitat in der gegenwartigen Physik,” Naturwissenschaften, 1931. 
Reprinted in Gesammelte Aufsdtze and in Gesetz, Kausalitat und 
Wahrsckei nlichkeit 

“The Future of Philosophy,” Publ. in Philos, of the College of the Pacific, 
1932. Reprinted in Gesammelte Aufsdtze, and in Bronstein, D., Kri- 
korian, Y. and Wiener, P., Basic Problems in Philosophy 
“A Nev/ Philosophy of Experience,” Publ. in Philos, of the College of 
the Pacific, 1932. Reprinted in Gesammelte Aufsdtze 
“Causality in Everyday Life and in Recent Science,” Publ in Philos, of 
the University of Calif., 1932. Reprinted in Gesammelte Aufsdtze, 
and in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“Positivismus und Realismus,” E, 1932-33. Reprinted in Gesammelte 
Aufsdtze. Eng. transi. in Synthese, 1948-49, and the present volume 
“Dber den Begriff der Ganzheit,” WissenschaftUcher Jahresbericht der 
phiiosophischen Gesellschaft an der 'Universitdt zu Wien fur das 
Vereinsjahr, 1933-34 and 1934-35, and E, 1935. Reprinted in Gesam- 
melte Aufsdtze, and in Gesetz, Kausalitat und Wahrscheinlichkeit 
“Les enonces scieniiaques et la realite du luonde exterieiir,” Actualites 
scientifiques, 1934 

“Uber das Fundament der Erkenntnis,” E, 1934. Reprinted in Gesam- 
melte Aufsdtze. Eng. transi. in the present volume; Fr. transL, 
Paris: Hermann, 1935 

“Philosophic und Naturv^dssenschaft,” E, 1934 

“Facts and Propositions,” A, 1934-35. Reprinted in Macdonald, M.# 
Philosophy and Analysis 

“De la relation entre ies notions psychologiques el les notions ph\^iques,” 
Revue de Synthese, 1935. Eng. transi. in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., 
Readings in Philosophical Analysis 

“Unanswerable Questions?,” The Philosopher, 1935. Reprinted in Ge- 
sammelte Aufsdtze 

“Sind die Naturgeseize Konventionen?,” Actes du Congres Intern, de 
Philos. Scientifique, Paris 1935, 1936. Reprinted in Gesammelte 
Aufsdtze and in Gesetz, Kausalitat, und Wahrscheinlichkeit. Eng. 
transi. in Feigl, H. and Brodbeck, M., Readings in the Philosophy 
of Science 

“Gesetz und Wahrscheinlichkeit,” Actes du Congres Intern, de Philos. 
Scientifique, Paris 1935, 1936. Reprinted in Gesammelte Aufsdtze 
and Gesetz, Kausalitat und Wahrscheinlichkeit 
“Meaning and Verification,” PR, 1936. Reprinted in Gesammelte Auf- 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism [ 437 ] 

Sdilick, M. (continued) 

satze, and in FeigI, H. and Seliars, W., Readings in Philosophical 

Analysis ^ , 

“Qiiantentiieorie iind Erkeimbarlieit der Natur,” E, 1936'37. ^Repnnted 
in Ge:mmmelte Auf satze and GesetZt Kausalizdt und Wahrschein- 
Uchkeit 

*%*6cole de Vienne et la philosopbie traditionelie,” Travaux du IXeme 
Congres Intern, de Philosophie, Paris, 1937 
“Form and Content, an Introduction to PhiiosopMcal T hink i n g. Thr^ 
Lectures, delivered in the University of London in Nov. 1932,” in 
Gesammelte Auf satze, 1938 

Schuitzer, B., “Empiricism as a Logical Problem,” T, 1949 
Scriven, M.. “Paradoxical Announcements,” M, 1951 
“Definitions in Amalyticai Philosophy,” PSt, 1954 
“Language in Fiction,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1954 
Segerstedt, T. T., “Imperative Propositions and Judgments of Value,” T, 1945 
Sellars, R. W., “The Meaning of True and False,” PPR, 1944-45 
Sellars, W., “Epistemology and the New Way of Words,” IP, 1947 
“Pure Pragmatics and Epistemology,” PS, 1947 

“Realism and the New Way of Words,” PPR, 1947-4S. Reprinted in 
Feigi, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“Concepts as Involving Laws and inconceivable without Tnem,“ PS, 1948 
“On the Logic of Complex Particulars.” M, 1949 

“Language, Rules and Behavior,” in Hook, S., John Deyeey: Philosopher 
of Science and Freedom, 1950 

“Quotation Marks, Sentences and Propositions,” PPR, 1949-50 
“Gestalt Qualities and the Paradox of Analysis,” PSt, 1950 
“The Identity of Linguistic Expressions and the Paradox of Analysis,” 
PSt, 1950 

“Mind, Meaning and Behavior,” PSt, 1952 
“Particulars,” PPR, 1952-53 
“Inference and Meaning,” M, 1953 
“Is There a Synthetic A Priori?,” PS, 1953 

“A Semantical Solution of the Mind-Body Problem,” Meihodos, 1953 
“Presupposing,” PR, 1954 

“Some Reflections on Language Games.'* PS, 19o4 
“Logical Subjects and Physical Objects. PPR, 1956-5, 

Sesonke, A., “On the Skepticism of Ethics and Language A IP, 1955 
“‘Cognitive’ and ‘Normative,’” PPR., 1956 
“Truth in Art,” JP, 1956 

Sheam, M., “Other People's Sense-Data,” Ar.Soc., 1949-50 
“Russell’s Anaiysis of Existence,” A:, 1950-51 
Shwayder, D. S., “Some Remarks on “Synonymity’ and the Language of the 
Semanticists,” PSt, 1954 
“Achilles Unbound,” /P, 1955 
“Self-Defeating Pronouncements,” A, 1955-56 
M, 1956 

Smart, H. R., “Language Games,” PQ, 1957 

Smart, J. J. C., “The River of Time,” M, 1949. Reprinted in Flew, A., Essays 
in Conceptual Analysis 

“■Whitehead and Russell’s Theory of Types,” A, 1949-50 


Paradox of Analysis,” 





[ 438 ] Bibliography of Logical Fositivism 

Smart, J. J. C. {continued) 

“Excogitatioii and Induction,” AJ, 1950 
“Reason and Conduct,” F, 1950 

“Theory Construction,” PFR, 1950-51. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic and 
Language (second series) 

“The Moving ‘Now,* ” AJ, 1953 
“The Temporal Asymmetry of the World,” A, 1953-54 
“The Existence of God,” Church Quarterly Review, 1955. Reprinted in 
Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A., New Essays in Philosophical Theology 
and in Edwards, P. and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philos- 
ophy 

“Metaphysics, Logic and Theology,” in Flew, A. and MacIntyre, A., New 
Essays in Philosophical Theology, 1955 
“Spatiaiizing Time,” M, 1955 
“The Reality of Theoretical Entities,” AJ, 1956 
“Plausible Reasoning in Philosophy,** M, 1951 
Smart, J. J. C. and Place, U. T., “Contradictories and Entaiiment,” FPR 
1954-55 

Smullyan, A., “Aspects,” PR, 1955 

“The Concept of Empirical Knowledge,” PR, 1956 
“The Concept of Empirical Language,**’ ibid. 

Somerville, J., “Logical Empiricism and the Problem of Causality in Social 
Science,” £, 1936-37 

Spillsbuiy^, R. J., “Dispositions and Phenomenalism,*’ M, 1953 

Stace, W. T., “Tne Refutation of Realism,” M, 1936. Reprinted in Feigl, H. 

and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis and in Edwards, 
P. and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 
“Metaphysics and Meaning,’* M, 1935. Reprinted in Edwards, P. and 
Pap. A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 
“Positivism,” M, 1944 

“Are All Empirical Statements Hypotheses?,” JP, 1947 
Stanley, R. L., “A Theory of Subjunctive Conditionals,” PPR, 1956-57 
Stebbing, L. S., “The Nature of Sensible Appearances,” ArSocSup., 1926 
“Substances, Events, and Facts,” JP, 1932 
“The Method of Analysis in Metaphysics,” ArSoc., 1932-33 
“The A Priori,” Ar.SGc.Sup., 1933 
“Constructions,” Ar.Soc., 1933-34 
“Communication and Verification,” Ar.Soc.Sup„ 1934 
“Directional Analysis and Basic Facts,” A, 1934-35 
“Carnap’s Logische Syntax der Sprache, Die Aufgabe der Wissenchafts- 
logik. Philosophy and Logical Syntax, The Unity of Science, M, 1935 
“Sounds, Shapes, and Words,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1935 
“Ayer’s Language, Truth and Logic, M., 1936 
“Carnap’s Logical Syntax of Language,*' P, 1938 
“Some Puzzles about Analysis,” Ar.Soc., 1938-39 

“Moore’s Influence,” in Schiipp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 
1942 

Stenius, F., “Linguistic Structure and the Structure of Experience,” T, 1954 
Stevenson, C. L., “The Emotive Meaning of Ethical Terms,” M, 1937. Re- 
printed in Sellars, W*. and Hospers, J., Readings in Ethical Theory, 
and in the present volume 


■ SiBiiograpky of Logical Positivism 


[ 439 ] 


Stevenson, C.. L. (continued} 

*"Etlilcal Judgments and Avoidability,” M, 1938. Reprinted in Sellars, W. 
and Hospers, J., Readings in Ethical Theory 
^ “Persuasive Definitions,” M, 1938. Reprinted in Hook, S., American 
Philosophers at Work 

“Moore’s Arguments against Certain Forms of Ethical Naturalism,” in 
ScMlpp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. £. Moore, 1942 
“Some Relations between Phiiosophy and the Study of Lanmiage” A, 
1947-48 

“Meaning: Descriptive and Emotive,” PR, 2948 

“The Nature of Ethical Disagreement,” in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., 
Readings in Philosophical Analysis, 1949. Reprinted in Edwards, P. 
and Pap, A., A Modern Introduction to Philosophy, and in Munitz, 
M. K., A Modern Introduction to Ethics 
“The Emotive Concept of Ethics and its Cognitive Implications,” PR, 1950 
“Interpretation and Evaluation in Aesthetics,” in Black, M., Philosophical 
Analysis, 1950 

“Critical Notice of Nowell -Smith’s EthicsP M, 1955 
“On ‘What Is a Poem’?,” PR, 1957 
Storer, T., “The Logic of Value Imperatives,” PS, 1946 

“The Philosophical Relevance of a ‘Behavioristic Semiotic,’ ” PS, 1948 
“On Communication,” PSt, 2950 
“On Defining ‘Soluble,’” A, 1950-51 
Stout, G. F., “The Status of Sense Data,” ArSoc., 1913-14 

“Are the Characteristics of Particular Things Universal or Particular?.” 
Ar.SocSup„ 1923 

“Mechanical and Teleological Causation,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1935 
“Phenomenalism,” Ar.Soc., 1938-39 

Strauss, M., “Ungenauigkeit, Wahrscheinlichkeit und Unbesiimmtheit,” E, 
1936-37 

“Kompiementaritat und Kausalitat im Lichte der Logischen Smax,” 
1936-37 

“Mathematics as Logical Syntax — ^A Method to Formalize the Language 
of a Physical Theory',” E, 1937-38 

Strawson, P. F., “Necessary Propositions and Entailment Staiements M, 1948 

**rr> i-Li? j t Art A T-t . .. 


‘Truth,” A, 1948-49. Reprinted in Macdonald, M.. Phiiosophy and 
Analysis 

“Ethical Intuitionism,” P, 1949. Reprinted in Sellars. W. and Hospers, J., 
Readings in Ethical Theory 

“On Referring,” M, 1950. Reprinted in Flew, A., Essays in Conceptual 
Analysis 

‘Truth,” Ar.Soc.Sup,, 1950 
“Particular and General,” Ar.Soc., 1953-54 
“Presupposing: a Reply to Mr. Sellars,” PR, 1954 
“Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations, M, 1954 
“A Logician’s Landscape,” P, 1955 

Construction and Analysis,” in Ayer, A. J. et al., The Revolution in 
Philosophy, 1956 

“Singular Terms, Ontology and Identity,” M, 1956 
^‘Xogical Subjects and Physical Objects,” PPR, 1956-57 
**Logic and Knowledge by Bertrand Russell,” PQ, 1951 





Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


4^;i 






J: 

h’i. * 




&9 ’ ‘; 

m'-' ' 

%k-: 

ii:."' 



[440] 

Strawson, P. F. {continued') 

“Professor Ayer’s The Problem of Knowledge f* P, 1957 

“Proper Names,” ArSocSup., 1957 

“Propositions, Concepts and Logical Tnitlis,” PQ, 1957 

Strawson, P. F. and Grice, H. F., “In Defense of a Dogma,” PR, 1956 

Strawson, P. R, Grice, H. P. and Pears, D. F., “Metaphysics,” in Pears, D. F., 
The Mature of Metaphysics, 1957 

Stroll, A., “A Problem concerning the Analysis of Belief Sentences,” A, 1953-54 

“Is Everyday Languase Inconsistent?,” M, 1954 

“On The,’ ”PPR, 1955-56 

Strzelewicz, W., “tlber Moraibegnindiing. Bemerknngen zu Victor Krafts Auf- 
satz,” T, 1941 

Tarski, A., “O w^yrazie pierwotnym logistyki,” Przeglad Filozoficzny, 1923. 

Reprinted in a modified version in tw’o parts: “Sur le terme primitif 
de la logistique,” Fundamenta Mathematicae, 1923, and “Sur les 
truth-functions au sens de MM. Russell et Whitehead,” Fundamenta 
Mathematicae, 1924, and in Eng. transL, “On the Primitive Term of 
Logistic,” in Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 

“Remarques sur les notions fondamentaJes de la methodoiogie des matbe- 
matiques,” Annales de la Societe Polonaise de Mathemadque, 1929. 
Reprinted in an expanded version as “Dber einige lundamentalen 
Begriffe der Mathematik,” Comptes rendus des seances de la So- 
elite des Sciences et des Lett res de Varsovie, 1930, and in Eng. 
transL, “On Some Fundamental Concepts of Metamathematics,” in 
Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 

“Fundamentale Begrifie der Methodoiogie der deduktiven Wissenschafien, 
I,” Monatsh. Math. Pkys., 1930. Eng. transL in Logic, Semantics, 
Metamathematics 

“Pojecie prawdy w jtzykach nauk dedukcyjnych,” Travaux ^de la Societe 
des Sciences et des Lettres de Varsovie, Classe III. Sciences mathe- 
matiques et physiques, 1933. Reprinted as “Der Wahrheitsbegrifi in 
den formaiisierten Sprachen” in Studia Fhilosophica, 1935, and as 
“The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages” in Logic, Seman- 
tics, Metamathematics 

“Einige methodologische Untersuchungen liber die Derinierbarkeit der 
Begriffe,” E, 1935. Eng. transL in Logic, Semantics, Metamath smatics 

“Grundlegung der wissenschafilichen Semaniik,” Actes du Congres Intern, 
de Philosophie Scientifique, Paris 1935, 1936. Eng. transL in Logic, 
Semantics, Metamathematics, and Polish transL in Przeglad Filozo- 
fiezny, 1936 

“Ober den Begrifi der logischen Folgerung,” Actes du Congres Intern, de 
Philosophie Scientifique, Paris 1935, 1936. Eng. transL in Logic, 
Semantics, Metamathematics, and Polish transL in Przeglad Filozo- 
ficzny, 1936 

“On Lfndecidabie Statements in Enlarged Systems of Logic and the Con- 
cept of Truth,” JSL, 1939 

“The Semantic Conception of Truth and the Foundations of Semantics,” 
PPR, 1943-44. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in 
Philosophical Analysis, and in Linsky, L., Semantics and the Philos- 
ophy of Language 

Tarski, A. and Lukasiewicz, J., “Untersuchungen liber den Aussagenkal kill,” 


[ 441 ] 


i 



Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

TaxsM, A. and Lukasiewicz, J. (continued) 

Comptes rendus des seances de la Societe des Sciences et des Letires 
de Varsovie^ 1930. Eng. transl. in Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics 
Taylor, D., ‘"Fallacies in Moral Philosophy. S. Hampshire,” M, 1951 
Taylor, R., “Mr. Black on Temporal Paradoxes,” A, 1951-52 
“Negative Things,” IF, 1952 

“Mr. Wisdom on Temporal Paradoxes,” A, 1952-53 
“Ayer’s Analysis of Negation,” FSt, 1953 
“Dilutes about Synonymy,” FR, 1954 

“Spatial and Temporal Analogies and the Concept of Identity,” IF, 1955 
“The Problem of Future Contingencies,” FR, 1957 
Terrell, D. B., “On a Supposed S5mthetic Entailment,” FSt, 1951 
“\^at You Will, or The Limits of Analysis,” FSt, 1952 
“A Remark on Good Reasons,” FSt, 1953 
Thompson, M., “What Are Law-Statements About?,” JF, 1955 
“On Category Differences,” PR, 1957 
Thomson, J. F., “A Note on Truth,” A, 1948-49 

“The Argument from Analogy and Our Knowledae of Other Minds,” M, 
1951 

“Some Remarks on Synon>miy,” A, 1951-52 
“Reducibility,” Ar.Soc.SLtp., 2952 
“Tasks and Super-Tasks,” A, 1954-55 
Toiman, E. C., “An Operational Analysis of ‘Demand,’ ” E, 1936-37 
Tomas, V., “Ethical Disagreements and the Emotive Theor>' of Values, M, 1951 
Toms, E., “Facts and Entailment,” M, 1948 
“Non-Existence and Universals,” PQ, 1956 
Touimin, S., “A Defence of ‘Synthetic Necessary Truth,’” M, 1949 

“Probability,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1950. Reprinted in Flew, A., Essays in Con- 
ceptual Analysis 

“is There a Fundamental Problem in Ethics?,” AJ, 1955 
“Contemporary/ Scientific Mythology,” in Touimin, et al. Metaphysical 
Beliefs, 1957 

Touimin, S. and Baier, K., “On Describing,” M, 1952 

University of California Associates, “The Freedom of the Will,” in Knowl- 
edge and Society, 1938. Reprinted in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W.. Read- 
ings in Philosophical Analysis and in Munitz, M. K., A Modem 
Introduction to Ethics 

Urban, W. M., “Value Propositions and Vermability,” JP, 1937 

“The Dialectic of Meaning and Truth: Truth as Immanent in Discourse,” 
PFR, 1943-44 

Uimson, I. O., “Are Necessary Truths True by Convention?,” .4,r.Soc.Sup., 1947 
“Two of the Senses of ‘Probable,’ ” A., 1947-48. Reprinted in Macdonald, 
M-, Philosophy and Analysis 

“On Grading,” M, 1950. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic and Language 
(second series) 

“Motives and Causes,” Ar.SocSup., 1952 

“Parenthetical Verbs,” M, 1952. Reprinted in Flew, A., Essays in Con- 
ceptual Analysis 

“Some Questions Concerning Validity,” Rev.Int.PhfL, 1953. Reprinted in 
Flew, A., Essays in Conceptual Analysis 
“Recognidon,” ArSoc., 1955-56 





.J 


tililK;. 


?i||i ^ f ■ ^ j 

mmA 


[ 442 ] Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Ushenko, A., “The Problem of General Propositioiis,” Monist, 1933 
“The Problem of Semantics,” /P, 1942 

“Rnsseil’s Critique of Empiricism,” in SchUpp, P. A., The Philosophy of 
Bertrand Russell, 1944 

“Undecidabie Statements and Meta-Language,” M, 1944 
“A Note on the Semantic Conception of Truth,” FFR, 1944-45 
Veatch, H., “Formalism and/or Intentionaiity in Logic,” FFR, 1950-51 
Vesey, G. N. A., “Unthinking Assumptions and their JustiScation,” M, 1954 
“Seeing and Seeing As,” ArJSoc., 1955-56 
Vosei, T., “Bemerkungen zur Aussagentheorie des radikalen Physikaiismus,” 
E, 1934 

Waismann, F., “Die Natur des Reduzibihtatsaxioms,” Monats. Math. Fhys,, 
1928 

“Logische Analyse des Wahrscheinlichkeitsbegriffs,” E, 1930-31 
“Ober den Begriff der Identitat,” E, 1936-37 
“1st die Logik eine deduktive Theorie?,” E, 1937-38 
“The Relevance of Psychology to Logic,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1938. Reprinted 
in Feigl, H. and Sellars, W., Readings in Philosophical Analysis 
“Verifiability,” ArSocSup,, 1945. Reprinted in Flew, A., Logic and Lan- 
guage (first series) 

“Are There Alternative Logics?,” ArSoc., 1945-46 
‘The Many-Level Stiucture of Language,” Synthese, 1946 
“Analytic-Synthetic, I- VI,” A, 1949-53 

“Language Strata,” in Fiew, A., Logic and Language (second series), 1953 
“How I See Philosophy,” in Lewis, H. D., Contemporary British Philos- 
ophy (third series), 1956. Reprinted in the present volume 
Walker, E. R., “Verification and Probability,” JF, 1947 
Walsh, W. H., “Analytic-Synthetic,” ArSoc., 1953-54 

Walter, W., “Einheitswissenschaft als Basis der Wlssenschaftsgescnichte,” £. 
1937-38 

W'ang, H., “The Existence of Material Objects,” M, 1948 
“What Is an Individual?,” PR, 1953 
“A Question of Knowledge of Knowledge,” A, 1953-54 
“Notes on the Analytic-Synthetic Distinction,” T, 1955 
“On Formalization,” M, 1955 
Wamock, G. J., “Concepts and Schematism,” A, 1948-49 

“Metaphysics in Logic,” Ar.Soc., 1950-51. Reprinted in Flew% A, Essays 
in Conceptual Analysis 

“Empirical Propositions and Hypothetical Statements,” M, 1951 
“Verification and the Use of Language,” Rev. I nt. Phil., 1951 
“Reducibiiity,” lrSoc.Sup., 1952 

“Every Event Has a Cause,” in Flew, A., Logic and Language (second 
series), 1953 

“Seeing,” Ar.Soc., 1954-55 

“Analysis and imagination,” in Ayer, A. J. et al., The Revolution in 
Philosophy, 1956 

“Criticisms of Metaphysics,” in Pears, D. F., The Nature of Metaphysics, 
1957 

Waters, B., “Positivistic and Activistic Theories of Causation, JP, 1938 
“Basic Sentences and Incorrigibility,” FS, 1942 
Watkins, I. W. N., “Between Analytical and Empirical,” P, 1957 






[ 443 ] 





Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


Watkins, J. W. N. {continued) 

“Confirmable and Infinential Metaphysics,” M, 1958 
“After the Revolution in Philosophy,” The Rationalist Annual, 1958 
Wailing, I., “The Causal Theory of Perception,” M, 1950 
“The Sum of an Infinite Series,” A, 1952-53 
“Propositions Asserting Causal Connections,” A, 1953-54 
“Ayer on Other Minds,” T, 1954 

“Inference from the Known to the Unknown,” ArSoc., 1954-55 
‘The Problem of Contrary-to-Fact Conditionals,” A, 1956-57 
“Bntailment,” ArSocSup., 1958 

Wailing, I. and Brown, R., “Amending the Verification Principle,” A,, 1950-51 
“Hypothetical Statements in Phenomenalism,” Synthese, 1950-51 
“Counterf actual Conditions,” M, 1952 

Weinberg, C. B., “Protocols, CommunicabiliW, and Pointer Readings,” JP, 1938 
Weinberg, J. R., “Our Knowledge of Other Minds,” PR, 1946 
“The Idea of Causal Efiicacy,” IP, 1950 
“Contraiy^-to-Fact Conditionals,” JP, 1951 

“Concerning Undefined Descriptive Predicates of Higher Levels,” M, 1954 
Weinberg, J. R. and Hay, W. K., “Concerning Allegedly Necessary Non- 
analyiic Propositions,” FSt, 1951 
Wdss, P., “The Logic of Semantics,” JP, 1942 
Weissmann, A., “The Meaning of Identity,” PPR, 1955-56 
Weitz, M., “Does Art Tell the Truth?,” FPR, 1942-43 

“Analysis and the Unity of RusselFs Philosophy,” in Schilpp, P* A., The 
Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, 1944 
“Philosophy and the Abuse of Language,” JP, 1947 
“Analysis and Rea! Definition,” PSt, 1950 
“Professor Ride's ‘Logical Behaviorism,’” JP, 1951 
“Oxford Philosophy,” PR, 1953 
“Analytic Statements,” M, 1954 
Weldon, T. D., “Science and Politics,” Ar.SocSup., 1949 
“Appraisals,” P, 1950 

“Political Principles,” in Laslett, P., Philosophy, Politics and Society, 1956 
Wells, D. A., “Basic Propositions in Ayer and Rmssell,” JP, 1954 
Welsh, P., “On the Nature of Inference,” PR., 1957 

Werkmeister, W. H,, “Seven Theses of Logical Positivism Criticaliv Exam- 
ined, I and II,” PR, 1937 

“The Meaning of ‘Meaning’ Re-examined,” PR, 1938 
“On ‘Describing a World,’” PPR, 1950-51 
“Problems of Value Theory,” PPR, 1951-52 
Wheatley, J. M. O., “Deliberative Questions,” A, 1954-55 
White, A. R., “Mr. Hampshire and Prof. Ryle on Dispositions,” A, 1953-54 
“A Note on Meaning and Verification,” M, 1954 
“On Claiming to Know,” PR, 1957 
‘Truth as Appraisal,” M, 1957 
White, M. G., “Probability and Confirmation,” JP, 1939 

“Historical Explanation,” M, 1943. Reprinted with postscript in Gardiner, 
P., Theories of History 

‘^e Attack on the Historical Method,” JP, 1945 
“A Note on the ‘Paradox of Analysis,’ ” M, 1945 
“Analysis and Identity: A Rejoinder,” M, 1945 



[444] 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


John Dewey: Philosopher of Science and Freedom, 1930. Repnnted 
in Linsky, L.. Semantics and 

“A Finitistic Approach to PMosop^cal The^s, PR, 19 
“Ontological Clarity and Semantic Obscunty, /P, 1951 
WWteley, C. H., ‘Truth by 

"On Meaning and Verifiability, A, 

"On the Justification of Induction, A, 

"HempeFs Paradoxes of Confirmation, M, 1945 iQ4i=; 

“Can Philosophical Theories Transcend Experience?, 

“More about ProbabiUty.” A. 1947-48. Repnnted m Macdonald, M., 

Philosophy and Analysis 
“On Understanding,” M, 1949 
"Rationality in Morals,” ArSoc,j 1949-50 
"Note on the Concept of Mind,” A, 

Whitrow, G. J., “On the Synthetic Aspect of Mathemati^, F, 1950 

W A "Moral Problems, Moral Philosophy ana Metaethics, PR, U5 
Wiener, *P. *?.,* "Some Metaphysical Assumptions and Problems oi Neo- 
Positivism ” JP, 1935 

“Philosophical, Scientific and Ordinary Language -^^.^948 
Wienpahl, P. D., “Philosophy of Ethics, Ethics, and Moral Theory, JP, 1948 
"Are All Signs Signs?,” PR, 1949 
“Frege's Sinn und Bedeutung/' M, 1950 
"Concerning Moral Responsibilit}', A, 1952-5^ 

W'iil, F. L., “Verifiability and the External World,” PS, 1940 
'“Is There a Problem of Induction?,” JP, 1942 

“Tne Coniran-io-ract Conditional,” M, 1947 . ^ a 

“Will the Future Be Like the Past?,” M, 1947. Repnnted m Flew, A., 
Logic and Language (second series), and in Edwards, P. and Pap, A., 
A Modern Introduction to Philosophy 

“Donald WOiiams’ Theory of Induction,” PR, 1948 * • iQ<n 

"Generalization and Evidence,” in Black, M., Philosophical Analysis, 195 
“Kneaie’s Tneories of Probability and Induction,” PR, 195^ 

“Tne Justincaiion of Theories,” PR, 1955 ^ r ^ a 

Williams. B. A. O., "Tertullian's Paradox,” in Flew.^ A. and MacIntyre, A., 
New Essays in Philosophical Theology, 1955 ^ 

“Personal identity’ and Individuation,” ArSoc., 1956-5/ 

“Metaphysical Arguments,” in Pears, D. F., The Nature o. Metaphysics, 
1957 

Williams, D. C., “Ethics as Pure Postulate,” PR, 1933. Reprinted m Sellars, W'. 
and Hospers, J., Readings in Ethical Theory ni: 

" Analysis, Analytic Propositions, and Real Definitions, A, 193 
"The Nature and Variety of the A Priori,” A, 1937-38 
‘The Realistic Interpretation of Scientific Sentences, E, 

"On the Derivation of Probabilities from Frequencies,” 

"The Challenging Situation in the Philosophy of Probabmty, FrK, 
1945-46 

“Induction and the Future,” M, 1948 , o j 

"The Myth of Passage,” JP, 1951. Reprinted in Hook, S., American 

Philosophers at Work 


[ 445 ] 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 

Wiliams,, D. C. (continued) 

“The Sea Fight Tomorrow,” in Henie, P., Kalien, H. M. and Langer, S. K., 
Structure, Method and Meaning, 1951 
“Professor Carnap’s Philosophy of Probablity,” PPR, 1952-53 
“On the Direct Probability of Inductions,” M, 1953 
“On the Elements of Being, I and 11,” RM, 1953-54 
Wiliams, G., “International Law and the Controversy Concerning the Word 
‘Law^’,” British Yearbook of International Law, 1945. Reprinted in 
Lasiett, P., Philosophy, Politics and Society 
“Language and the Law%” Law Quarterly Review LV, 1945 and 1946 
Wilis, R., “The Phenomenaiist Theory of the World,” M, 1957 
Wflson, N. L., “Description and Designation,” JP, 1953 

“In Defense of Proper Names against Descriptions,” PSt, 1953 
“Property Designation and Description,” Pi?, 1953 
“Space, Time, and Individuals,” JP, 1955 

“Existence Assumptions and Contingent Meaningfuiness,” M, 1956 
Winch, P. G.y “Necessar>' and Contingent Truths.” A, 1952-53 
Wisdom, John, ‘Time, Fact and Substance,” ArSoc., 1928-29 
“Logical Constructions, I-V,” M, 1931-33 

“Ostentation,” Psyche, 1933. Reprinted in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis 
“Is Analysis a Useful Method in Philosophy?,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1934. Re- 
printed in Philosoakv and Psycho-Analysis 
“God and Evil,” M, 1935 

“Philosophical Perplexity,” ArSoc., 1936-37, Reprinted in Philosophy and 
Psycho- A nalysis 

“Metaphysics and Verification,” M, 1938. Reprinted in Philosophy and 
Psycho- A nalysis 

“Other Minds, M, 1940-43. Reprinted in Other Minds 

“Moore’s Technique,” in Schilpp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. E. Moore, 
1942. Reprinted in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis 
“Waddingtons Science and EthicsT M, 1943. Reprinted in Philosophy 
and Psycho-Analysis 

“Philosophy, Anxiety and Noveit}*,” M, 1944. Reprinted in Philosophy 
and Psycho-Analysis 

“Gods,” Ar.Soc., 1944-45. Reprinied in Flew, A., Logic and Language 
(first series), and in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis 
“Other Minds,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1946 

“Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis,’' Polemic, 1946. Reprinted in Philosophy 
and Psycho-Analysis 

“Bertrand Russell and Modern Philosophy.” Politics and Letters, 1947. 

Reprinted in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis 
“Note on the New Edition of Professor Ayer’s Language, Truth and 
Logic/' M, 1948. Reprinted in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis 
“Things and Persons,” Ar.Soc.Sup., 1948. Reprinted in Philosophy and 
Psych o-A nalysis 

“The Concept of Mind,” Ar.Soc., 1949-50. Reprinted in Other Minds 
“A Note on Probability,” in Black, M-, Philosophical Analysis, 1950. 

Reprinted in Philosophy and Psycho-Analysis 
“Metaphysics,” Ar.Soc., 1950-51. Reprinted in Other Minds 
“Ludwig Wittgenstein,” M, 1952 



[ 446 ] 


Bibliography of Logical Positivism 


"S&cs and Psychoanalysis ” in Philosophy an4 Psycho- 

Wisdom, J. O., “Solijsism,” A, 1933-34 

“The Analysis of Sense-Data, A, 1934-ij »» iqai 

“Why Achilles Does Not Fail to Catch the Tortoise. M, 19 

“Positivism,” M, 1945 

“Perception-Statements,” v4r.Soc., p48-49 1051.52 

“A New Model for the Mind-Body Relation ^ 1929 

Wittgenstein, L., “Some Remarks on Lo^cal Form, 

WoUheim, R., “Privacy” ArSoc., 1950-51 

‘Tre^FomSiS of Psycholo£l Tneory.” E, 1937-38 
“Science W'ithout Properties,” BJFS, 1951-52 
Wooziey, A. D., “Dispositions,” M, 1948 
“ifnowing and No: Knowing.” ,4rEoc., 

“Ordinary' L^n'^uase and Common Sense, la, 

Wrigh? G a vt; “D« WahrscheinUchkeitsbegrifi m der modemen Erkenm- 

nisphiiosophie,” T, 1938^ ^ 

“Camais’s Tneor\’ of Probability,” PR, 1951 

1955. i. 

Uaicolm.'^.. Ludwig Wittgenstein— A Memoir 

Xenakis. J., “Ordinan- Language and Ordinary Bcusm t'o., .so-, 

Yolton, I. W., “A Defense of Sense Data,’ A.. Ij’*® 

“Linguistic and Epistemological Dualism, A, -f the 

ZawLrski. Z., “O wdecziym powTocie swiatow (Tne tverlastm. Return or 

Worlds), KKartalnik Fiiozoftczny. 1927 w,u„.i,p;nlichkeits- 

“Dber das Verhaltnis der mehrwertigen Logik zur Wahrs.nemhchkeits 

Z •SSSi ol o”So. ..5 Cf Obs.™„," P| 1956 

P.'. ’Amt and tne ‘Object of Art’,” M. 190 1- Repnnted m Elton. W., 

Aesthetics and Language Zeit” 

Zilsei, E., “Die Asymmetric der Kausalitat und me Einsmm.,keu der Ze , 
Naiurwissenschaften, 1927 ^ 

“Bemerkungen zur Wissenschaftslogik, £, 1 t qti,c ” p<? 1941 

“Phvsics a^d the Problem of Historico-Sociological Laws PS 1941. 
Reprtoed fn Feigl. H. and Brodbeck. M-. Readings tn the Philosophy 

“The Genesis of the Concept of Physical L‘R< ^ jjjg 

Zinkemagel, P., “On the Problem of Objecuve Reality as Conceived m the 

Emniricist Tradition,” Si, 1955 



Index 


Ackennas, W., 135 
Adjuciewicz, K., 6, 7, 241 
Analogy, 229, 373; arguments from, 
176, 177 , 

Analysis, 5, 324; critical, 363; logical, 

7, 76, 124 n., 133, 145, 169, 1/7, 
293, 317; logical, and philosophi- 
cal problems, 8; logical, and phi- 
losophy, 77; logical, as business 
of philosophy, 47; philosophical, 
23, 28; see also Definition 
Antinoiiues, logical, 139 
Aquinas, 134 

Aristotle, 333, 334, 368, 369 
Arithmetic, 200, 341; also Logic 
St Augustine, 218, 346, 347, 360, 362 
Austin, J. L., 9, 28 
Avenarius, R., 4, 85, 86, 291 
Axiom(s), 346; and philosophy, 330; 
of geometry, 360; doubtful, 31; 
see also Geometry, Logic, Mathe- 
matics 

Axiomatization, 136 
Ayer, A. L, 6, 8. 110 n., 112 n., 114, 
115, 116, 123 n., 124 n. 

Bar-Hillel, Y., 8 

Behavior, 21, 189, 294, 296, 304, 305, 
306, 307, 312; meaningful, 181, 
182; moral, 263; of groups 301, 
316; physical, 181; understand- 
able, 182: see also Psychology 
Behaviorism, 181, 286, 296, 297, 299, 
300, 316; social, 296, 301, 303, 
308-310, 313, 315-317 
Behmann, H-, 135 
Benjamin, A. C., 108 n. 

Bentham, 4 
Bergson, 80 

Berkeley, 16, 17, 97, 368 
Bemays, P., 135 


h 4. 

7, 8, 13, 18, 

20, 

21, 

25, 

26, 27, 28, 

107 

n., 

1 17. 

n9, 120, 

122 

n.. 

125 

n., 128 n.. 

133 



Black, M., 8, 165 n., 199n. 

Blake, William, 365 
Blondiot, R., 91 
Blumberg, A. E., 106 n. 

Bolzmann, L., 4 
Boole, G., 134 

Bradley, F, H., 32, 41, 42, 43, 46, a74 
Braiihwaite, R. B., 6 
Brentanc, F-, 4 
Bridgman, P. W., 120 n. 

Calvinism, 310, 311 
Cantor, G., 32, 359, 364 
Capitalism, 310, 311 


22, 24, 
no n.. 


147 n.. 165 n.. 199 n., 201, 202 n., 
203. 204, 205, 206, 207, 208, 209, 
210, 213 n., 231, 233 n., 235, 
236, 237, 238, 282, 290, 298, 324 
Causation, 242 
Chisholm, B.. M., 120 n, 

Church, A., 8, 116 
Chwisiek, L., 6. 135 
Ciccotti. E., 215 n. 

Cognition, 219. 222, 223, 227; or toe 
good, 250 

Coleridge, S. T., 367 
Coilingwood, R. G., 327, 328, 329 
Common-sense, 8, 101, 110 n., 356 
Comte, A., 4, 83 

Concepts, 13, 17, 24, 133, 145, 146, 
232. 233, 248, 288, 334-336, 338, 
341, 342, 376; and the given, 144; 
clarification of, 283; dispositional, 
186, 187, 197; kinematic, 186; 
limiting, 286; logical, powers of, 
333; of the good, 250, 251, 253, 
255 256, 261; of mathematics, 


Index 


[448 ] 

Concepts {continued} 

135; of the new logic, 141; of 
physics, 182, 184, 186; of science, 
143; physical, 167, 181-183, 186; 
psychoio^cal, 167, 185, 189, 190, 
197; socioiogicai, 311 
Conditional, coimterfactuai, 120; ma- 
terial, 119, 120 

Confirmability, 111 n., 114, 146 
Confirmation' 221-223, 225, 226 
Connective, logical, meaning of, 142 
ConsdoHsness, 258, 306; content of, 
98, 103, 177, 218; date of, 94, 98, 
99 

Constructs, empirical, 22, 121; hypo- 
thetical, 197; theoretical, 122 n. 
Contradiction, iaw^ of. 153, 155; truth, 
as absence of, 214 

Convention(s), 236, 237, 238. 240; 
and basic proposiiions, 235; lin- 
guistic, 238 
Copernicus, 167 
Cornelius, H., 107 n. 

Couturat, L., 32 

Darwin, 167 
Darwinism, 377 

Data, 110; observ'aiional, 112, 211; 

primitive, 237; see also Protocols 
Deduction, 115. 136. 156, 157, 305, 
330, 360, 373 

Definition(s), 322, 323, 365; actual, 
322, 323; as a system of philos- 
ophy, 322; implicit, 361; nominal, 
322; of a word, 323; ostensive, 
25; see also Analysis 
DeMorgan, A., 134, 139 
Descartes, 54. 74, 98, 99. 209, 362, 
377, 379, 380 

Description(s), common-sense. 15; 

physicalistic, 295; theory of, 36 
Determinism, 26, 353 
Dilthey, W., 79 

Disagreement, ethical, 279; in belief, 

277, 278, 279; in interest, 277, 

278, 279 
Driesch, H., 290 
Duhem, P., 4, 208 

Economy, principle of, 216, 217, 218, 
231 


Einstein, A., 4, 58, 59, 89, 139, 151, 
161, 174, 200, 360, 376, 379 
Eieatics, the, 83 

Emotive theory of ethics, 22 264 

fi.; see also Ethics 
Empathy, 296, 298, 299 
Empiricism, 8, 31, 106, 107, 108, 143, 
149, 150, 209; see also Experi- 
ence 

Enriques, F., 44 
Epicurus, 4 

Epimenides, paradox of, 41 
Esthetics, 58 

Ethics, 6, 17, 21, 22, 57, 261, 267, 
268, 277, 278, 281, 304, 305-309; 
and knowledge, 247, 248; and 
life, 258; and psychology, 280; 
and truth, 247; as factual science, 
258; as normative science, 256, 
259; as science, 247; as part of 
psychology', 65; concept of, 252; 
emotive theory of, 22, 23; facts 
of, 252; imperative theory of, 22; 
method of. 263: philosophical, 
253; questions of, 247, 248, 259, 
263, 264; task of, 250, 251, 256, 
261; theological, 252 
Euclid, 31. 330, 366 
Evil, 252. 254. 255, 258/ 259, 260, 
261 

Existence, 36, 73 fi., 96, 106, 332; 

of the external w^orld, 85 
Experience (s). 11. 18, 20, 21, 26, .86, 
108, 109, 144, 145, 148, 150, 

151, 161, 194, 213. 215, 219, 

223, 225, 229, 230, 234, 240, 

242, 248; and mathematical and 
logical propositions, 149, 152; 
and science, 221; atomic, 204; 
immediate, 204: moral, 240 
Explanation, 260; historical, 328 

Facts, 25, 115 n., 151, 159, 209, 210, 
214, 225, 226, 228, 229, 235, 

238’, 24 i’ 257,’ 258* 269,’ 285’, 

324, 329, 348, 355, 357; abso- 
lutely simple, 11; and the laws 
of excluded middle and contra- 
diction, 153; and simples, 42, 43; 
and statements, 155; atomic, 11; 
empirical, 212, 278; knowledge 



Index 

Facts (continued) 

of, 152; natural, 22; norms, ^ as 
expression of, 255; of ethics, 
252; of perception, 218; pri- 
maiy, 212; relation between prop- 
ositioE and, 242; see also Judg- 
ments, Propositions, Sentences, 
Statements 

Faisifiabiiity 113, 114, 127, 128 
Falsification, 229 
Fatalism, 355, 368 

Feigl, H., 3, 7, 8, 106 n., 120 n., 122 
123 n., 128 n., 146, 197, 198 
Fermat, P., 72 
Feuerbach, L., 4 
Fichte, 80 
Field, G. C., 267 
Flew, A., 239 n. 

Form, logical, and knowledge, 55 
Formal mode of speech, 25, 165, 237 
Frank, P., 3, 6, 7, 107 n., 128 n., 287 
Frege, G.. 4, 10, 32, 3 j, ^5, 54, i24 n», 
134, 135, 140, 208, 282, 356, 358, 
359, 361, 363, 378 
Freud, S., 168 

Galileo, 376 

Geometry, axioms of, 360; non-Eu- 
ciidean, 32; see also Logic, 
Mathematics 

Gestalt psychology, 169, 237, 238 
God, 16, 66, 94, 239, 240, 252, 253, 
300 

Godel, K., 2, 7, 8, 359 
Goethe, 367 

Good, 248-256, 258-260, 264-271, 
274, 275, 280, 281; as indefin- 
able, 251; cognition of, 250; con- 
cept of the, 250-256, 262; con- 
tent of, 253; definition of, 249; 
formal characteristics of the, 
252; material characteristics of, 
253; scientific knowledge of, 261; 
see also Ethics 

Goodman, N., 7, 8, 26, 27, 117, 120 n. 
Graphology, 185, 186, 188, 189, 190 


[ 449 ] 

Hegel, 32, 73, 75, 80, 134, 143 
Heidegger, M., 16, 69 n., 71, 75, 80, 
200 

Heisenberg, W., 376 
Heimholz, H., 4 

Hempel, C. G., 5, 7, 8, 120 n., 128 n., 
229, 230 m, 231, 234, 237 
Heraclitus, 374 

Hilbert, D., 4, 135, 360, 361, 379 
Hobbes, 265, 266, 267, 277 
Hume, 4, 10, 11, 22, 31, 265, 266, 

267, 367, 376 
Hypostatization, 264 

Hypothesis, 14, 15, 18, 20, 21, 220, 
222, 223, 226, 227, 329, 331; 
and scientific theory, 214 

Idea(s), 332-336, 338-340, 343, 344; 
abstract, 340, 341, 343; arith- 
metical, 337; concrete, 340, 343; 
general, 347; logical power of, 
332-335, 337, 340, 344; Platonic, 

268, 280 

Idealism, 9, 15, 41, 85 
Imperative(s), 22, 278, 279; cate- 
gorical. 268; see also Ethics 
Induction, 169, 220, 298, 299, 329, 
345 

infinity, 359 

introspection, 191, 192, 194, 262, 
380; see also Behaviorism, Con- 
sciousness 

Intuition, 188, 239; and knowledge, 
102; logical, 359; moral, 21 
Intuitionism, ethical, 23 

James, W., 37, 228 
Jevons, W. S., 292 
Joergensen, J., 5, 7 
Judgment(s), 210, 211, 213, 261, 304; 
analytic, 224; moral, 22, 23, 254, 
255, 258, 261, 262, 267, 268, 
269, 270, 277, 278, 279, 280, 
304, 305; of observation, 222 
von Juhos, B., 242 
Jurisnnidence, 205. 207, 309 


[ 450 ] 

Kant {continued) 

253, 256, 259, 346, 34S, 360, 376, 
3S0 

Kaplan, A., 122 n. 

Keisen, H., 307 n., 308 n. 

Kepler, 360 

Knowledge, 10, 56, 144, 148, 151, 
171, 210, 212, 220, 221, 227, 
334, 340, 343; a priori, 152; and 
ethics, 247, 248; and positivism, 
90; and re^ty, 226; as intuition, 
102; as sensation, 102; basis of, 
20, 213, 216, 222, 223, 226; cer- 
tainty of human, 209; empirical, 
278, 279; intersubjective, 211; 
limitation of human, 72, 73; 
metaphysical, 72; non-analytic, 
108; of facts, 152; of other 
minds, 177; of physiolog\% 175; 
origin of, 221; scientific, 17, 125, 
284; scientific, of the good, 261; 
systems of, 219, 222; theor>'' of, 
133, 136, 209, 292, 293; thi^- 
ing and, 149; see also Empiri- 
cism, Rationalism 
Kotarbinskv, T., 6, 7 
Kraft, V., 3, 7 
Kraus, O., 310, 311 
fCronecker, L., 25 

Laas, E., 85 
Langford, C. H., 120 n. 

Language, 19, 21, 23, 24, 26, 27, 55, 
“■llO n., 116, 117, 152, 157, 167, 
177, 179, 205, 214, 219, 237, 238, 
241, 271, 285, 289, 295, 323, 340, 
342’ 343, 350, 354, 358, 362-364, 
366, 372. 374; and contemporary 
British philosophy, 5; and type 
confusion, 75; constituents, 61; 
current uses of, 7; empiricist, 
116-118, 120-123, 128 n.; games, 
27; ideal, 199; influence on phi- 
losophy, 38; intersubjective, 205, 
206; logical, construction of, 45; 
logical syntax of, 6; of everyday 
life, 287; of physics, 287; of sci- 
ence, 28, 199, 200, 202, 203; 
ordinary use of, 9; phenomenalis- 
tic, 201; protocol, 165, 182, 188, 
201, 202, 205-207; structure of, 


Index 

24; subject-predicate, 39; system, 
24, 166, 235; see also Meaning 
Lazerowitz, M-, 8 

Leibniz, 4, 32, 44, 54, 134, 135, 137, 
139, 380 

Lesnievsky, S., 6, 135 
Leverrier, U. J. J., 151, 160 
Lewin, K., 284 
Lewis, C. L, 120 n. 

Lichtenberg, G. C., 350 
Xx)ckc 19 

Logic,’ 8, 22, 74, 96, 114, 117, 134, 

150, 152, 236, 282, 284-286, 317, 
322, 324, 358, 372, 376; and 
mathematics, 134, 307; and meta- 
physics, 60, 143: and numbers, 
135; and symbolic method, 136; 
applied, 134; as method of 
philosophizing, 153 f., laws of, 

151, 153; mathematics as branch 

of, 140, 143; natural, 366: of re- 
lations, 137; of science. 24; phi- 
iosopm' and, 24, 134, 364. 376; 
propositions of, 158; lautoiogical 
character of, 141, 142, 143; 

three-valued, 353; traditional, 
133, 134; see also Empiricism, 
Rationalism 

Lukasiewicz, I., 6. 135, 353' 

Mach, E., 4, 9, 85, 86, 139, 174, 20S, 
282 

Malcolm, N., 8 
Malebranche, 380 
Maithus, 312 
Mannoury, G., 6 
Marc-Wogau, K.. " 

Marx, 4, 167, 312 
Marxism, 7, 9, 306. 308, 309, 315 
Material mode of sneech. 25. 165 fi.. 
257 g- 

Materialism, 324, 345 
Mathematics, 135, 150, 158, 159, 282, 
284, 285, 286, 322, 370. 377; and 
logic, 134, 307; and reality, 360: 
as branch of logic. 140, 143: 
foundations of, 32, 135; laws of, 
151; propositions of, 158; sen- 
tences of, as analytic, 143; sen- 
tences of, as tautologies, 142; un- 
decidabie questions in, 359; see 


Index 

Mathematics {continued} 

aha Empiricisin, Logic, Ration- 
alism 

Matter, 36; as logical construction, 
37; history of, 49 
McTaggart, J. E. M-, 16 
Maxwell,, G-, 12S n. 

Maxwell, J. C, 33, 151 
Meaning, 15, 19, 122, 225, 226, 228, 
231, 272, 293, 321, 323-325; and 
name, 249; and pseudo problems, 
56; cognitive, 116, 117, 123; com- 
municability of, 95; criterion of, 
14, 108, 115 n., 116 ff.; emotive, 
10, 273-277, 280, 291; empirical, 
110, 111, 113, 122; of ethical 
terms, 271; of a logical connec- 
tive, 142; of a philosophic ques- 
tion, 86; of a proposition, 87, 
90 ff., 106; of a word, 62 tt.; os- 
tensive, 57; verifiable, 95; see 
also Language, Metaphysics 
Menger, C., 4 
Menger, K., 3 

Metaphysics, 8, 9, 10, 11, 14, 17, 72, 
83, 159, 166, 283-286, 291, 292, 
299, 301, 304, 305, 309, 316, 317; 
and logic, 60, 143; and physics, 
174; and psychology, 174; and 
science, 174; as attitude towards 
life, 78 E.; as substitute for art, 
80; Berkeleyan, 85; elimination 
of, 145, 300; error of, 57; his- 
torical role of, 78; idealistic, 85, 
86, 290; meaning of words, 65; 
solipsistic, 85 

Method, axiomatic, 360, 361, 379; em- 
pirical, 267, 268, 277, 278, 279, 
280; mtuitive, 170, 171, 182, 191: 
of ethics, 263; of philosophical 
reasoning, 343; of philosophy, 
23; rational, 170, 188; scientific, 
8, 200, 267, 268, 283, 305, 308, 
317, 327; see also Empiricism, 
Rationalism, Science 
Min, L S, 4, 31, 32, 97, 143, 257, 258 
Mind(s), 15, 16, 170, 174, 191, 213, 
234, 239, 332, 345, 347, 348; and 
space-time, 49; knowledge of 
other, 177; puzzle of other, re- 


i J 

solved, 206; see abo Behavior, 
Consciousness, Introspection 
von Mises, R., 5 
Monism, 40, 45 

Moore, G. E., 3, 5, 8, 28, 32, 243, 
250, 266 n-, 268, 280, 321, 345, 
368, 375 

Morris, C, W., 6 
Mulier-Lyer figure, 4 
Mysticism, 5 

Nagel, E., 6, 7 

Nature, 151, 307, 328, 380; laws of 
160-161 

Neo-Hegelianism, 9 
Neo-Kantianism, 9 
INfess Ak. 5 7 

Neurath" o!, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 20, 206, 207, 
211, 214, 229, 230, 231, 237, 286, 
300, 314 n., 317 n. 

Newton, 135, 139, 160, 161, 348, 360, 
380 

Nietzsche, 80, 168, 350, 374 
Norm(s), 255, 256, 257, 259, 261; as 
expression of fact, 255; ethical, 
and life, 258; moral, 255, 262; 
system of, 261; theory of, 260; ul- 
timate, 258; see also Ethics 
Nothing, the (‘"das Nichtes”)* 16, 
69 fi. 

du Noiiy, Lecomte, 109 
Number(s), and logic, 135; natural, 
359; see also Mathematics 

Objectivity, 247 

Observation (s), 14, 18, 20, 21, 109, 
115 n., 147-153, 155. 160, 161, 
215, 216, 220, 228, 230, 231, 233, 
236; and theory in physics, 160; 
data of, 211; facts of immediate, 
215; judgments of, 222, language, 
197; predicates, 117-119, 121, 
122; sentences, 63, 76, 110, 111, 
113-116, 122, 123, 146; state- 
ments, 200, 219, 221, 222, 223, 
225, 226, 283, 285, 287, 289, 290, 
300; see also Data, Facts 
Occam’s razor, 34 
Ogden, C, K., 73 
Ontology, 26 
Oppenheim, P., 120 n. 



[452 ] 

Oppenheimer, F., 284 n. 

Pap, A., ilO B-. il4 n., 124 n. 
Paradoxfes), 333, 334, 340, 349, 351; 
logical, 330, 333, 336; of Achilles 
and the tortoise, 351, 352 
Fhscal, 366 
Pasch, M., 4 
Paul, G. A., 239 n. 

Pavlov, I., 298 

Peano, G-, 4, 10, 32, 134, 135 
Pears, D., 9 

Perception, 17, 110 n., 117, 144, 205, 
226, 252, 287, 289; centers, 292; 
and experimental propositions, 
99; external, 296; internal, 296; 
organic, 290, 297, 298; sensory. 

Perry, " r. B., 265 
Petzail, A., 5, 7, 106 n. 
Phenomenology, 1 68 
Philosophy. 17, 23, 24, 26, 177, 204, 
208, 282, 283, 293, 294, 325, 336, 
364, 365, 374-376, 379, 380; ana- 
lytical, 3: and empirical sciences, 
133: and logic, 24, 134, 364, 376; 
and posmlaies, 330; as a system 
of dennitions, 321, 322; contrast- 
ed with science, 56-57, 34 d: mean- 
ing of, 57; method of, 346. 367: 
nature of, 346, 367; not a science, 
56 g.; scientific, 77; task of, 356 
Physicaiism, 21, 27, 166, 167, 175, 182, 
185. 194, 197, 198, 200, 202, 208, 
282’ 286-292, 296, 297, 299, 305, 
309, 317; language of, 287, 290; 
statements of, 290; unified lan- 
guage of, 286, 308, 317; see also 
Behaviorism 

Physicalization, 182, 184, 186-189: in 
graphology, 185; of psychological 
concepts, 190 

Physics, 147, 148, 169, 172, 197; and 
metaphysics, 174; and science, 
166; concepts of, 182, 186, 197; 
psychology as part of, 168, 197; 
theory^ and observ’ation in, 160 
Picasso, P., 379 
Fieri, M., 4 
Planck, M., 90 

Plato, 83, 134, 342, 346, 347, 367, 369, 
375 


Index 

Pluralism, 32, 40, 45 
Poincare, H., 4, 159, 174, 208, 282 
Popper, K., 6, 7, 13, 14, 113 n., 120 n., 
213 n., 229 n,, 235, 236 
Popper-Lynkaeus, 4 
Positivism, 5, 8, 9, 83, 106; and the 
externa! world, 85; and knowl- 
edge, 90; and reality, 97; logical, 
3-28 passim, 106, 359; methodo- 
logical, 144, 206, 207; see also 
Empiricism, Vienna Circie 
Postulates, and philosophy, 330 
Pragmatism, 27, 37 
Price, H. H-, 232, 242 
Probability, 232, 233 
Propositions, 15, 19, 23, 24, 27, 87 £, 
107, 159, 229-232, 236, 238. 241, 
285, 317, 330-333, 336-33S, 34G- 
343; and words, 317; basic, 229, 
230, 235, 236, 237, 23S. 243; 
concrete, 235; criterion of iniih 
and faisitv of, S7; emnirical. SI',, 
90 fi., 106, 228, 233,* 234, 236. 
239, 243; existential, and percep- 
tions, 99; existential, logical form 
of, 98; factual, 10, 237': hrst-or- 
der, 242; formal 10: logical pow- 
ers of, 331, 332, 333, 337; of sci- 
ence, 19, 23; philosophical. 25, 24. 
329; protocol, 230, -231, 233. 234, 
235, 236, 237; pseudo-factual. 
237, 238; pseudo-syniacticaL 238: 
relation between fact and. 242; 
significant, 10; singular, 228; 229, 
236; syntactical 237, 238; system 
of empirical 231; universal 228. 
229; see also Facts. jTiagmenis.. 
Sentences, Statements 
Protocols), 202, 203, 205, 206. 20“ . 
221, 226, 231. 236; of science. 
226; see also Statements, Sen- 
tences 

Proust, M., 350, 367 
Pseudo-Statements, 61, 64, 67-68; and 
logical mistakes, 73; metaphysi- 
cal, 69 

Psychoanalysis, 306 
Psychology^ 58, 165 ff.. 172, 263, 267, 
296, 300, 306, 323, 325; and 
ethics, 280; and metaphysics, 174; 
as part of physics, 168, 197; con- 
cepts of, 189, 198; ethics, as pan 



Fs?cbology {continued) 

■ of 263; Gestalt, 169; introspec- 
ti¥e, 191; intuitive, ISl, 182, 184; 

occurrent properties^ of, 186; of 
sensution, 238; scientific, 198; sen- 
tences of, 183; also Beliavior- 
ism, Physicalism 

- Quality, experience of, 93;^ primary, 
19; primary and secondary, 297; 
statements about, 297 
Quine, W. V., 6, 7, 8, 26, 27, 28 

Ramsey, F. P., 6, 19, 21, 23, 28, 135, 
241 

Rationalism, 150, 159 ff., 310; see 
also Knowledge 

Realism, 15, 21, 41, 107: and the ex- 
ternal world, 85; metaphysical, 
105 

Reality, 23, 96, 105, 148, 151, 211, 
214, 225, 228, 230, 240, 241, 
263, 292, 295; absolute, 104; 
agreement with, 215, 229, 234; 
and mathematics, 360; and sen- 
sations, 98; and thinking, 159; 
knowledge of, 225, 226; of the 
external world, 85, 86, 91, 95 ff., 
100; positivism and the question 
of, 84 ff.. 97; transcendenh 101, 
102, 105 

Reductio ad absurdum, 330, 335, 336, 
337, 338, 343, 369, 370 ft., 374 
Reichenbach, H., 5, 6, 120 n., 122 n. 
Reininger, R., 286 

Reiation(s), and monism, 40; and 
pluralism, 40; and subject-predi- 
cate logic, 39; internal and ex- 
ternal, 42 ff.; reality of, 32, 46; 
theory' of, 137; transitive and 
symmetrical, 34 
Richards, L A., 273 
Rickert, H., 303 
Riemann, B., 4 
Rilke, R. M., 380 

RusseE, B., 3, 4, 8, 10, 11, 12, 17, 24, 
26, 27, 54, 98, 108 n., 110 n., 
Ill n., 113 n., 124 n., 135, 138, 
139, 140, 208, 321 n. 

Ryle, G., 6, 8, 9, 27, 367, 373 
Rynin, D., 128 n. 


Scepticism, 31 

Scheffler, L, 128 m, 129 n., 378 
Schelling, 80, 134 
Schiipp, P. A., 198 
Schlick, M*, 3, 5, 6, 20, 21, 22, 24, 
Him, 133 m, 221 m, 286 
Scholasticism 325 
Schoiz, H., 6, 7 

Schopenhauer, 263, 347, 348, 349 
Schroder, E., 4, 135, 208 
Science(s), 17, 21, 25, 185, 208-212, 
^20, 222, 223, 226, 227, 234, 

247, 249, 263, 285-287, 291, 293, 
296, 298, 301, 303, 305, 317, 

332, 358, 364, 365, 376, 377, 

380; and experience, 221; and 

physics, 166; as data of philoso- 
phy, 46; concepts of, 143, 187; 
concepts of, unified, 287; con- 
trasted with philosophy, 56, 57, 
345: dennition of, 56; ethics, as 
factual, 258; language of, 24; 
logic of, 24; logical starting point 
of, 211; moral, 294, 295, 296, 
298, 308; normative, 256, 258, 
260; social, 21; statements of, 
19, 20, 23, 212, 213, 226; system 
of, 210, 219; unified, 143, 166, 
200. 201, 204, 207, 208, 282-287, 
281, 293, 294, 296, 297, 305-308, 
316, 317; unity of, 146 
Scriven, M., 128 n., 146,- 197 
Segerstedt, T. T., 7 
Sellars, W., 221 n. 

Semantics, 6, 20, 177; see also Lan- 
guage, Meaning 

Sensation(s), 17, 107, 110 m, 117, 
238, 241, 259, 323; and knowl- 
edge, 102; and reality, 98; Gestalt 
theory 238; psychology of, 
238 

Sense-data, 13, 17, 18, 229, 236, 242 
Sense-impressions, 90, 346 
Sense-perception (s), 148, 179, 290 
Sentences, 24, 25, 109, 115 m, 117, 
122, 124, 127, 128 n., 129, 137, 
142, 166, 167, 171-74, 176, 179, 
180, 192, 203, 204-208, 211, 224, 
230, 231, 234, 241, 336, 337; 
about other minds, 170, 174, 175, 
176, 192, 197; about one’s own 
mind, 170, 192, 194, 195; ana- 


Index 



[454] 

Sentences (continued) 

ivtic. 111, 115; atomic, 199, dy- 
jiamic use of, 271; of 
matics, as 

tion, 174; physical, 175, 182, 194, 
195; observation, 63, /o, 

in 113-116, 122, 123, 166, 171, 
175, 185, 191, 194, 195, 199, 
-100 202-205, 207; psychological, 
182’, 183, 190, 193, 197; reduc- 
tion, 120, 121, 128; tautological, 
142- 143; see also Facts, Proposi- 
tions, Protocols, Statements 
Significance, see Meaning 

Simples, denned, 44 ^ 

Simultaneity, ^89 It., 94, :>19 

S’girt'W 300 301, 3W. 

307-309, 312, 316, 317; empmcal, 
306, 308, 309, 315, 316, 317; 
physicaiistic, 301 

Socrates, 342, 343 , . i i 

Solipsism, 13, 18; methoaologicai, 

206, 207, 290, 293; theory or 
multiple, 19 
Somban, W., 296 
Suace, 48, 49. 58. 151, 166, 3^9 
Space-Time, 48, 49, 286; points, 19/, 
235 

IpinoS: S: .-4, 346, 366, 376, 380 
Stace, W. T., 108 n., 115 n._^ 
Statement(s), 11, 13, 

20 21, 27, 116, 12/, i28, 13/, 
213, 214, 224, 234, 238, 286, 291- 
293, 299, 316, 332, 365; about 
qualities, 297; about reality, 91- 
292; agreement of, 216; analytic, 
27, "223-225: and concepts, 133; 
and facts, 155; and their ori^n, 
218; and value-judgments, 77; 
basic, 216, 217; common-sense, 
16; corrigibiiity of, 216; descrip- 
tive, 22; elementary and com- 
plex, 11; empirical, 18, 20, 21, 
23, 122; ethical, 22, 278, 281; 
formal, 23; impossibility of mean- 
ingful metaphysical, 76; intro- 
spective, 195, 196; kinds of mean- 
ingful, 76; mathematical, as tau- 
tnloeies. 158: meaningless, 284, 


286, 317; metaphysical, 16; nor- 
mative, 22; observation, 219-223, 
225, 226, 283, 285, 287, 289, 290, 
300, 307, 310; of physicaHsm, 
290; of physics, 147; of science, 

20, " 212 , 226; of unified science, 
'>95; philosophical, 25, 26; physi- 
20, 180, 290; physicaiistic, 
293 296-298; protocol, 20, 209- 
213, 216, 2X7, 219-221, 234, 237, 
238, 290, 309; protocol, logical 
and temporal priority of, 211; 
psychological, 198; relational, 
138; scientific, 16; semantic, 25; 
significant, 12, 125; singular, 210; 
synthetic, 27, 227; two kinds of, 
154, 155; universal, 210, 222; 

also Facts, Judgments, Propo- 
sitions, Protocols, Sentences 
Stebbing, L. S., 6 
Stevenson, C. L., 8, 22 
Strabo, 313 
Strawson, P. F., 9, 23 
Syntax, 26, 284, 292; logical, 24, 208; 
unified, 284 

System(s), 129, 231, 232, 234, 28., 
292, 317, 378, 384; Aristoteiian- 
Scholastic of logic, 134; > axiom- 
adzed uninterpreted, 121; ethical, 
248, 256; formal, 359; Hegel’s, 
143; h^TOtheiico-deductive. 121; 
Konsdtution, 24; of definitions, 
philosophy as, 32, 322; of empiri- 
cal proposidons, 231; of knovvi- 
edce, 219; of norms, 261; or 
proposidons, 157; 01 science, 210, 
'^12y 219, 233; philosophical, 

346; physbal, 180, 291; physicai- 
istic, 292; positivist and matenal- 
isdc constitution, 144; specula- 
tive, 376; symbolic, 199, theo- 
retical, 122; also^ Logic, 

Mathematics, Metaphysics, Sci- 
ence 

System-ianeuage, physicaiistic, 235, 
237 

Tabula rasa, 201 
Tarski, A., 6, 7, 8, 20, 124 
Tautology hes), 12, 76, 143, K5, Dc, 
156, 159, 200, 202, 223, 228, 


[ 455 ] 



ituie* 

TantDlogydes) 322- 

7%9 2U, 292, 297, 3m, 
defiiution of, 142; mathematical 
^temeats as. 158; propositions 
of logic as, 157; see also Logic, 
Mathematics 

?Sl“Sl,‘203,'?08, 307. 324, 32S. 
■^^^2 333 351; demonstrative, 

225; disposition, 1 18, 1 19, 120; 
empirical, 118, 121 ; ethical, 22, 
270 271, 281; significant, 128 
Theology, 295, 297, 304, 316; see also 
God, Metaphysics 

Testability. 110; criterion, 114 115, 

116, iiS* i24; see also Falsm- 
abiiity, Veriliabiiity 
Theory, 146, 214, 327, 335; and hy- 
pothesis, 214; and observation in 
physics, 160; scientific, 214; 
sense-datum, 357; see also Sci- 
ence ^ , 

Thought, 156, 211, 323, 374; delusions 
of, 149, 150 

rune, 16, 48, 49, 58, 89, 151, 166, 
211, 289, 325, 347-351,361, 362, 
369; see also Space-Time 
Transformation, tautological. 158, 159 
Translatability, 116, 122, 128 n., 167, 
190; criterion, 117, 118, 121, 128 
Truth, 213, 218, 225, 230, 231, 232, 
238, 241, 263, 280, 327, 340, 353, 
354, 355, 376, 377; as absence of 
contradiction, 214; as mutual 
agreement of statements, 214; 
coherence theory of, 20, 214, 
215, 216, 231, 232, 233, 242; cor- 
respondence theor>- of, 21, 214; 
criterion of, 213, 215-216; ethics 
and, 247; formal, 22, 215, 223- 
224; nature of, 214; nature of 
arithmetical, 358; necessary, 352; 
of empirical proposition, 234; of 
statements, 24; philosophic, 283; 
semanticai definition of, 124 n, 
Type(s), logical, 40 ff., 333 fi., 336, 
337, 339; logical and meaning 
of words, 41 fi.; theory of, 136, 
140, 359; violation of rules of 
theory of, 75; see also Paradox 


Universais, 38, 39 

Vagueness, 264 
Vaihinger, H., 85 
Vailati, G-, 4 

Validity, 142, 152, 210, 223, 224, 226, 
229, 231 

Vaine(s), 240, 257, 258, 260, 307, 
323; post-Kantian philosophy of, 
263; world of, 14, 22; also 
Ethics 

Verifiability, 111 n., 114, 127, 128, 
146; criterion of. 111 n., 113, 
127; in principle, 88, 111; see 
also Verification 

Verification, 13 S., 21, 56, 94, 106, 
201, 204, 212, 221, 222, 223, 
225, 235, 236, 242, 291; method 
of, 13, 87 g. 

Vienna Circle, 3-9, 15, 21, 22, 24, 110, 
207, 208, 282, 283, 286, 291 

Waismann, F., 3, 5, 6, 7, 28 
Watson, J. B., 298 
Weber, M., 310, 311 
W’edberg, A., 7 
Weierstrass, K* T. W., 32 
Werkmeister, W. H., 112 n. 
Whitehead. A. N., 4, 12, 33, 34, 36, 
135, 140 

W’isdom, 342, 343 
Wisdom, J., 6, 8, 9, 243 
Wittgenstein, L., 3, 4, 5, 7, 8, 11, 12, 
13, 15, 17, 23, 24, 25, 27, 28, 
54, 76, 135, 146, 208, 214, 282, 
284, 285, 321, 325, 326, 356, 373, 
374, 375, 380 

Word(s), and propositions, 317; defi- 
nition of, 323; dynamic use of, 
272, 273; meaning of, 62 ff-, 
meaningless, 145; meaningless se- 
quences of and natural language, 
67; see also Propositions, Sen- 
tences 

von Wright, G. H., 7 

Zeno, 351, 368 
Ziisei, E,, 3, 241 n. 






I2.3fi7